University of Arkansas, Fayetteville University of Arkansas, Fayetteville
ScholarWorks@UARK ScholarWorks@UARK
Graduate Theses and Dissertations
8-2016
Biocentrism in Environmental Ethics: Questions of Inherent Worth, Biocentrism in Environmental Ethics: Questions of Inherent Worth,
Etiology, and Teleofunctional Interests Etiology, and Teleofunctional Interests
David Lewis Rice III
University of Arkansas, Fayetteville
Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.uark.edu/etd
Part of the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons
Citation Citation
Rice, D. L. (2016). Biocentrism in Environmental Ethics: Questions of Inherent Worth, Etiology, and
Teleofunctional Interests.
Graduate Theses and Dissertations
Retrieved from
https://scholarworks.uark.edu/etd/1650
This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks@UARK. It has been accepted for
inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UARK. For more
information, please contact [email protected].
Biocentrism in Environmental Ethics: Questions of Inherent Worth, Etiology, and
Teleofunctional Interests
A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment
of the requirements for the degree of
Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy
by
David Rice
Delta State University
Bachelor of Science in Biology, 1994
Delta State University
Master of Science in Natural Sciences in Biology, 1999
University of Mississippi
Master of Arts in Philosophy, 2009
August 2016
University of Arkansas
This dissertation is approved for recommendation to the Graduate Council.
____________________________________
Dr. Richard Lee
Dissertation Director
____________________________________
Dr. Warren Herold
Committee Member
____________________________________
Dr. Tom Senor
Committee Member
Abstract
Some biocentrists argue that all living things have "inherent worth". Anything that has
inherent worth has interests that provide a reason for why all moral agents should care about it in
and of itself. There are, however, some difficulties for biocentric individualist arguments which
claim that all living things have inherent worth.
Some biocentrists maintain that all living things have inherent worth and that artificial
living things do not because the former, but not the latter, have interests by recourse to their
natural selection etiology. Some also argue that synthetic forms of life do not have moral
standing because they are "artificial" instead of "natural". However, there are good reasons to
think that naturally-selected functions do not adequately define biocentric interests or that what
is "natural" is not always of interest to the individual organism.
A systems-based account of interests, on the other hand, attempts to solve the problem of
harmful, selected functions by construing what is in a thing’s interests by recourse to whether it
has highly integrated functions aimed at its self-maintenance. Cases of harmful selected
functions are handled adequately, but unfortunately this account allows for the existence of non-
sentient “instant organisms”, that have teleofunctional interests but that do not have
teleofunctional interests that provide them direct moral standing. It also allows possible, future,
designed entities to count as interest possessors.
A systems-based account cannot provide guidance on what makes the teleofunctional
interests of non-sentient beings morally considerable to the extent that they have direct moral
standing. While rational agents and sentient beings have interests that provide them with direct
moral standing regardless of their etiology, it does not appear that non-sentient living things also
have interests that provide them with direct moral standing. Indirect moral standing is the only
kind of moral standing that non-sentient living things can have.
I argue that the non-design etiology of natural selection is incapable of guaranteeing
indirect moral standing for non-sentient living things. If, on the other hand, all non-sentient
living things were designed, then they would be guaranteed to have indirect moral standing.
©2016 by David Rice
All Rights Reserved
Acknowledgements
I owe many thanks to my dissertation director, Dr. Richard Lee, who made helpful
suggestions on the drafting of this dissertation. This dissertation would be substantially lacking
without his contribution. Thanks also to my committee members Dr. Warren Herold and Dr.
Tom Senor for their insights on the questions posed here.
Dedication
This dissertation is dedicated with the deepest of love to my mother, Shirley Gaston Rice.
You are missed very much.
Table of Contents
Chapter One: An Introduction to Biocentrism and Inherent Worth ................................................1
I. "What is considered valuable?" ..............................................................................................2
II. "What kind of value do these things have?" .........................................................................6
III. A Discussion of Intrinsic Value ...........................................................................................9
IV. The Varieties of Intrinsic Value ........................................................................................13
V. Intrinsic Subjective Value ...................................................................................................15
VI. Intrinsic Objective Value ...................................................................................................17
VII. Inherent Worth .................................................................................................................18
VIII. Clarifying the Definition of Inherent Worth ...................................................................26
IX. "From where does such value come?" ...............................................................................34
X. The Aim of this Dissertation ...............................................................................................35
Chapter Two: A Natural Selection Etiological Account of Biological Interests ...........................40
I. Background Information Relevant to Biocentric Individualism ..........................................41
II. Gary Varner’s Natural Selection Etiological Account of Interests .....................................46
III. The Importance of Etiology to Varner’s View ..................................................................50
IV. A Survey of Etiological Accounts of Living Organisms ...................................................58
V. Non-etiological Account of Interests ..................................................................................65
VI. Craig Delancey’s Criticism of Varner’s Etiological Account of Biological Functions ....66
VII. Conclusion ........................................................................................................................75
Chapter Three: The Systems-based Account and a Definition of Interests ...................................77
I. Delancey's Systems-Based Account of Interests ..................................................................79
II. Further Clarification on the Definition of Interests .............................................................85
III. Artifact Inclusion ...............................................................................................................97
IV. Replacing the term "Biological Functions" and "Biological Interests" with
"Teleofunctions" and "Teleofunctional Interests" ...........................................................102
V. Criticisms of a Systems-based View and Some Responses ..............................................104
VI. Criticisms of, and Responses to, "Artifact Interests".......................................................124
VII. The Status of Synthetic Life Research ...........................................................................141
VIII. Conclusion ....................................................................................................................145
Chapter Four: The Moral Considerability of Interests .................................................................147
I. Granting Morally Considerable Interests to Conscious Agents and Sentient Beings ........152
II. A Sufficient Condition for Having a Morally Considerable, Teleofunctional Interest .....155
III.A Necessary Condition for Having a Goal of One's Own ................................................166
IV. Can a Systems-based Account be used to Reliably Establish the Existence of Morally
Considerable Teleofunctional Interests for Non-Sentient Beings? ..................................178
V. Can "Instant, Non-Sentient Beings" have Morally Considerable Teleofunctional
Interests? ..........................................................................................................................183
VI. Can Non-Sentient Beings produced by an Agent-Selection, Non-Design Etiology have
Morally Considerable Teleofunctional Interests? ............................................................183
VII. Naturally Selected, Proper Functions and Goals of One's Own .....................................188
VIII. Natural Selection and Aristotelianism ..........................................................................198
IX. Can Genes have Goals of Their Own? ............................................................................228
X. Is This the End for a Biocentrism Based on Natural Selection? .......................................233
XI. Why All Non-sentient Living Things Do Not Have a Good of Their Own ....................234
XII. Some Clarification on Morally Considerable Interests and Moral Standing .................238
XIII. Can All Naturally-Selected Non-Sentient Living Things be guaranteed to Have Indirect
Moral Standing? ...............................................................................................................246
XIV. Conclusion ....................................................................................................................254
Chapter Five: A Design Etiology and Indirect Morally Considerable, Teleofunctional
Interests ..................................................................................................................................259
I.What Does it Mean to Have a Design Etiology? .................................................................263
II. Can all Designed, Non-Sentient, Living Things be guaranteed to have Indirect Moral
Standing?; (i) The Argument from Creativity .................................................................273
III. Can all Designed, Non-Sentient, Living Things be guaranteed to have Indirect Moral
Standing?; (ii) The Argument from Teleofunctional Purposes ........................................280
IV. Introduction to a Theistic, Design Etiology and Further Reasons Available for the
Indirect Moral Standing of Designed, Non-sentient Beings ............................................283
V. Theism and Its Place in Environmental Ethics .................................................................286
VI. Information and the Design of Non-Sentient, Teleofunctional Beings ...........................289
VII. Is Natural Selection Creative or Brilliant? .....................................................................302
VIII. The Argument from Awe, Wonder and Thankfulness to God. .....................................306
IX. The Argument from Projects ...........................................................................................316
X. Conclusion .......................................................................................................................322
References Cited ..........................................................................................................................326
Vitae .............................................................................................................................................340
List of Figures
Figure 1: Four categories of etiologies for living things................................................................59
Figure 2. Structure of the DNA double-helix and its nucleotide base pairs. ...............................291
Figure 3. Metabolic diagram for tryptophan metabolism in yeast. ..............................................296
1
CHAPTER ONE
An Introduction to Biocentrism and Inherent Worth
In the introduction to the Blackwell Anthology on Environmental Ethics, Claire Palmer
writes,
“A wide spectrum of ethical positions is covered by the umbrella term
‘environmental ethics.’ These positions draw on a variety of ethical traditions,
from Plato and Aristotle to Mill and Moore. As one might expect, a vigorous
debate is being conducted between those advocating such diverse approaches.
Certain key questions lie at its heart. One central area of debate concerns value
theory in environmental ethics. What is considered valuable, and from where does
such value
1
come?” (Palmer, 2000, p.16).
But, of course, this is not the only issue for environmental ethics. The key question
highlighted by Palmer involves asking other, more fundamental, questions of metaethics such as,
"What is the nature of the value that nonhumans have?”. “Is the value in question objective or
subjective?”. “Is it intrinsic or extrinsic?”. “Instrumental or non-instrumental?". These questions
are primarily focused on the nature of the value of nonhumans and the environment and can be
summed up by the basic question, "What kind of value do these things have?"
Thus, we could perhaps rephrase Palmer’s key question in environmental ethics as three
separate questions: "What entities are considered valuable? What kind of value do these things
have? And, from where does such value come?"
1
There is, of course, the question of what exactly the term “value” itself means. I will assume
that value is the same thing as what G.E. Moore calls “goodness” or “good”, terms which he
believes are undefinable notions that are “simple”. Moore writes,
“What, then, is good? How is good to be defined?...What I want to discover is the nature of that
object or idea, and about this I am extremely anxious to arrive at an agreement… But if we
understand the question in this sense, my answer to it may seem a very disappointing one. If I am
asked, ‘What is good?’ my answer is that good is good, and that is the end of the matter. Or if I
am asked ‘How is good to be defined?’ my answer is that it cannot be defined and that is all I
have to say about it…My point is that ‘good’ is a simple notion, just as ‘yellow’ is a simple
notion; that just as you cannot, by any manner of means, explain to anyone who does not already
know it, what yellow is, so you cannot explain what good is.” (Moore, 1948, pp. 6-7).
2
The first question is a question of scope. Answers to it will determine the range or the
type of things that are deemed morally considerable or that have moral standing. The second
question is a question of metaethics. Answers to it will determine the type of value that the things
identified in the first question have. And the third question is a question of environmental ethical
theory.
2
Answers to it will provide some kind of justification for why the entities identified in the
first question have the kind of value identified in the second.
I. "What is considered valuable?"
The natural environment and the entities that comprise it are of deep ethical concern to
the environmentalist. To that end a basic project for the environmentalist is to establish that
entities in the natural world including individual living organisms
3
, species, and ecological
systems are due some kind of moral standing or considerability. For them things such as
butterflies, endangered populations, rainforests and salt marshes deserve significant moral
deference and respect from us. The environmentalist seeks to expand the scope of what moral
patients are beyond the confines of humans and their interests. However, to what extent this
expansion should occur is a matter of some debate. The question regarding the extent of this
expansion, and of what kinds of things ought to be covered by it, is one of scope for an
environmental ethic.
4
2
The separation of these questions is not meant to suggest that environmental metaethics is
completely distinct and separate from the formulation of environmental ethical theories. In fact
virtually any well-articulated environmental ethical theory is going to take some position on
metaethics.
3
In this dissertation I will use the term “living things” and “organisms” interchangeably.
4
For references on the question of scope for an environmental ethic, see: B. Muraca, “The Map
of Moral Significance: A New Axiological Matrix for Environmental Ethics”, Environmental
Values or E. Katz, “Is There a Place for Animals in the Moral Consideration of Nature?”, in
Environmental Ethics: An Anthology (eds. A. Light and H. Rolston III), 2003, Blackwell
3
In light of these considerations I would like to provide a brief overview of the variety of
perspectives on the scope of environmental ethics.
The environmental ethicist’s main concern is to argue on behalf of the existence of non-
anthropocentric value.
5
This broadening of ethical concern, away from what they regard as a
narrow form of anthropocentrism, is aimed at preventing further destruction of the natural world
by humans. In order to be successful at treating the natural environment with care, they say that
we must first think differently about it. They argue that since our moral regard for nonhumans
and the environment has up until this point been either biased or prejudiced, we have
unthinkingly harmed the natural world by treating various parts of it improperly. That is we have
treated them as falling outside of the scope of moral considerability. The scope for a new,
environmental ethic seeks to go beyond mere anthropocentricism usually by incorporating either
a biocentric
6
or an ecocentric perspective
7
or some combination of the two.
8
Publishing. These are but two sources among many that address the question of scope.
5
Non-anthropocentrism in ethics is basically the claim that there are things beside human beings
and their states such as living organisms, species, or ecosystems that have intrinsic value.
6
There are two basic positions within biocentrism, 1) Biocentric individualism and 2) Biocentric
holism. Biocentric individualism claims that individual living organisms are directly morally
considerable. Biocentric holism, on the other hand, claims that groups of individual organisms,
most notably species, are the objects of direct moral consideration. A species is a collective unit
of individual living organisms that typically are reproductively isolated. For a good treatment on
the question of the moral standing, preservation and value of species see “Part II: Values and
Objectives” of the book The Preservation of Species: The Value of Biological Diversity, ed. B.G.
Norton, 1986, Princeton University Press. A biocentrist could embrace individualism, holism or
both. For a defense of the scope of biocentrism see, James Sterba’s (1998) “A Biocentrist Strikes
Back”, Environmental Ethics, 20:361-376. Other key figures in the biocentric ethic are Albert
Schweitzer, Kenneth Goodpaster, and Paul Taylor.
7
An ecocentrist claims that entities above and beyond mere individual biological organisms and
species have value. For the ecocentrist, the domain of value should encompass ecosystems,
communities, and habitats, etc. For an interesting discussion of whether ecosystems have value
see Harley Cahen’s “Against the Moral Considerability of Ecosystems”, Environmental Ethics,
1988, 10: 195-216.
8
Some environmental ethicists argue that there is no need for a new, non-anthropocentric ethic
4
Biocentrists might be silent on the question of whether ecosystems have value. Being a
biocentrist does not entail being an ecocentrist. All that is required for biocentrism is the belief
that all living organisms have intrinsic value. One reason for this emphasis is found in their
concern for the protection of endangered species or rare organisms. Other collective entities of
living organisms that are also valued by environmentalists are rare or endangered communities
9
of organisms or threatened habitats
10
such as salt flats, bogs or savannas.
11
There are also two
basic strands of biocentrism. The first is what is known as biocentric holism. This position
claims that what has value or moral standing is a species. The second is known as biocentric
individualism. This position claims that what has value or moral standing are individual
organisms. Some biocentrist might choose to embrace both of these views. Some, biocentrists,
however, argue that only species can have moral standing, while other biocentrists argue that
only individual organisms can have moral standing.
An environmental ethic need not be confined to biocentrism. Since a great variety of
living organisms and species are ecologically interconnected as member of an ecosystem,
environmentalists have a great concern for this larger collective as well. Ecosystems are not just
at all. To see a further treatment of the question of whether a non-anthropocentric ethic is needed
see: “R. Sylvan, “Is There a Need for a New, an Environmental, Ethic?”, in Environmental
Ethics: An Anthology (eds. A. Light and H. Rolston III), 2003, Blackwell Publishing.
9
A community is an association of different species of individual organisms that usually inhabit
a common location or habitat.
10
A habitat includes both biotic and abiotic factors which vary on the basis of things like soil
type, vegetation type, salinity, altitude, availability of water, climate, temperature, etc.
11
Another somewhat perplexing aspect of the distinction between biocentrism and ecocentrism
lies in differences over what it means for something to be “alive”. For many ecocentrists the
land, habitats and ecosystems themselves simply are alive just as much as individual organisms
are. This claim, however, is quite controversial and not universally accepted. For an in-depth
evaluation of the claim that ecosystems are alive see Vincent Vesterby’s “Are Ecosystems
Alive?” in The Proceedings of the 52
nd
Annual Meeting of the ISSS, 2008.
5
comprised of the individual, living organisms present within a given area but also the abiotic
factors in the environment.
12
In any event, some ecocentrists may nonetheless wish to abandon a commitment to a
biocentric ethic which claims that living organisms have intrinsic value and instead opt to ground
the value of living organisms on their extrinsic or utilitarian value in terms of their functional
contribution to the larger, intrinsically-valuable ecosystem of which they are a part.
Some environmentalists believe that even the non-biotic components of the earth have
value as well. They argue that water soil, natural resources, air, etc. have moral standing.
13
Others go even further and claim that the planet itself has moral value. These types of positions
are typically found among Deep Ecologists
14
and Gaia theorists
15
who view all elements of the
biotic and abiotic world as members of a mutually-dependent and value-laden reality.
12
Given that specific habitats are often home to specific organisms, most biocentrists have an
interest in habitat protection as well. They do not see biological interests as being all that
separate from ecological or ecosystem-level interests. To that end see, Philip Carafo’s discussion
of the connection between the preservation of species and preservation of habitat or communities
in “For a Grounded Conception of Wilderness and More Wilderness on the Ground”, Ethics and
the Environment, 2001, 6:1-17. Respect for the organism means respecting its habitat and
surroundings. Also, the dividing line between biocentrism and ecocentrism is not precisely clear
cut. An individual animal can also serve as a host to a number of other species that live either in
it or on it. So, is the animal in question an ecosystem? Or is it a single biological organism?
13
For this view see Aldo Leopold’s “The Land Ethic” in A Sand County Almanac. Deep
ecologists such as Arne Naess and George Sessions also hold this view.
14
The term “Deep Ecology” was first coined by Arne Naess (1973) in “The Shallow and the
Deep Ecology Movement”, Inquiry, 16:95-100. Deep ecologists stress human’s place in an
interconnected web of ecological relations and of human’s oneness with nature. Figures also
include Bill Devall, Warwick Fox, George Sessions and Michael Zimmerman among others.
15
Gaia theorists think that the Earth itself is one living organism with perhaps its own
consciousness. A key figure in Gaia theory is James Lovelock. For an interesting discussion on
the connection between Gaia theory and environmental ethics see Anthony Weston’s (1987)
“Forms of Gaian Ethics”, Environmental Ethics, 9:217-230.
6
The positions outlined above illustrate that there is a wide variety of views on what the
proper scope of an environmental ethic should be. However, most environmentalists tend to
focus their concern on the proper treatment of living organisms, species, or ecosystems. Other
environmental ethicists wish to cast the net further and claim that land or even the planet Earth
itself has value.
16
For the purposes of this dissertation, I will confine my discussion of environmental
ethical theories to those that make arguments in support of biocentric individualism.
II. "What kind of value do these things have?"
Environmentalists are concerned with what kind of value that living organisms, species,
and ecosystems possess. Many of them maintain that the kind of value they have is intrinsic.
17
Biocentrists, for example believe that life has intrinsic value while many ecocentrists believe that
ecosystems have such value.
One of the motivating reasons for the biocentrist’s endorsement of the claim that living
organisms have intrinsic value is that they feel that a proper attitude of respect for nature should
16
Some may even go so far as to claim that the universe as a whole is an object of value. Frank
Lunger defends the intrinsic moral value of the cosmos in “Anthropocentrism vs.
Cosmocentrism: Groping Towards a Paradigm Shift”, The Newsletter of the Philosophical
Discussion Group of British Mensa, 2000, 102, (http://theotodman.com/c10208.htm). Also, Mark
Lupisella, a NASA scientist, has argued that the cosmocentric perspective might also serve us
well in the endeavor to communicate with extraterrestrial life forms. Both humans and
extraterrestrials could communicate over something they value in common, namely our “ultimate
shared cosmic origins”. See M.L. Lupisella, “Cosmocentrism and the Active Search for
Extraterrestrial Intelligence”, Astrobiology Science Conference, 2010.
17
Intrinsic value, broadly defined, is the value that a thing has in and of itself. There is also
some question as to whether saying that something has intrinsic value means saying that it
possesses that value itself or that it ought to be valued in and of itself.
I will further discuss the concept of intrinsic value and of its various definitions later in this
chapter.
7
move us away from construing things such as non-human living organisms as being only
instrumentally valuable for human purposes. Thinking that nature has such value also encourages
movement away from radically subjectivist notions of what has value (“I know that you think
that butterflies are non-instrumentally valuable, but that’s just your opinion from your
perspective!”). Embracing nature’s intrinsic value moves us towards an attitude of evaluation
that considers nature and the objects found in nature as morally valuable regardless of how
useful or instrumental they might be for us and regardless of whether they happens to be valued
merely on the basis some individual’s personal opinion. Intrinsic value is usually put in contrast
with either radically subjective views of value or strictly instrumentalist value for human
beings.
18
Environmentalists think that we should move away from thinking that the natural
world only has these kinds of value.
First, environmentalists think that if we continue to believe that nonhumans, species or
ecosystems only have instrumental value then we will not have the proper attitude about the
environment that we should. Instead of regarding nature as a mere collection of useful
instruments, we should regard it as being good in itself. For example, the biocentrist thinks that
all organisms are valuable, not just the ones that happen to be useful to Homo sapiens. They
think that a person who believes that all nonhuman moral value is merely instrumental doesn’t
really have any good reason (apart from those instrumental values themselves) to adequately
respect living things that aren’t useful for us.
Second, many environmentalists want to avoid radically subjective views about the value
18
It should be noted, however, that one can reject both instrumentalist and radical subjectivist
views of environmental value without also having to accept a theory of intrinsic value. These
people might hold the view that a living thing could have extrinsic value, as opposed to intrinsic
value, but still think that its extrinsic value gives a reason for why someone ought to value it in
and of itself.
8
of the natural world. They think that if environmental value should turn out to be just a matter of
personal preference or opinion, then there wouldn’t be any objectively right or wrong answer as
to what our moral obligations are towards nature. For instance, should a person choose to regard
the red-cockaded woodpecker
19
to be without moral value (as a result of her own personal taste)
then that person isn’t necessarily committing any moral oversight by having that preference or of
thinking that she had no moral obligations toward that species or an individual of that species.
Consequently such a person’s ethical view cannot be criticized as inadequate. Her view of the
moral status of the bird is simply different from, but not inferior to, the biocentrist’s view. And
since no one preference is inherently better than any other, a preference for non-biocentrism isn’t
necessarily wrong or inferior to biocentrism according to this type of subjectivism.
Holmes Rolston III, a significant contributor to environmental ethics, has argued that this
kind of subjectivity in environmental ethics must be challenged. He writes, “with the
environmental turn, so surprising and pressing in the final quarter of our century, [this]
subjectivism in values needs review…”(Rolston III, 1982, p. 126).
20
Rolston is wary about the
prospect that subjectivism may hold for an environmental ethic. He believes “value is (in part)
provided objectively in nature”. But he also holds that “value arises only as a product of
subjective experience, albeit relationally in nature…” (Rolston, 1982, p. 144). Rolston claims
that the objective properties in nature bring about in a perceiver the (admittedly) subjective
experience of morally valuing the thing perceived.
21
19
A federally-listed, endangered species.
20
Later in this chapter I will discuss the objectivism/subjectivism debate as it applies to intrinsic
value, not simply value simpliciter. This particular debate has taken place between Rolston and J.
Baird Callicott.
21
While some environmental philosophers may want to claim that this view is ultimately a form
of value subjectivism, Rolston maintains that it can still avoid a subjectivist meta-ethic (Rolston,
9
Another environmental ethicist, R. W. Sperry has stressed the need for human society to
get it right on the question of nature’s moral value. It was objectively wrong for us to have
caused as much damage as we have to the environment, Sperry claims, and it is objectively right
that we should do something to protect and respect it. This implies the existence of a moral
standard beside that of mere subjective preference. And because our environmental problems are
so pressing and important, we need a principled way of guiding our dealings with the
environment. We must move away from laissez-faire moral subjectivity and recognize the truth
of our moral obligations to the environment. He writes,
“…large segments of civilized society drift today in a state of confusion, at a loss
with regard to ethical standards, morality, goals, and sense of purpose and
direction in the human endeavor generally….When the Society for Zero
Population Growth squares off against the church on issues of abortion, birth
control, optimal population, and related questions, by what ultimate standards do
we decide who is in the right?...Our tolerant, educated Western societies, in
particular, seem more and more to be lacking in conviction with regard to any
kind of ultimate standards.” (Sperry, 1974, p. 10)
According to Sperry we must not simply wander in a sea of subjectivity if we are going
to meet the challenge of protecting the environment as we ought.
III. A Discussion of Intrinsic Value
In opposition to radically subjective or instrumentalist views, environmentalists have
taken up the task of persuading others away from such thinking about nature. They want us to
take up a different, higher view of nature which values it intrinsically. Environmentalists think
that nonhumans and ecosystems are valuable in and of themselves and not simply on the basis of
1982). This is very similar to the position of Y.S. Lo who claims that analysis of a natural
object’s moral properties reduces to “the empirical relations between the object’s natural
properties [empirical properties] and people’s psychological dispositions to respond to them.”
(Lo, 2006, p.123).
10
either subjective, personal preferences or instrumentalist concerns.
Many biocentrists argue that living organisms are valuable in themselves for fairly
straightforward reasons. Persons who fail to recognize these reasons also fail to value nature in
and of itself, and thus are guilty of a kind of moral blindness. These persons, it is argued, either
have an inability to recognize their moral obligations concerning nature or they have an outright
unwillingness to acknowledge the existence of such obligations.
22
Environmentalists hold that our proper treatment of the natural world will take root only
insofar as we have a new and right understanding of the kind of value that nonhumans, species
and ecosystems have. They claim that a proper attitude about nature begins by recognizing the
intrinsic value that exists in nature.
For instance, in 1949 Aldo Leopold argued that our attitude and outlook toward nature
needed to change and be redirected towards an “intense consciousness of land”. He wrote,
"Perhaps the most serious obstacle impeding the evolution of the land ethic is the
fact that our educational and economic system is headed away from, rather than
toward, an intense consciousness of land. Your true modern is separated from the
land by many middlemen, and by innumerable physical gadgets. He had no vital
relation to it; to him it is the space between cities and which crops grow. Turn him
loose for a day on the land, and if the spot does not happen to be a golf links or a
‘scenic’ area, he is bored stiff." (Leopold, 2003, p. 46).
An "intense consciousness of land" requires thinking about the land, or the environment,
22
Some may argue, however, that a person can still believe that they have moral obligations to
protect the environment for anthropocentrically-oriented utilitarian reasons. But many
environmentalists think that utilitarian reasons of that kind are not enough of a warrant for real
moral obligations to protect the environment. For instance, a biocentrist thinks that all living
organisms are due moral consideration. But since at least some organisms do not appear to have
any substantial utilitarian value for human beings, most biocentrists think that anthropocentric
utilitarian concerns aren’t enough of a warrant for the protection of all of life either. However,
should it turn out that all living organisms have at least some utilitarian value, an instrumentalist
could claim that we would have an obligation to protect them as one would protect a useful
instrument. Under those conditions a person could embrace an instrumentalist take on value and
also be a biocentrist.
11
differently. According to Leopold we must value nature for what it is in and of itself instead of
viewing nature as existing solely for our benefit. We must value it intrinsically
23
. This, he
claims, will lead us to a new ethic, one that properly values plants, animals and ecosystems as
ends in themselves. All other ethics, particularly the dominant ethic of Western civilization, see
nature as a storehouse or factory of goods that are only available for us to use and that exist at
our disposal. "We must change this," says the environmental ethicist.
Much of the discussion about moral value in nature has focused on intrinsic value and
what precisely it means to say that living organisms and ecosystems have this value. As Lars
Samuelsson puts it, “Ever since environmental ethics (EE) began to take form as an academic
discipline in the early 1970s, the notion of intrinsic value has occupied a prominent position
within the field.” (Samuelsson, 2010, p. 517). Also, J. Baird Callicot has said “Indeed, how to
discover intrinsic value in nature is the defining problem for environmental ethics.” (Callicott,
1995). This “defining problem” attempts to place nonhumans and even ecosystems in the proper
place of moral valuations, as possessors of ‘intrinsic value’. As Holmes Rolston III articulates it,
“Natural things can and ought to count morally for what they are in themselves.” (my emphasis,
Rolston III, 2009, p.97).
Still other environmental philosophers have argued that the notion of intrinsic value itself
23
Leopold stresses the importance of thinking differently about the environment and of the
value that is has in itself in the final section of “The Land Ethic”. To be clear Leopold does not
use the term intrinsic to describe the value of nature, but he does think that nature’s value is not
economic. At least with regard to human economic endeavors nature has non-instrumental value.
He writes,
“The ‘key-log’ which must be moved…is simply this: quit thinking about decent land-use as
solely an economic problem. Examine each question in terms of what is ethically and esthetically
right…The fallacy that the economic determinists have tied around our collective neck…is the
belief that economics determines all landuse.”(Leopold, 2003, p.46).
I interpret Leopold's passage here to mean that nature is something that is valuable in itself or
that it should be valued for what it is, not for what it can do for us.
12
needs to be dropped from the practice of environmental ethics altogether.
24
Some of intrinsic
value’s detractors argue that environmental ethics should be more about the practical business of
solving real environmental problems, than getting bogged down with metaphysically strange
concepts such as intrinsic value. They argue that we must assess what it is that we ought to do by
finding the best practical solutions to environmental problems through either policy changes or
changes in education. Paul Ott, for example, claims that intrinsic value theory in environmental
ethics “like all theory, arose as a response to a set of problems in experience, in this case the
problems of human overuse and abuse of nonhuman nature.” (Ott, 2010, p. 291). That is intrinsic
value is not so much an objectively existing concept found in the nature of things but a concept
constructed out of human desires to pragmatically respond to environmental problems.
25
Nonetheless, intrinsic value remains a major aspect of the overall project of
environmental ethics. Many environmentalists hold that intrinsic value, as such a central feature,
is what makes it the case that we have certain moral obligations towards nonhumans or
ecosystems. Hugh McDonald explains how intrinsic value links the value of nonhumans and
ecosystems to our moral obligations regarding them. He writes,
24
They include the ‘environmental pragmatists’ Paul Ott, Bryan Norton, Bruce Morito, and
Anthony Weston. See Bruce Morito’s (2003) “Intrinsic Value: A Modern Albatross for the
Ecological Approach.” Environmental Values 12: 317-336, Bryan Norton’s (1987) Why Preserve
Natural Variety?, Princeton University Press, and Anthony Weston (1996) “Beyond Intrinsic
Value: Pragmatism in Environmental Ethics.” In Environmental Pragmatism, edited by Andrew
Light and Eric Katz (London: Routledge): 285-306. Also I recommend reviewing Andrew
Light’s concept of ‘methodological environmental pragmatism’ in (2002) “Contemporary
Environmental Ethics: From Metaethics to Public Philosophy.” Metaphilosophy 33: 426-429.
25
Not all environmental pragmatists reject intrinsic value. An environmental pragmatist who
accepts the concept of intrinsic value is Eugene Hargrove. See Hargrove’s (1992) “Weak
Anthropocentric Intrinsic Value”, Monist, 75:183-207. I will not address the arguments of the
environmental pragmatists in further detail here, but I will nonetheless defend a particular
understanding of intrinsic value as an important central feature to a biocentric ethic. For a broad
defense of the concept of intrinsic value see Katie McShane’s (2007) “Why Environmental
Ethics Shouldn’t Give Up on Intrinsic Value.” Environmental Ethics, 29: 43-61.
13
"If something has inherent or intrinsic value, it is entitled to moral considerability.
This is the hidden minor in many of the intrinsic value arguments in
environmental ethics. The conclusion, that moral agents have a duty [my
emphasis] to protect bearers of intrinsic value, does not follow directly from the
"presence" of intrinsic value. The minor is required to connect value to obligation.
This creates a warrant, ground, reason, or justification for the protection of
nonhuman nature, however the latter is defined. Environmental ethics, then, is
within the rationalist tradition of the West in attempting to justify its ethical
mandates with reasons." (McDonald, 2003, p. 8)
In other words, if something has intrinsic value, that value also provides a “warrant,
ground, reason, or justification” for our moral duties to those things.
26
And since biocentrists
and ecocentrists are interested in providing compelling reasons for the existence of the duties
that we have to the natural world, they are also in the business of showing how nonhumans,
species and ecosystems have intrinsic value and for why such value is reason-giving in the way
described by McDonald.
IV. The Varieties of Intrinsic Value
The specific claim that individual, non-human, living organisms have intrinsic value,
unfortunately, has been subject to a considerable lack of clarity
27
. As Jonathan O’Neill writes,
“To hold an environmental ethic is to hold that non-human beings and states of
26
This, however, should not be interpreted to mean that the only way for a person to care about
the environment is by valuing it intrinsically. A person may show care for nature and think that
they have duties to protect it and yet only value it for instrumental or personal, subjective
reasons. Instead it should be interpreted to mean that the proper or best way for a person to value
the environment is to value it intrinsically which can only be done by recognizing something
about the environment that warrants our having that attitude about it. This is what the
environmentalist thinks that we should do. We should value nature in the right way and with the
right attitude.
27
There is, however, a very broad understanding of what intrinsic value is even though working
out some of its conceptual details has been, and continues to be, a challenge. As mentioned
previously, intrinsic value basically refers to the kind of value that a thing has ‘in itself’. As
Ronald Sandler writes, "Generally, intrinsic value refers to the value that something has in and of
itself. It is often contrasted with instrumental value - i.e. the value that something possesses as a
means to a desired end of another." (Sandler, 2012, p. 92)
14
affairs in the natural world have intrinsic value. This seemingly straightforward
claim has been the focus of much recent philosophical discussion of
environmental issues. Its clarity is, however, illusory. The term 'intrinsic value'
has a variety of senses [my emphasis] and many arguments on environmental
ethics suffer from conflation of these different senses: specimen hunters for the
fallacy of equivocation will find rich pickings in the area.”(O'Neill, 1992, p.119).
The question of what sense of intrinsic value is most appropriate for an environmental
ethic has been considered at length by various environmental ethicists. I will address the
existence of intrinsic value’s “variety of senses” alluded to by O’Neill by considering three
separate definitions of it that have been provided by Ronald Sandler (2012a).
28
These
definitions are: 1) intrinsic subjective value, 2) intrinsic objective value, and 3) inherent worth.
They are defined as:
Intrinsic subjective value: The value that something possesses in virtue of being
valued for what it is, rather than its usefulness as a means to an end.
Intrinsic objective value: The value that something possesses in and of itself,
independent of whether anyone actually values it.
Inherent worth: The value that something possesses in virtue of having a good of
its own (or interests) that valuers (or moral agents) ought to care about. (Sandler,
2012a, p. 92)
For purposes of this dissertation I will briefly describe the first two senses of intrinsic
value and then proceed to a deeper discussion of the third sense of intrinsic value known as
28
Jonathan O’Neill has isolated three distinct definitions of intrinsic value (O’Neill, 1992) while
Dale Jamieson has isolated four in chapter three of his book "Ethics and the Environment: An
Introduction" (Jamieson, 2008). For the purposes of this dissertation, however, I will address the
three varieties of intrinsic value discussed by Sandler. In formulating an environmental ethical
theory one must be sensitive to these distinctions and be prepared to apply their preferred
definition consistently. O’Neill identifies three senses of intrinsic value which are different from
Sandler’s. They are 1) “non-instrumental value”, 2) “non-relational (Moorean) value” and 3)
“objective value”. O’Neill’s second sense of intrinsic value, non-relational (Moorean) value
defines intrinsic value as, value an object has solely in virtue of its ‘intrinsic properties’. G.E.
Moore believed that intrinsic properties were non-relational. (see O’Neill, 1992, p. 123). These
properties come from the intrinsic nature of the object in question. The link between the things
intrinsic value and its intrinsic property (ies) is immediate and does not depend on any relations
between that entity and other things outside of it. Such relations might be, for example, those
between the psychological states of valuers and the thing being valued. That is, this value can be
characterized without reference to other objects and any of their states.
15
“inherent worth”. Among all three senses of intrinsic value, inherent worth is the most important
for the biocentrist endeavoring to make arguments on behalf of biocentric individualism.
V. Intrinsic Subjective Value
Let us take the first sense of intrinsic value as “intrinsic subjective value”
29
. This notion claims
that intrinsic value comes into existence whenever a moral agent values a thing intrinsically.
Whenever a moral agent values a thing intrinsically that agent values that thing for what it is, not
for what it does. Things can be intrinsically valued by a moral agent if that moral agent values it
for what it is. This type of intrinsic value is one that can only exist in the presence of an actual
valuer intrinsically valuing a thing. As Ronald Sandler describes it this value is “created by
valuers through their evaluative attitudes or judgments it does not exist prior to or independent
from these” (Sandler, 2012b, p.4).
30
29
This sense of intrinsic value is roughly synonymous with O’Neill’s “non-instrumental value”.
O’Neill references Arne Naess who captures this sense of intrinsic value thusly, “This value is
independent of any instrumental usefulness for limited human purposes” (Naess, 1984, p. 266).
30
It should be noted that the usage of the term “intrinsic subjective value” is not considered
standard by a number of ethical theorists. Christine Korsgard, for example would most likely
object to the use of the term “intrinsic subjective value”. She thinks (or would most likely think)
that intrinsic value means “intrinsic objective value”. That is it is a kind of value or goodness that
a thing possesses in itself, regardless of it being valued “intrinsically” by other valuers. For her
intrinsic value is not something that can be brought about by a valuer valuing a thing in and of
itself. For her the proper distinction should be between intrinsic value and extrinsic value as
opposed to intrinsic value and instrumental value. She writes,
It is rather standard fare in philosophy to distinguish two kinds of this value of goodness, often
called "intrinsic" and "instrumental."' Objects, activities, or whatever, have an instrumental value
if they are valued for the sake of something else-tools, money, and chores would be standard
examples. A common explanation of the supposedly contrasting kind, intrinsic goodness, is to
say that a thing is intrinsically good if it is valued for its own sake, that being the obvious
alternative to a thing's being valued for the sake of something else. This is not, however, what
the words "intrinsic value" mean. To say that something is intrinsically good is not by definition
to say that it is valued for its own sake: it is to say that it has its goodness in itself [my
emphasis]. It refers, one might say, to the location or source of the goodness rather than the way
we value the thing. The contrast between instrumental and intrinsic value is therefore misleading,
16
A major voice behind this view of intrinsic value is J. Baird Callicott. Callicott thinks that
intrinsic value is indeed vital to a solid environmental ethic, but he also thinks that intrinsic value
as such must ultimately be rooted in metaethical subjectivity. He writes, “After thinking very
hard, during the mid-1980s, about the ontology of value finally I came reluctantly to the
conclusion that intrinsic value cannot exist objectively.” (Callicott, 1992, p. 132). Callicott
claims that value does not specifically reside in the object valued. Rather intrinsic value is
brought about whenever a person values something intrinsically or in and of itself.
Holmes Rolston sums up what this subjective version of intrinsic value means in the
following way,
“To say that something is intrinsically valuable means that it is of such a kind that
were valuers to arrive they might value it intrinsically rather than
instrumentally…By this account there is no actual value ownership autonomous
to the valued and valuable flower; there is value ignition when humans come.”
(Rolston, 1988, p. 114).
31
Other environmentalists might want to clarify Rolston’s statement to say that it is not the
case that valuers might value a living things intrinsically upon encountering them but that valuers
would value living things intrinsically upon encountering them. This kind of metaethical
subjectivism could still claim that it would objectively be the case that if some valuer, V, were to
encounter living organism, X, that V would intrinsically value X.
Even if it should turn out that intrinsic value is, to use Rolston’s term, “ignited” by the
presence of a valuer, it does not follow that moral obligations are subjective as well. Something
a false contrast. The natural contrast to intrinsic goodness - the value a thing has "in itself" - is
extrinsic goodness - the value a thing gets from some other source. (Korsgard, 1983, pp. 169-
170).
So for Korsgard “intrinsic subjective value” would not be a kind of intrinsic value at all but
rather a kind of extrinsic value.
31
Rolston also calls the view that intrinsic value can be autonomously owned by the valued
object a “theory of autonomous intrinsic value” (Rolston, 1988, p. 114).
17
can possess an objective property that provides a moral agent with sound reasons for the
existence of real moral obligations that are genuinely binding. For instance, should it be the case
that all living organisms have their own biological life purposes and goals, then the existence of
these projects and goals might also provide reasons for why that organism’s life should not be
ended without good cause. Moreover should the value of the organism be the product of a
valuing subject it does not follow that the existence of that kind of subjective value precludes the
existence of objective moral obligations to treat the organism with care. Hence, it is possible to
believe that even if value should turn out to be metaethically subjective, moral obligations might
nonetheless be valuer independent.
VI. Intrinsic Objective Value
The second sense of intrinsic value provided by Sandler is roughly the same as Jonathan
O’Neill’s “objective value” defined as “value that an object possesses independently of the
valuations of valuers” (O’Neill, 1992, p. 125). According to O’Neill if something possesses
intrinsic objective value then it also possesses “evaluative properties [which] are real properties
of objects, that is, they are properties that objects possesses independently of the valuations of
valuers
32
” (my emphasis, O’Neill, 1992, p. 125). The evaluative properties of a thing are those
properties that make that thing good and worthy of being treated with some care. On this
understanding, a thing’s moral status is acquired on the basis of its possession of one or more
evaluative properties. Under this understanding of intrinsic value some objectively true
statement(s) about an object, those statements that employ one or more evaluative properties, are
also statements that support the thing’s moral standing along with whatever moral obligations we
32
O’Neill does not say whether these properties are natural or non-natural.
18
have. Evaluative properties belong to the object in question and continue to exist and be
associated with that object regardless of observers knowing about those properties or having
thoughts of moral approval of them.
VII. Inherent Worth
The third, and final, variety of intrinsic value considered by Sandler is different from
either subjective or objective intrinsic value. This third sense of intrinsic value is that of
“inherent worth”. It is defined by Sandler as: “The value that something possesses in virtue of
having a good of its own (or interests) that valuers ought to care about”.
33
It should be noted that the mere existence of interests does not necessarily prove that
someone ought to care about the thing that has those interests. For instance, Paul Taylor
recognizes that even if all living things have "a good of their own" (an ‘is’
34
, Taylor, 1986,
p.72), a person may still deny that all living things have what he calls "inherent worth" or that we
have any moral duties (“oughts”) to protect them. He writes,
“The concept of inherent worth must not be confused with the concept of a good
of a being. To bring out the difference between them, consider the logical gap
between the fact that a being has a good of its own (an is-statement) and the claim
that it should or should not be treated in a certain way (an ought-statement). One
can acknowledge that an animal or plant has a good of its own and yet
consistently with this acknowledgement, deny that moral agents have a duty to
33
Instead of referring to a “good of one’s own” I will use the term “interests” instead. The
definition of inherent worth provided by Sandler suggests that there is no difference between
something have a "good of its own" and it having interests. However, in chapter four of this
dissertation I suggest that is possible for some living thing to have interests yet not have a "good
of their own".
34
Environmentalist tend to reserve the use of the notion of “having a good of one’s own” in
their arguments for non-anthropocentric value. For example, Paul Taylor has said, “Since I am
concerned only with human treatment of wild organisms, species populations, and communities
of life as they occur in our planet’s natural ecosystems, it is to those entities alone that the
concept “having a good of its own” will here be applied” (Taylor, 2003, p. 75). For Taylor,
beings that “have a good of their own” deserve moral respect.
19
promote or protect its good or even to refrain from harming it. One does not
contradict oneself by saying, 'Yes, I know that this action of mine will adversely
affect the good of living things, but nevertheless there is no reason why I
shouldn't do it.' There may in truth be a reason against doing the act, and that
reason may be the fact that the act will be detrimental to the good of living things,
but we cannot just assert this to be the case on the ground that the living things in
question have a good of their own” (Taylor, 1986, p. 71-72).
That is, says Taylor, just because something has a "good of its own" someone may still
argue it does not mean that that thing automatically deserves moral standing or that such goods
place any moral duties upon moral agents to be recognized. This is roughly known as the
"is/ought" distinction. Hume made use of this distinction to argue that normative statements,
statements about what we ought to do, are not logically deducible on the basis of what is the
case. Hence, ought statements can always be doubted on the basis of whatever is the case.
Nonetheless, a person can point to what is the case as a means of persuading someone else to
accept an evaluative claim.
The first part of Sandler's definition of inherent worth represents an “is” clause. An "is"
clause is simply a descriptive statement. The descriptive statement found in the definition of
inherent worth above is that of “having interests”. According to this clause of the definition there
is some objective fact of the matter which makes it the case that a thing has interests.
Note that according to Sandler’s definition of inherent worth it is possible for something
to have interests but in which such interests are not ones that valuers have some obligation to
care about. Claims about having interests, as a purely descriptive matter, are either true or false.
If they are true then we still have the question of whether those interests provide reason for why
valuers ought to care about the thing that has those interests. Furthermore, something can have
interests independently of whether anyone thinks that it has such interests or whether anyone
cares about such interests.
The second part of the definition is the “ought” clause. An "ought" clause is some kind of
20
evaluative statement or claim such as "You ought to care about X." or "You ought to value Y in
and of itself." This clause of Sandler's above definition simply states that moral agents ought to
care about the thing that has interests.
35
But what does it mean to say that a thing “has interests”? And why think that having
interests is roughly the same as having a “good of one’s own”? To say that a thing has interests is
to say that it has a stake in bringing about some condition that benefits it and in avoiding other
conditions that harm it. For example, I have an interest in being properly hydrated. This means
that I have a stake in being properly hydrated because proper hydration is beneficial for me. It is
a “good of my own” to be properly hydrated. Hence, I have an interest in it. Conversely, it is to
my detriment if I am incapable of obtaining water when I need it. I have a stake in avoiding
dehydration. This too means that I have an interest in avoiding dehydration.
I will assume that to say that a living thing has an interest is also to say that it has an
interest in something. So for instance, human beings have an interest in consuming water, an
interest in having a heart that functions correctly and an interest in having mitochondria that
make ATP. Canines, primates and many other vertebrate animals, also have interests in these
things too.
Interests are whatever is good for the thing that has them. Consuming water, having a
properly functioning heart and having mitochodria that make ATP are things that are “good for”
many living things.
As a first approximation, I will define an interest in the following way:
X has
36
an interest in Y (Y is an interest of X’s) if and only if Y is good for X
35
The point I intend to make here is not that having interests is a sufficient reason for why
someone ought to care about a thing that has interests. Rather I am pointing out the presence of
both an "is" and an "ought" clause within Sandler's definition of inherent worth.
36
Non-psychologically 'has'. To say that someone non-psychologically has an interest is roughly
21
where “Y is good for X” means that:
1) If X is denied Y then X is harmed and 2) If X is not denied Y then X is
benefited.
This definition is simply meant to serve as a first, rough approximation of what an
interest is. In chapter three I will make further clarifications of this definition of interests. The
main point I wish to get across here is that my use of the term “interests” will be limited to what
is necessary for a thing’s self-regulation or maintenance. These are the kinds of interests that a
thing can non-psychologically have. A thing can non-psychologically have interests in what
contributes to its self-regulation.
There can however, exist cases were something, Y, can be good for X but in which X
would not be harmed if it were denied Y. For example, a little bit of extra fertilizer on a plant
might be “good for” it. But if the plant is denied that little bit of fertilizer it is not harmed. A little
bit of extra fertilizer, is not necessary to the continued self-regulation and maintenance of it. On
the above definition the plant would not have an interest in the little bit of extra fertilizer even
though it looks as if having a little bit of extra fertilizer would be in the plant's interest.
37
Also, having interests is not the same thing as having some physical characteristic. I don’t
have an interest in drinking water in the same sort of way that one has blue eyes for example. I
have an interest in drinking water because the consumption of water is tied to my continued well-
the same as to say that there are certain things that are in a person's interests regardless of
whether he or she has a psychological awareness of it being good for them. To say that someone
psychologically has an interest is to say that that person has a conscious or psychological desire
or preference for something. If my wife psychologically has an interest in going walking then she
has a conscious desire to go walking. This is the difference between psychologically having an
interest and non-psychologically having an interest. On the above definition a person has an
interest if they have a non-psychological interest.
37
I am here simply using this case to show that there is a problem for the definition of having an
interest provided above. I will address this particular problem for the above definition of interests
when I discuss the unified, definition of interests in chapter three.
22
being. But having blue eyes is a characteristic that is not connected to my continued well-being
in the same sort of way. Thus, I have an interest in drinking water, but having blue eyes doesn’t
factor into what is in my interests.
Biocentrists claim that human beings are not the only living things that have interests.
They think that all living things have interests in the same sort of way that we have an interest in
proper hydration. For example, proper hydration and the avoidance of dehydration are good for
many animals. As such a deer will purposefully seek out water because it has an interest in it.
The reason why the deer engages in the "goal-directed" behavior of seeking out water is because
proper hydration is good for it. Proper hydration is in its interests. Biocentrists use this line of
thinking to argue that all forms of life have various interests in light of the kinds of beings that
they are. Every living thing in some sense "pursues" those things which are good for it and
"tries" to avoid those things which are bad for it. Their biological "pursuits" may not, however,
be ones that are consciously pursued. In the case of plants for example, gathering sunlight is in
their interests because it is good for them. And the fact that it is good for them is evidenced by
some of their goal-directed behaviors or tendencies
38
to get sunlight.
Many biocentrists argue that if a thing has interests then there is some good that it
pursues (or is pursuing) in one way or another.
But not all living things have the same interests. For example, a trout does not have an
interest in breathing air because breathing air is not one of the things that it needs to do.
However, breathing air is good for a kangaroo. So what is good for one living thing might not
38
I do not mean to say here that having interests means having pursuits or goal-directed
behavior only that having pursuits is regarded by some biocentrists as providing some evidence
about what is good for them and what they have interests in. Also, I do not hold the view that all
living things should be regarded as beings capable of engaging in "pursuits" or having "goal-
directed" behavior.
23
necessarily be good for some other living thing. The biocentrist holds that these goods are goods
of the living things themselves not merely goods for something else. As Sandler writes,
“An entity possesses a good of its own if it can be benefitted or harmed in a way
that isn’t relative to another’s aims or goals. For example, if in the process of an
excavation the roots of an oak tree are ripped up, it is in a straightforward way
bad for and harmful to the oak tree. It impairs its parts and processes, and thereby
its capabilities to survive, grow, and reproduce. Moreover, it is possible to make
sense of the harm without having to refer to anything beyond the oak tree e.g.,
the owner of the tree or the services that it provides for people or other species. It
is bad for the oak tree because it diminishes its capacity to pursue its ends (or to
flourish as an oak tree), independent of the effects on other organisms” (Sandler,
2012a, p. 97).
With regard to an oak tree there are things that can either harm it or benefit it. Ripping up
an oak tree’s roots causes it to be harmed. It is “bad” for the tree to sustain that kind of damage
because such damage either hampers or prevents its normal growth. It is “good for” the tree to
avoid such damage because avoidance of such damage contributes to its proper growth.
Accordingly, the tree has an interest in avoiding root damage.
But not only do oak trees have an interest in avoiding harmful conditions they also have
an interest in obtaining that which is positively beneficial to their survival and flourishing. So,
for instance, an oak tree has an interest in obtaining water and sunlight. It "directs"
(nonconsciously) its own physiological processes towards obtaining those things. Water and
sunlight are “good for” the tree just as much as avoiding root damage is “good for” the tree.
Thus, with regard to the tree’s growth, maintenance, survival and reproduction, etc. the oak tree
has an interest in both avoiding root damage, and in obtaining water and sunlight.
The above argument is the main reason why many biocentrists speak of “goods of one’s
(or its) own” to be roughly interchangeable with “interests”. A thing that has a “good of its own”,
is a thing that can either be harmed or benefitted and a thing that can be harmed or benefitted has
24
some goals or purposes
39
of its own that can either be prevented or realized by various
conditions.
40
Biocentric arguments that make reference to the concept of interests play a significant
role in the overall moral project of showing why all living things should be valued intrinsically.
Kenneth Goodpaster, one of the pioneers of the case for biocentrism notes the importance of
interests and its usage. He writes,
“I think the core of my answer must derive from reflection on the concept of
morality itself. Though this concept is not exhausted by its inclusion of reference
to the good and harm done to others by an agent, this reference is surely a central
part of it. Beneficence and nonmaleficence, then, are not only necessary
ingredients in our shared conception of moral (vs. nonmoral) obligation, they are
central. But one cannot do good for or avoid harm to entities that have no
interests [my emphasis]. Inanimate objects have no interests.” (Goodpaster, 1980,
p. 282).
Here Goodpaster is arguing that doing good for or avoiding harm to a thing is a central
factor in whether it has interests. For Goodpaster if a being has interests then that being is one
39
I do not wish to defend the claim that all living things have goals. Rather I am attempting to
describe what many biocentrists think having an interest means.
40
Paul Taylor, however, thinks that having a good of one’s own is not synonymous with having
interests. Taylor interprets the "having" of interests to be akin to having various psychological
states, such as desires or intentions or conscious aims towards acquiring some good or of having
experiences of satisfaction and dissatisfaction. Beings that do not have interests in this sense are
ones that “are not interested in, [and] do not care about, what happens to them” (Taylor, 1986, p.
63). Nonetheless Taylor thinks that there can still be things that are in an organism’s interest that
the organism itself might not have an interest in. For Taylor, those things that are in an
organism's interest are also the goods of that organism. Gary Varner, on the other hand, construes
the having of interests to be understood in non-psychological terms, in terms of what is good for
an organism. For him a thing can have interests even if it doesn’t have psychological states of
being interested in or of satisfaction and dissatisfaction. On this point, then, Varner and Taylor
disagree as to what the appropriate understanding of having an interest should mean. For this
dissertation I will interpret the having of interests to be either having an interest psychologically
(in the case of having psychological preferences) or having an interest non-psychologically (in
the case of having interests that do not depend on the existence of any psychological
preferences).
25
that can be either benefited or harmed.
41
Also Goodpaster thinks that if a being has interests
then that being has moral worth.
42
Gary Varner reiterates this basic view when he writes,
“It is because the concept of others’ interests is so closely allied with the concepts
of doing harm to and benefitting others [my emphasis] that interests are crucial to
our thinking about ethics. To say that a being has interests is to say that it has a
welfare, or a good of its own, that matters from the moral point of view. This is
why the satisfaction of interests [my emphasis] constitutes a fundamental moral
value.” (Varner, 1998, p.6).
43
Others, of course, could argue that the satisfaction of an organism’s interests isn’t
necessarily a morally good thing or that moral agents have any obligation to bring about what is
good for them, to avoid what is bad for them or even to care about them. As Ronald Sandler
writes,
“While it is relatively uncontroversial that all natural living things have a good of
their own, it is quite controversial which of those goods moral agents ought to
care about. On biocentric views, moral agents ought to care about the good of all
living things (Taylor 1986; Sterba 199[8], 2001); on sentientist
44
views, they
need only care about the goods of all conscious or self-aware living things (Singer
1975; Jamieson 1998); and on anthropocentric views, they need only care about
the goods of members of the species Homo sapiens (Baxter 1974; Pinchot 1914)”
(Sandler, 2012a, p. 98).
I will use the term “interests” to broadly denote those goods of living things that if
41
In chapter three I make a distinction between different kinds of “harm”. For example, a
picture can be “harmed” if someone scratches it. But this does not mean that the picture has
interests. There can exist some things that can be harmed but that do not have interests.
However, anything that has interests can be harmed.
42
Gary Varner also agrees with the notion that having interests is key in moral arguments in
support of a life-centered ethic. He writes, “I do not claim that the satisfaction of interests is the
only kind of moral value, but I do think it carries special weight, and…the environmentalist
agenda will be based, ultimately, on the satisfaction of interests.” (Varner, 1998, p.7)
43
As a reminder, I argue in chapter four of this dissertation that having a good of one's own is
not the same thing as having interests.
44
A sentientist is someone who thinks that only sentient beings, beings capable of feeling
pleasure and/or pain can qualify as beings that have moral standing.
26
pursued bring about their well-being.
45
If those goods are in one way or another prevented from
being realized, then that thing is subject to a harm. And if those goods are realized then it obtains
some benefit.
VIII. Clarifying the Definition of Inherent Worth
According to the definition of inherent worth provided above the value that a thing has is
based on whether the interests of a thing provide a valuing agent a compelling reason to care
about it.
As I mentioned previously, some might wish to regard inherent worth as defined here as
being a kind of intrinsic value. Others, however, might want to argue that it is not a kind of
intrinsic value but rather a kind of extrinsic value. Christine Korsgard would not regard inherent
worth as defined here to be a kind of intrinsic value because for her intrinsic value is not
something that is brought about by a valuer valuing a thing in and of itself. For her intrinsic
value is a kind of value that a thing possesses in itself, regardless of whether it is valued
“intrinsically” by other valuers.
For the purposes of this dissertation I will not address the question of whether we should
regard inherent worth as being a kind of intrinsic value or as a kind of extrinsic value. Whether
inherent worth is itself a type of intrinsic or extrinsic value is not an issue I wish to defend.
At this juncture I would like to provide some further clarification on the definition of
inherent worth that was provided by Sandler. In the following passage Sandler argues that
inherent worth, while sharing some similarities with intrinsic objective value, can also be
distinguished from it. He writes,
45
However, in chapter three I raise the view that some non-living things can have interests too.
27
“On some accounts of the basis of inherent worth it is a variety of intrinsic
objective value. On other accounts it is not. This is possible because the concept
of inherent worth differs from that of intrinsic objective value in the following
way: if an entity has intrinsic objective value it possesses that value even if there
are no valuers, whereas an entity possesses inherent worth if a valuer ought to
care about its interests [my emphasis]. One possible reason that a valuer ought to
care about the interests of an entity is it has intrinsic objective value, but that is
not the only possible reason.” (Sandler, 2012a, p. 97)
I would like to consider the above passage in further detail.
As Sandler suggests, “One possible reason that a valuer ought to care about the interests
of an entity is it has intrinsic objective value, but that is not the only possible reason”. For
instance, a valuer might hold the view that they ought to care about the interests of some things
and yet deny that intrinsic value itself is objective or that the thing in question has intrinsic
objective value. They may, for instance, think that intrinsic value is subjectively conferred yet
still affirm that they ought to care about it and its interests accordingly. It is for this reason that a
person can care about the interests of a thing for reasons other than its possession of intrinsic
objective value especially if they think that intrinsic objective value is a problematic metaethical
concept.
The definition of inherent worth provided by Sandler suggests (if not explicitly) that if an
entity possesses interests and the possession of interests does something in the way of providing
objective grounds or reasons for why valuers ought to care about it then it has inherent worth.
The proponent of inherent worth on this view seems to be committed to the view that at least
some interests are genuinely reason-providing and that such interests should not be merely
regarded as morally compelling based on one’s own personal opinion or preference about the
thing that has interests. However, if one grants from the outset that having interests automatically
provides a reason for why valuers should care about living things, then it would be a rather
straightforward matter to show that living organisms have inherent worth simply by showing that
28
they have interests.
This seems to be the approach of Paul Taylor who writes,
“If the fact that an entity has a good of its own does not logically entail that moral
agents ought or ought not to treat it in a certain way, the problem arises: What
relationship holds (if any) between an entity’s having a good and the claim its
good makes upon moral agents? I shall argue that, if a moral agent is to recognize
or acknowledge such a claim, the entity in question must not only be thought of as
having a good of its own; it must also be regarded as having inherent worth [my
emphasis].” (Taylor, 1986, p. 72).
That is, Taylor thinks that having a good of one’s own (interests) is the thing that
objectively and automatically provides a reason to think that something has inherent worth.
46
I, however, will be working on the assumption that the possession of interests does not by
itself necessarily or definitionally entail the existence of inherent worth for the thing that
possesses those interests. In order for living things to have inherent worth their interests must be
ones that have some objective quality about them that makes their possessor one that ought to be
cared about. Also I will be working on the assumption that if something has interests that do
provide a reason for why valuers ought to care about it, that such reasons make it the case that all
valuers ought to care about the thing that has those interests. What I want to suggest is that the
"reason providing" nature of interests makes it the case that all valuers ought to care about the
possessor of those interests even if those reasons are not appreciated or even fully known by any
valuers. There could exist some cases where a living thing could have an interest yet the interest
in question not be one that makes its possessor a thing that all valuers ought to care about. In
other words there can exist interests that might not provide a reason why any valuer should care
46
Gary Varner also appears to hold this view. He writes, “To say that a being has interests is to
say that it has a welfare, or a good of its own, that matters from the moral point of view [my
emphasis].” (see footnote 35 above). He also writes, “As I am using the term…an interest is, by
definition [my emphasis], morally significant.” (Varner, 1998, p. 77).
29
about the thing that has those interests. Hence, I will, unlike Taylor and Varner, treat the
possession of interests and whether those interests provide reasons for why valuers ought to care
about their possessor as two separate questions. To that end I would like to make a distinction
between interests and interests that provide such reasons. Interests that provide reasons for why
all valuers should care about their possessor are ones that I will call “morally considerable
interests”.
Since there is such a distinction I intend to define inherent worth more precisely. Such a
definition should make it a necessary condition that having inherent worth requires not simply
having interests but also having “morally considerable interests”, that is those interests that also
provide a reason for why all moral agents ought to care about the possessor of those interests. By
"moral agent" I mean a being that has the cognitive faculties that enable such a being to engage
in moral reasoning. A moral agent is one that is able to engage in at least three things, 1) to
discern right action from wrong action, 2) to be responsive to reasons for moral actions and
evaluations and 3) to make judgements regarding what has value and of what kind of value that
there is. A moral agent, as I use the term, is one that has properly-functioning cognitive
equipment that enables that being to engage in moral reasoning. So, if there happens to be an
individual that has some kind of brain injury that results in a malfunction of his cognitive
equipment that prevents him from properly engaging in moral reasoning, then that individual
would not be a moral agent.
With the above clarification in mind I offer the following, amended definition of inherent
worth:
First clarified definition of Inherent Worth (IW1): The value that a thing has in
virtue of,
a) having interests and
30
b) where such interests provide a reason why all
47
moral agents ought to care
about the thing that has such interests.
However, it might be objected that to ‘care about’ a thing is not necessarily the same
thing as to intrinsically value it or to value it in and of itself. For instance, I can care about my
car because it is a useful tool for transportation. But that does not necessarily mean that I also
intrinsically value my car.
48
I might only care about it instrumentally and not value it non-
instrumentally. It should be noted that when biocentrists say that we should "care about" living
things they don't mean that we should care about them because they are instrumentally useful.
They think we should care about them in a different sense, that of caring about them intrinsically.
For them, the instrumental value of living organisms should not be the reason why all moral
agents should care about them. Instead valuers should care about them for reasons independent
of their instrumental usefulness.
As such they would challenge the above definition of inherent worth by making the
following argument.
1) If x cares about y, then x values y non-instrumentally.
2) If x values y non-instrumentally, then x values y intrinsically.
3) Thus, if x cares about y, then x values y intrinsically.
Still others could object to the first premise of the above argument on the grounds that
there can exist some things, indeed many things that we "care about" but that we do not non-
47
I use the word "all" here to highlight the inclusion of not just human beings in the range of
moral valuers, but to all moral agents properly responsive to moral reasons. Presumably, there
could exist other moral agents besides human beings such as space aliens for example.
48
This should not mean that I cannot intrinsically value my car. I could take up the attitude of
valuing my car in and of itself as well.
31
instrumentally care about.
49
For instance, sometimes we care about things because of how
instrumentally valuable they are to us. For example, it makes some sense for many of us to say
that we "care about" our cars because of how useful they are in providing us with transportation.
This sense of "caring about", however, is not a sense non-instrumentally valuing a thing. Rather
this sense involves caring about a thing as a means of utilizing it for an instrumental end. It is a
sense of valuing a thing instrumentally.
But the sense of "caring about" that I am endorsing here, and that most environmentalists
endorse, is a sense of caring about something intrinsically.
But what does it mean to care about a thing intrinsically or non-instrumentally?
Consider these comments from Robert Simpson on the different things that we
intrinsically value. He writes,
"The things people value intrinsically can be grouped into three categories. First,
there are things whose value seems basic, primitive, or irreducible. ‘Pleasure’ is
the stock example of this it’s difficult to conceive of any further basis or reason
for pleasure being valuable; it just seems valuable full stop, so to speak. Call
whatever is valuable in this way an ‘elemental good’. Second, there are things
which, according to influential strands of ethical theory, there is a categorical
obligation to value intrinsically: persons, or relationships, or some class of beings
en masse (e.g. self-conscious creatures). Call anything that is valuable in this way
a ‘deontic good’. Third, there are all the things that do not seem like either
elemental or deontic goods, but which we intrinsically value nevertheless. As an
example, think of how you might value a beautiful tree in a park or garden. It’s
not that you believe you have a categorical duty to value the tree intrinsically. Nor
is it that you can’t conceive of there being any further bases or reasons for the
tree’s being valuable – indeed, the tree’s extrinsic benefits may be a large part of
why it matters to you. Nevertheless, you don’t value the tree extrinsically, in view
of the further good things it contains, leads to, or is associated with [my
emphasis]. Rather, to use that familiar and enigmatic expression, you value the
tree ‘in and of itself’. This is one example among many. Because of the rich
variety of ways in which people find value in their lives, there is wide range of
things which people value intrinsically despite the fact that those things would not
seem to the duly reflective valuer like elemental or deontic goods." (Simpson,
49
I also discuss notion of "caring for" something instrumentally versus "caring for" something
non-instrumentally in section VIII of chapter one.
32
pp. 2-3, 2015)
What Simpson is getting at in his description of the third sense of the way that we
intrinsically value things is that of taking up a valuing stance that has no regard for a thing's
utilitarian value in bringing about some other good. We value that thing non-instrumentally.
Basically whenever a person cares about something non-instrumentally they value it
without an eye to how useful that thing might be. This is how biocentrists think we should value
all living things. Things that we care about non-instrumentally, are things that we care about in
the way that biocentrists and other environmentalists think we should.
To that end I would like to amend premise one of the above argument to reflect
this sense of "caring about" a thing non-instrumentally.
The amended argument is the following:
1) If x cares about y non-instrumentally, then x values y non-instrumentally.
50
2) If x values y non-instrumentally, then x values y intrinsically.
3) Thus, if x cares about y non-instrumentally, then x values y intrinsically.
Some at this point might still have an objection to the above argument. They might find
fault with the second premise. They might say, "The only things that can be intrinsically valued
or cared about are those thing that have intrinsic value. So, for example, Michaelangelo's Pieta
does not have intrinsic value. So we cannot care about this sculpture intrinsically."
But an objector to the above argument might respond by saying, "I grant that the Pieta
only has extrinsic value. But why should that preclude my valuing it intrinsically? Why can't
having a desire to protect it from harm, without thinking about how useful it might be for some
instrumental end, be a proper evaluative stance for me to take? And why can't this instance of
50
I also discuss this issue in section VIII of chapter one.
33
valuing it in that way be a way of intrinsically valuing it? After all I don't find myself valuing the
sculpture because it is instrumentally useful (although it is so). Rather I just find it reasonable to
care about it without any concern for how extrinsically valuable it might be. In other words, just
because something only has extrinsic value that should not mean that it cannot be valued
intrinsically which makes no reference to its extrinsic value to the valuer."
51
This view is also consistent with what Katie McShane has to say regarding the reasons
why it is appropriate from some person to care for somethings extrinsically and inappropriate for
them to care for other things in this same sense. She writes,
"...the distinction between intrinsic and extrinsic valuation plays an important role
in ethics, and rightly so. We think that some things should be valued intrinsically
[my emphasis] and other things should be valued extrinsically. While these
judgments will usually be context dependent, they are nonetheless very important
in our thinking about what to do and how to feel. For an example, consider the
case of Ebeneezer Scrooge, the character from Charles Dickens’ A Christmas
Carol.
52
What was Scrooge’s moral mistake? His mistake was that he valued
money intrinsically and he valued people extrinsically (instrumentally, in fact).
53
51
Not all things that a person intrinsically values should be cared about in the same way.
McShane illustrates this when she writes,
"...the way it is appropriate to treat the proper objects of different kinds of intrinsic valuation are
quite different. Consider the difference between the ways that it is appropriate to treat the proper
objects of awe, on the one hand, and the proper objects of love, on the other hand. You might
want to say that both the Mona Lisa and your daughter have intrinsic value, the artwork because
it is the appropriate object of awe and the child because she is the appropriate object of love. But
the ways that it is appropriate to treat them will be quite different. It might be appropriate to put
the Mona Lisa in a big plastic cage to protect it from flashbulbs and treat it with various
chemicals in order to ensure that it changes as little as possible over time. But to lock your
daughter away and carefully control the environment in an attempt to prevent her from changing
in any way would be terrible. You should nurture her, help her to develop and change over time,
and try to make it so that she changes in good ways rather than bad ones. But taking this strategy
of benevolent improvement with the Mona Lisa would be a disaster. The Mona Lisa probably
would look better in a nice hat, but you should not add one, even if the hat would constitute an
aesthetic improvement." (McShane 2007, p. 56)
52
McShane enters the following footnote here: See Charles Dickens, A Christmas Carol
(Peterborough, Ontario: Broadview Press, 2003).
53
McShane enters the following footnote here: That Scrooge is unfriendly and a miser is well
known, but the text also provides glimpses of his attitudes toward human relationships in
34
He got it backwards. People are supposed to be valued intrinsically and money is
supposed to be valued extrinsically. In fact, that is the whole point of the morality
taleand it has a happy ending because Scrooge finally figures out his mistake
and gets it right. But Scrooge is not that uncommon: many of our morality tales
are about people who care about the wrong things in the wrong ways and how
they do or do not fix this mistake." (McShane, 2007, p. 53)
So, in order to further clarify what the notion of to ‘care about’ should mean for a
biocentric conception of inherent worth I offer the following clarification to the above definition
of inherent worth:
Second clarified definition of Inherent Worth (IW2): The value that a thing has
in virtue of,
a) having interests and
b) where such interests provide a reason why all moral agents ought to non-
instrumentally care about the thing that has such interests.
Let us refer to clause “a” as the “interests clause”. This clause is satisfied by the presence
of the conditions needed for an entity to have interests.
54
Clause “b” is what I will call the
“moral considerability clause”. This clause is satisfied whenever the interests identified in the
first clause also provide reasons for why all moral agents ought to non-instrumentally care about
the thing that has those interests.
55
That is, clause b, identifies morally considerable interests.
For the purposes of this dissertation I will use this definition of inherent worth (IW2) as a
means of capturing an important sense, or variety of intrinsic value that is of interest to
biocentric individualists. I will also regard the “is” clause of inherent worth (clause a) to be
synonymous with objectively true statements about living organisms that demonstrate that they
have interests.
general: “‘Why did you get married?’ said Scrooge. ‘Because I fell in love.’ ‘Because you fell in
love!’ growled Scrooge, as if that were the only thing in the world more ridiculous than a merry
Christmas” (ibid., p. 43).
54
The question of precisely what these conditions are (or should be) will be addressed in the
next chapter.
55
In the next chapter I argue that the minimal condition of intrinsically valuing a thing is that of
its “moral standing”. If something has moral standing then it at least has minimal intrinsic value.
35
IX. "From where does such value come?"
So, what actually is it about individual living organisms that grounds their inherent
worth, makes them worth protecting and demands our ethical consideration? Many of us may
have an intuition or feel as if plants, animals and other nonhumans simply have some kind of
moral standing, but the grounding for an environmental ethic must surely do more than that. Can
environmentalists ground their claims of the value of living organisms by some objective
feature(s) that they possess? Given that this dissertation is confined to the arguments for
biocentric individualism
56
that also rely on a definition of inherent worth, there is a rather
straightforward answer to the question “From where does the value of individual living
organisms come?”. The answer is that individual living organisms have inherent worth because
they have interests and those interests provide a reason for why moral agents ought to non-
instrumentally care about them.
But how does one go about showing that something has inherent worth? According to the
definition of inherent worth above one needs to show two things in order to support that claim.
The first is that it must be shown that all living organisms have interests.
The second is that it must be shown that the identified interests that belong to all living
things have some quality about them that provide moral agents with a reason to non-
instrumentally care about all living things. To put it another way if all living organisms have
inherent worth, then that means that they all have interests that provide a reason for why any
moral agent should care about them non-instrumentally.
56
However, I do advance some further considerations for the moral standing of ecosystems and
species in this dissertation.
36
X. The Aim of this Dissertation
A proper analysis of the biocentric individualist’s ethical project should take into account
the concept of interests. These interests are an important factor in many arguments in support of
the general claim that all living organisms have inherent worth. The basic reasoning behind these
interest-based arguments goes something like this,
1) Anything that is capable of being harmed or benefited has interests.
2) Many, if not all, living organisms are capable of being harmed or benefited.
3) Thus, many, if not all living organisms have interests.
4) Beings that have interests are ones that ought to be non-instrumentally cared
about.
5) Thus, many, if not all living organisms have inherent worth.
Beginning with chapter two I will describe Gary Varner's view that etiology plays an
important role in whether a living thing has interests. An etiology is a causal history of some
kind put forward as an explanation for how something came about. Etiological accounts of
interests attempt to show that the causal history of a thing is relevant to whether it has interests. I
will discuss Gary Varner's evolutionary, or natural selection, etiological account of biological
interests. This account claims that all naturally-selected, living things are morally considerable
because they have interests. This account also claims that artifacts are not morally considerable
because they were not produced by the process of evolution by natural selection. Varner argues
that only biological organisms have morally considerable interests because those interests are
“biological” meaning that their biological functions are proper functions that arose via a process
of natural selection. All manipulated forms of life, including other complex designed
contrivances, do not have structures that perform biological functions hence they do not have
interests. On this understanding a living thing’s interests are morally considerable if its
functional structures were brought about by an evolutionary, natural selection etiology. Non-
37
biological interests, such as those that arose via a process of artificial selection or design, are not
morally considerable because those interests did not arise in the context of that etiology.
In chapter two I also provide an overview of all of the relevant etiologies that a
biocentrist could appeal to in order to construct an etiological account of interests for all living
things. These etiologies are a natural selection etiology, an "Instant Organism" etiology, an
agent-selection, non-teleological etiology and a design etiology. I will argue that under Varner's
account some of the identified interests are not in the interests of the individual organism. I will
argue that the process of natural selection is incapable of showing that all "proper functions" are
of interest to individual living organisms. There are many cases in which a proper function
generated by a natural selection etiology is not in the individual organism’s interests to have.
That is, even if one were to grant that evolutionary etiological accounts are able to identify
"proper functions", there is no guarantee that those functions are actually what represent the
organism’s own good. As such Varner's account is unsuccessful in accounting for the inherent
worth of all individual living things.
In chapter three I discuss a non-etiological account of interests advanced by Craig
Delancey. This account, known as a "systems-based" account, claims that living things have
interests by recourse to the kind of internal organization that they have as self-regulating beings.
On this view living things have interests that are independent of their etiology. I will argue that
while this account is successful at identifying the existence of interests for all living things it is
unsuccessful at identifying the existence of morally considerable interests for all living things. In
this chapter I will also challenge the basic claim made by Varner that having interests means
having morally considerable interests. Insights from the system's based account, a non-
etiological account of interests, show that living things produced by any etiology whatsoever will
38
have interests. But this account also shows that some artificial things might likewise be regarded
as having interests.
For instance, artificially-produced forms of life possess just as many interests and life
functions as their natural counterparts do. How they came about is irrelevant to whether they
have interests. The systems-based account also leaves open the possibility that some non-
biological entities such as sophisticated robots can have interests as well. The system's based
account implies that while biological organisms have interests it is not true that they are the only
things that can have interests. This is a problem for the biocentrist who wishes to keep
artificially-produced organisms and other complex, designed entities that are not “alive” in the
traditional sense, outside of the scope of moral standing.
Some biocentrists think that artificially-produced entities cannot have interests or be
morally considerable because they are not "natural". But the claim that naturalness grounds the
moral standing of a thing has its own problems. I will argue that there are good reasons to think
that naturalness, as opposed to artificiality, is not a good-making property, particularly when it
comes to the moral status of interests. An artificially-produced entity can have interests in the
same sort of way that a naturally-produced one can. Hence, any supposed moral difference
between an artificially-produced entity, whether biological or not, and a similar naturally-
produced entity cannot be based on whether they have interests.
In chapter four I argue that while it is true that all living things can be identified as having
interests (because they all have teleofunctional interests) under a non-etiological, "systems-
based" view, that account of interests cannot provide guidance on why those interests should be
regarded as ones that provide them with direct moral standing. I then consider the question of
whether an organism's etiology could make a difference to whether its interests are morally
39
considerable in the sense of providing it with direct moral standing. I argue that while rational
agents and sentient beings have interests that provide them with direct moral standing regardless
of their etiology, non-sentient living things do not have interests that provide them with direct
moral. I then inquire into whether an agent-selection, non-teleological etiology, an instant
organism etiology or a natural selection etiology could be capable of bringing about non-sentient
living things that have interests that provide them direct moral standing. I argue that these
etiologies cannot produce non-sentient living things that have interests that give them direct
moral standing.
At the end of chapter four I argue that all non-sentient, living things regardless of their
etiology cannot have direct moral standing. This means that some form of indirect moral
standing is the only available option left for the biocentrist hoping to argue on behalf of the
protection of all non-sentient living things. I then inquire into whether all non-sentient living
things could be guaranteed to have indirect moral standing. I argue that a natural selection
etiology is unable to guarantee indirect moral standing for all non-sentient living things brought
about by that etiology.
In chapter five I will consider the question of whether a design etiology could guarantee
indirect moral standing for all non-sentient living things produced by that etiology. I argue that
all non-sentient living things if designed would be guaranteed to have indirect moral standing in
that there would exist a reason not to harm those beings independently of human preferences or
interests in them.
40
CHAPTER TWO
A Natural Selection Etiological Account of Biological Interests
In the previous chapter I attempted to highlight the basic grounds that biocentrists appeal
to in their argument for the claim that all living things have inherent worth. Many of them think
that anything that has interests also has inherent worth. At is claimed that since all living things
have interests that automatically provides reason to think that all living things should be cared
about non-instrumentally.
57
Some biocentrists think that the fact that all living things have
interests automatically provide a reason for why they are, or at least should be, morally
considerable. But, as I mentioned in the previous chapter, I will not assume that having interests
automatically provides such a reason.
In the first section of this chapter I will provide some further background information
relevant to this kind of basic biocentrist’s arguments in favor of the inherent worth of all
individual living things.
In the second section I will provide a discussion and critique of Gary Varner’s natural
selection etiological account of interests which makes particular reference to the concept of
“biological interests” as providing a reason to think that all living things have moral
considerability.
58
In the third section, I will provide some background information relevant to the
57
The “reasons” here are meant to indicate reasons that are available to valuing agents that can
be responsive to the reasons given. For example, there cannot be a “reasons for” a cat to value
other cats in and of themselves because cats (and all other non-rational beings) cannot be
responsive to those reasons. The “reasons for” are reasons for valuing agents to consider and be
appropriately responsive to.
58
As I mentioned previously in chapter one, whenever I use the term “moral considerability” I
mean that living things that have such considerability are things that ought to be cared about non-
instrumentally. Also, the term "morally considerable interests" refers to interests that provide a
reason for why someone should care about the possessor of those interests non-instrumentally.
41
development of Varner’s etiological view and why Varner invokes etiology as being important to
the existence of morally considerable interests. Varner argues that only organisms that have a
natural selection etiology can have biological functions which makes them candidates for interest
possession.
In the fourth section, I provide an overview of all of the relevant etiologies that could be
invoked to explain the existence of living things and their interests. These etiologies are 1) a
natural selection etiology, 2) an agent-selection, non-teleological etiology, 3) an "instant
organism" etiology, and 4) a design etiology.
In the fifth section I will provide some background information on what a non-etiological
account of interest is and what sets it apart from etiological accounts of interests.
In the sixth section, I explain Graig Delancey's criticism of Varner’s etiological approach
and why he thinks that it is not adequate to account for the existence of interests for all living
things. In light of these criticisms, and some of my own, I will argue that biocentrists should
abandon Varner's approach and seek an alternative account of interests.
In the seventh, and final, section I provide a conclusion along with some background
information relevant to the development of a non-etiological view of interests known as the
"systems-based" account of interests.
I. Background Information Relevant to Biocentric Individualism
I will now provide some background information pertinent to the development of the
biocentrist’s argument in support of the view that all living things have interests. As previously
mentioned, many biocentrists claim that all living things are valuable in and of themselves
because they have interests.
42
Others, however, are not convinced that all living organisms have interests. They think
that only sentient forms of life are capable of having interests.
For instance Tom Regan highlights what he calls the “interests argument”.
59
This
argument attempts to show that not all forms of life, especially non-sentient forms, are worthy of
ethical or moral consideration because they do not have interests. The argument goes something
like this:
(1) The only beings which can have moral standing are those beings which can
have interests.
(2) The only beings which can have interests are those which have the capacity
for consciousness.
(3) Therefore, the only beings which can have moral standing are those which
have the capacity for consciousness. (Regan, 1981, p. 21).
This argument, according to Regan,
"…exploits an ambiguity in the concept of something having interests. To speak
of A's interests in X might mean either (a) that A is interested in (wants, desires,
hopes for, cares about, etc.) x, or (b) that X is in A's interest (that X will
contribute to A's good, or well-being, or welfare). Clearly if the only beings
which can have moral standing are those which can be interested in things (have
desires, wants, etc.), then only conscious beings can have moral standing...If, on
the other hand, we mean beings which can be benefited or harmed by what is
given or denied them, then it is an open question whether the class of beings
which can have moral standing is coextensive with the class of beings having the
capacity for consciousness." (Regan, 1981, p. 21-22).
Biocentrists attempt to diffuse the “interests argument” by showing that premise two of
the argument is false. One way to do that is to show that having interests is not a privilege
reserved only for conscious beings and that having an interest in X is not coextensive with taking
an interest in X.
60
All living organisms, whether conscious or not, have interests by the fact that
59
Regan highlights this argument in order to refute it. He does not endorse the interests
argument.
60
I have previously mentioned that traditional anthropocentrism does not regard the interests of
non-humans, whether conscious or unconscious, to be of intrinsic moral concern. However,
Anderson-Gold (2003) has argued that anthropocentrism can be ‘reconstituted’ into an
43
they can be helped or harmed. They have various needs
61
and pursuits that can either be
furthered or thwarted.
Various biocentric ethical theories have made use of the basic argument that all living
organisms have interests as evidenced by the fact that they all "pursue" in some sense those
things that are good for them. Most notably living things have an interest in whatever allows
them to maintain their own biological integrity and well-being. Whatever contributes to a living
thing's well-being is what it "tries" to bring about.
62
So for example, a bacterium has an interest
in finding enough nutrients in its environment. Bacteria routinely "seek out" sources of nutrients.
If a bacterium cannot get nutrients it is harmed. If it can get nutrients then it is benefited in some
way. Nutrients contribute to its biological integrity and this is enough to show that it has
interests.
There are several examples of biocentric ethical theories that rely on the notion of interest
possession as a justification for the moral considerability of not just some but of all living things.
environmentally-friendly ethic. She argues that the human perspective is ‘ineliminable’ to any
ethic simply because all ethics aims to prescribe and guide human action. Hence, the
anthropocentric point of view simply cannot be taken away. But this does not mean that
anthropocentrism must only be aimed at human interests. It only means that a human perspective
is necessary in knowing what our moral obligations to the environment are. Instead, reconstituted
anthropocentrism maintains that nonhumans have an objective “good of their own” that we as
humans can come to know and understand from our own uniquely human perspective. On this
basis it is objectively wrong to think that only humans and their interests are morally considerable.
According to Anderson-Gold, “This ‘objective knowledge’ may include changes in our
understanding of the capacities of non-human animals, the functioning of natural systems, and
even our more general model of nature.” (pp. 114-115). Hence, this version on anthropocentrism
is decidedly different in kind from the traditional or classic understanding of ethical
anthropocentrism.
61
This, of course, is separate from what a living thing may want. The needs of an organism are
to be understood here as being purely biological and objective. Consequently, biological interests
are based on what a living thing objectively needs independently of whatever mental states such
as wants, desires, longings. etc. that living thing may or may not have.
62
In section IX of chapter four I argue that non-sentient living beings actually do not have goals
or a "good of their own" per se.
44
As Hans-Jürgen Link describes it, these theories,
“rel[y] on the observation that living beings appear to aspire to an inherent end;
after all, even biologists seem to give a functional description of life. Plants, for
example, grow, seek nutrition and reproduce. In an Aristotelian diction, organisms
give the impression of being directed towards a telos…Even if less complex life
forms do not have experiences, it is argued, to compromise a living organism is
contrary to its ‘interests’ and therefore morally wrong since it is not appropriate to
its natural telos” (Link, 2013, p. 439).
Likewise, Gary Varner writes that “…I believe that the strongest reason for pursuing the
environmentalist agenda will be based, ultimately, on the satisfaction of interests.” (Varner,
2001, p. 7). So interests and the satisfaction of interests feature prominently in arguments in
support of an environmental ethic and in particular a biocentric one.
63
At first glance many people might find an ethical position of biocentrism to be
implausible. For instance, a biocentrist might try to argue that a swamp privet (an invasive plant)
has interests and so on that basis never deserves to be killed. But someone could reasonably
argue that the action of killing that plant is not morally wrong especially if that plant is
interfering with the flourishing of other plants or wildlife or is harming one’s own property.
Initially many people might think that if this is what biocentrism amounts to then it is simply
implausible. Many would not be willing to say that they think that a plant matters just as much,
ethically speaking, as a dog or another human being.
But a biocentrist herself need not embrace such a view. All that a biocentrist has to
endorse is the claim that all living things have some moral standing. Dealing with value conflicts
or cases of competing interests would be another matter. Biocentrists that point to the existence
of interests are only trying to argue that their having such interests give some reason for why
63
This is, of course, not to say that interests and the satisfaction of interests are the only support
for an environmental ethic.
45
they should be valued non-instrumentally, in and of themselves.
Biocentric individualists argue that the existence of these kinds of interests, interests in
meeting basic requirements for biological flourishing or well-being, are what make all living
things morally considerable. A mouse, for example, has an interest in drinking water. And since
it has that interest it would be wrong to deprive that mouse of water. The reason why it is wrong
to interfere with such biological goals is because such interference is harmful to it. So in the case
of drinking water a mouse should be left free to pursue that interest all else being equal.
Interests can also be connected to other interests. For instance, a blue jay can have an
interest in flying as a means of catching food and if it does have that interest then it also will
have a related interest in its wings functioning properly. If we consider the blue jay’s interest in
its wings functioning correctly and if flight is something that is good for the bird then, says the
biocentrist, it looks like stopping or interfering with the blue jay’s attempts at flight or damaging
its wings would be wrong because such interference is harmful or detrimental to the bird. If
having interests makes living things morally considerable then interfering with the satisfaction of
their interests causes them to be harmed. Such beings cannot properly function or flourish unless
they are left free to pursue their interests in which case the functions of their structures are
allowed to occur.
But sentient organisms like blue jays and human beings are not the only beings that can
have interests according to the biocentrist. Non-sentient forms of life such as plants have
interests too. For example, an oak tree has an interest in obtaining sunlight. It has leaves that
contain chlorophyll which enable it to absorb the sunlight necessary for its own growth. One of
the ways in which we can know that plants have such an interest is by observing its growth. A
plant’s interest in acquiring sunlight is evidenced by its behavioral tendencies to move toward
46
sunlight. Plants in general direct their own growth towards sources of light under various
conditions. Plants exhibit a "goal-directed" behavior in response to its need for sunlight. This
indicates that the plant has an interest in acquiring sunlight. If the plant were moved away from
the light or covered so that it could not get light the plant would be harmed. Its leaves would fall
off and its growth would be stunted. The plant thus has an interest in obtaining sunlight and it
also has an interest in its leaves working properly to harness that light. So, argues the biocentrist,
interfering with this biological end for no good reason would be ethically wrong too.
64
II. Gary Varner’s Natural Selection Etiological Account of Interests
Gary Varner has commented on the proposition that goal-directed behavior indicates that
a thing has interests. All living things have what he calls “biological interests”. A biological
interest, according to Varner, is an interest in some biological process taking place or in some
biological structure performing a vital function.
For Varner, all biological interests are morally considerable. For instance, a butterfly has
a biological interest in locating sources of nectar, but it also (presumably) has a biological
interest in its proboscis working properly so that nectar can be efficiently extracted from flowers.
All living things have biological interests. And since they do they are all morally considerable.
But conscious living things have additional interests besides biological interests. These
interests are what Varner calls “preference interests”. A preference interest is a psychological
preference or desire that a conscious, living organism can have for certain things. Non-sentient
64
This argument would apply to all living things. Even the simplest forms of life such as bacteria
have interests. An H. pylori bacterium, for example, has an interest in acquiring nutrients from its
environment. Acquiring nutrients is good for the bacterium’s welfare. Hence, interfering with that
bacterium’s interests is prima facie wrong.
47
forms of life, on the other hand, have biological interests but not preference interests.
65
They do
not have psychological states such as desires or preferences. As Varner writes,
“…I offer two general clarifying remarks. First, since [my] burden…is to explain
how non-conscious beings such as plants can have interests, and since our
paradigm of an interest involves the endeavors of conscious beings, it is useful to
introduce a terminological distinction between those interests that do involve
consciousness in some and those that do not. Tom Regan marks this difference by
distinguishing between conscious “preference interests” on the one hand, and
“welfare interests” on the other. Although I use Regan’s term for the former, I
instead call the latter biological interests. My reason is that “welfare” suggests too
strongly something like the integrated satisfaction of all an individual’s interests,
and when I say that “A has a biological interest in X” I mean only that X is in one
of A’s interests, that X would be good for A in some respect or other, rather than
that X would be best for A, all things considered.” (Varner, 1990, p. 254).
66
Varner argues that goal-directed behaviors or tendencies are not strictly reserved for
living organisms. He acknowledges that artifacts could exhibit these behaviors and tendencies as
well.
67
But that leaves open the suggestion that artifacts could possibly have goal-directed
behaviors and interests too and thus would be objects of moral considerability. Varner writes,
“…if we are going to attribute interests to plants on the grounds that they exhibit
goal-directed behavior, then by the same token we will have to assign an interest
in regulating temperature to a home heating system, and to do so would constitute
a reductio ad absurdum of the proposal…Since simple artifacts clearly have
needs in certain senses of the word, two things will have to be established before
we can understand how the fact that plants needs suffices to show that they have
interests. The first is an empirical claim:
The empirical claim: plants have needs in some sense in which artifacts do not.
The second is a normative claim:
The normative claim: this difference qualifies plants, but not artifacts, for direct
65
We could, however, image a case of angels or disembodied spirits that have neither ancestors
nor any sort of biological interests but who could still have other interests based on their desires
for certain things. These beings would have preference interests but not biological interests. Plants,
on the other hand, have biological interests but not preference interests (since they are
nonconscious).
66
From this point on I will use the term “biological interests” to denote those interests that all
living things have whether sentient or not.
67
I will address the subject of whether artifacts can have interests in a section III of this chapter
three.
48
moral consideration” (Varner, 1990, p. 251).
Varner thinks that only living entities, not artifacts, have interests.
68
Hence, all living
things are morally considerable but all artifacts are not.
Varner tackles this problem by arguing that artifacts do not have interests. He argues that
there are some empirical facts about plants which demonstrate that they have interests and other
empirical facts about artifacts which show that they do not have interests. He does this by way of
establishing criteria for interest possession that rule out artifacts as interest possessors.
According to Varner, if something possesses a structure with a biological function
69
,
then that thing also has a biological interest
70
in that structures performing that function. Varner
makes the connection between the fulfillment of biological functions and with what is in the
biological interests of living things by means of the following argument. He writes,
“if the fulfillment of the biological function (what Millikan means by proper
function) of our subsystems is in our interest irrespective of our being capable of
consciously taking an interest in their fulfillment, would not the fulfillment of
those functions in plants be in their interest, even though they are incapable of
taking an interest in them? That is the best available argument for the expansive
conception of moral standing [my emphasis] represented in biocentric
individualism” (Varner, 1998, p. 74).
Varner here is making an analogical argument of sorts. Since the fulfillment of the
biological function of the human heart (pumping blood) is in our interests irrespective of us
taking an interest in it, and since the pumping of blood is good for us, then the fulfillment of the
biological functions of plants is likewise in their interests irrespective of it taking that interest
and thus it is likewise good for them. And since our interest in having properly-oxygenated blood
68
This, of course, assumes that anything that is an artifact cannot also be a living thing.
69
Later in this chapter I will discuss Varner’s use of the term “biological function” and how he
defines it.
70
I will also discuss and critique Varner’s concept “biological interest” in section VI this chapter.
49
is one of the many things that gives us some degree of moral standing, plants should also be
accorded some degree of moral standing too.
Some may find Varner’s argument by analogy to be seriously flawed. For instance,
someone could reasonably think that plants are simply not like human beings in the relevant sorts
of ways that could make their interests morally considerable. It could be argued that the fact that
certain things might be in both the interest of a plant and in the interest of a human being does
nothing to show that there is also an ethical dimension to the plant's interests. For purposes of the
discussion I will assume that it is true that both sentient and non-sentient forms of life have
interests. What I want to explore is Varner’s claim that the above analogy warrants, in his words,
“the expansive conception of moral standing represented in biocentric individualism” which is
that the existence of biological interests for all living things makes it the case that all living
things are morally considerable.
As I alluded to previously, this “expansive conception” need not entail the view that all
living things must never be harmed or killed or that all living things have the same degree of
moral standing. Instead I will take it that the biocentrist must at least be committed to the
proposition that all living things have some kind of minimal moral standing based on their
possession of interests such that all things being equal they should not be harmed or killed but
should instead be valued in and of themselves to some degree.
With the above considerations in mind, I think a further note of caution is in order.
Varner works on the assumption that having interests is a sufficient condition for moral standing.
He thinks that if something has interests then that thing is morally considerable. He writes, “To
say that a being has interests is to say that it has a welfare, or a good of its own, that matters from
the moral point of view.” (Varner, 1998, p.6). Elsewhere Varner writes, “As I am using the
50
term…an interest is, by definition, morally significant.”
71
(Varner, 1998, p. 77).
72
I, unlike
Varner, will argue in this chapter that having interests does not always or necessarily entail
having morally considerable interests. More precisely, having interests does not entail the claim
that all possessors of interests should be valued intrinsically or in and of themselves.
73
More
needs to be said about the kinds of interests in question and why we should think that those
interests give any moral agent a reason to value the possessor of the identified interests in and of
itself.
III. The Importance of Etiology to Varner’s View
Varner’s criteria of biological functions were partially-inspired by Larry Wright’s
teleological explanation of function
74
.
71
Varner here suggests that interests themselves are morally significant and that (presumably)
possessors of interests are morally significant in light of that fact. Most biocentrists believe that
possessors of interests are morally significant. But some of them may either be agnostic or actually
oppose the view that interests themselves are morally significant. I will work on the assumption
that the biocentrist would at least accept the latter position without necessarily having to accept
the former. Whether the biocentrist thinks that interests per se are morally significant is a subject
I will set aside for the purposes of this dissertation. Also, in light of the clarified definition of
inherent worth, I will assume that if something is to have inherent worth it must possess an interest
that also provides a reason for why the thing that possesses it should be valued in and of itself.
72
Premise one of Regan’s above argument, however, claims that having interests is not a
sufficient condition but is instead a necessary condition for a thing to have moral standing. Varner
does not address this aspect of Regan’s argument. I will set this point aside for the purposes of this
dissertation.
73
In this chapter I will attempt to show that having biological interests, in Varner’s sense of the
term, is not a sufficient condition for the claim that satisfaction of such interests brings about what
is good for individual living things. If a thing has biological interests it does not mean that those
interests are morally considerable. Various counterexamples will show that it is possible for a
living thing to have a biological interest in some state of affairs and yet that interest not be a
compelling reason for why its possessor should be valued in and of itself.
74
See Larry Wright’s book Teleological Explanations: An Etiological Analysis of Goals and
Functions, 1976, University of California Press.
51
Varner, however, thinks that there is a serious problem with Wright's criteria of function.
According to Varner, Wright's criteria of function could be used to attribute functional purposes
or goals to the structures of artifacts. But, argues Varner, Wright's criteria should not be used as
means of identifying functional interests.
Wright’s criteria of functions are etiological. That is, they are ones that refer to the causal
history of a function in question.
75
Wright’s criteria of functions claims that:
The function of X is Z if and only if:
(i) Z is a consequence (result) of X’s being there,
(ii) X is there because it does (results in) Z.
Biocentrists think that the fact that biological structures have functions is important for
biocentric accounts of interests for the following reason. All living things seem to be comprised
of various structures that have functional purposes, the functions that those structures are for.
The heart, for example, has the functional purpose of pumping blood. The pumping of blood is
what the heart is for. The pumping of blood is vital to the good of the organism that has that
heart. If the organism's heart were not able perform its functional purpose we would say that the
heart is malfunctioning. A malfunctioning heart is not good for the life of the organism. The
organism thus has an interest in its heart performing its functional purpose.
There are other functions that structures can perform but that are not the functional
purposes of those structures. The heart, for instance, does not have the functional purpose of
making its characteristic "thumpa-thumpa" sound. This is a function that the heart performs but it
is not its functional purpose. The heart does not have the function of making that "thumpa-
75
See also page 71 of Christopher Boorse’s “Wright on Functions” in The Philosophical Review,
LXXXV: 70-86.
52
thumpa" sound. Performances of making the "thumpa-thumpa" are not vital to its well-being at
all. Hence an organism does not have an interest in its heart making the "thumpa-thumpa" sound.
Varner argues that if the biocentrist were to apply Wright’s above criteria of function, to
an etiological account of interests it would turn out that many human-designed artifacts, as well
as all living things, would have interests. Thus, both artifacts and living organisms would be
morally considerable. But Varner think that artifacts do not have interests. Hence, he thinks that
Wright's criteria of function should be amended in some way.
For example, Varner might argue that under Wright’s criteria of function that both cars
and elephants could be said to have parts or subsystems that have a function. According to the
Wright criteria the function of a car battery is to supply power to the car if and only if the power
being supplied to the car is a result of the car battery being there and the car battery is there
because it supplies power to the car.
76
Similarly, the function of the elephant’s trunk is to siphon
water if and only if the siphoning of water is a result of the elephant’s trunk being where it is and
the elephant’s trunk is where it is because it siphons water.
77
On that basis it looks like both cars and elephants have structures with functional
purpose. Hence, they both have interests in their structures performing their functional purposes.
Hence, they both are morally considerable.
76
Note that the clause “the car battery is there because it supplies power to the car” could be
rewritten as a longer causal sequence that employs more immediate causal factors to explain in
greater detail just why the car’s battery is there. For example: “The battery is there because a
designer put the battery there and the designer put the battery there because that seemed to be the
best location for it and it seems to be the best location for it (immediately) because the battery
supplies power to the car’s engine.”
77
We could construct a similar, more-detailed explanation of what it means to say “the elephant’s
trunk is there because it siphons water”. We could rewrite that clause to say, “The elephant’s trunk
is there because it was adaptive to the elephant’s ancestors and it was adaptive to the elephant’s
ancestors because it allowed those ancestors to have sufficient hydration and it allowed them to
have sufficient hydration because it siphons water.”
53
Clause ii of Wright’s criteria is known as the ‘etiology clause’ in that it attempts to give
some kind of historical, causal explanation for why a structure is where it is. This particular
clause, however, does not distinguish functions brought about by designers and their intentions
and functions brought about by non-teleological processes like natural selection. It merely states
that some structure X is there because it performs some function Z. Since clause ii applies
equally to the function of a car battery (an object produced by a teleological process of human
design) and to the function of an elephant’s trunk (an object produced by the non-teleological
process of natural selection) a distinction between human-designed functions and naturally-
selected functions cannot be made. And since no etiological distinction between those functions
can be made, the biocentrist would have to regard artifact functions to be of the same kind as
those of living things. As Christopher Boorse writes, “one would assume that regardless of
whether organisms or artifacts are in question, any ordinary sort of etiological explanation of X
by X’s effects will support a function statement” (Boorse, 1976, p.71).
Wright’s criteria, of course, will not help Varner in distinguishing artifacts from living
things. In order to avoid the implication that both biological structures and designed structures
could have functional purposes that the things have interests in, Varner provides a further
explanation of what clause ii of Wright’s criteria could mean so that the functions of living
things can be distinguished from the functions of designed artifacts. He claims that the functions
of living things are only produced by a process of natural selection.
78
He writes, “One thing that
78
Natural selection, however, should not be regarded as a teleological process. A teleological
process is one that is goal-directed in some way with specific aims, purposes or ends. For example,
car batteries are produced by a teleological process in which the battery’s designer built it to
achieve a particular functional end. Non-teleological processes, on the other hand, are unguided
and do not involve any forethought or planning. Natural selection is regarded by many scientists
and philosophers to be non-teleological. Ernst Mayr, one of the leading voices in evolutionary
biology, holds such a view. He writes,
54
distinguishes organisms from artifacts is that the former but not the latter are the result of natural
selection.” (Varner, 1998, p. 69). On this view a structure has a biological function only if it
came about by natural selection.
Here Varner makes an etiological distinction between the functions of artifacts on the one
hand and the functions of organisms on the other by appeals to what he calls the ‘biological
theory of welfare’. According to this theory things with biological functions also have biological
interests in those functions being performed. This is illustrated in the third part of his theory of
interests. Varner writes,
“…an individual A has an interest in X if and only if
(1) A actually desires X,
(2) A would desire X if A were adequately informed and impartial across all
phases of A’s life, or
(3) X would fulfill some biological function of some organ or subsystem of A,
where X is a biological function of S [an organ or subsystem] in A if and only
if
(a) X is a consequence of A’s having S and
(b) A has S because achieving X was adaptive for A’s ancestors” (Varner, 1998, p.
68).
Parts 1 and 2 of this account of interest possession covers cases of desire interests or
“[Natural] selection is not teleological (goal-directed)...[Natural selection eliminates unfit
mutants without regard to end goals] Selection does not have a long-term goal. It is a
process repeated anew in every generation. The frequency of extinction of evolutionary
lineages, as well as their frequent changes in direction, is inconsistent with the mistaken
claim that selection is a teleological process” (Mayr, 2001, p. 121).
Also Jerry Coyne, another prominent figure in evolutionary biology writes,
“…to the best of our knowledge evolution, like all natural processes, is purposeless and
unguided. After all, scientists have no problem saying that the melting of glaciers, the
movement of tectonic plates, or the decay of atoms are processes that are unguided and
purposeless...There seems to be no direction, mutations are random, and we haven’t
detected a teleological force or agent that pushes it in one direction. And it’s important to
realize this: the great importance of Darwin’s theory of natural selection is that an
unguided, purposeless process can nevertheless produce animals and plants that are
exquisitely adapted to their environment. That’s why it’s called natural selection, not
supernatural selection or simply selection” (Coyne, 2012, p.1).
55
preference interests that rely on sentience or consciousness. But the instrumental criterion for
separating artifacts from living organisms is found in clause 3b. This criterion claims that
artifacts do not have interests (whether biological or not) but that plants do because plants have
biological functions whereas artifacts do not. Sub-clauses a and b jointly attempt to define what a
biological function is. Since biological functions only belong to structures found within naturally
evolved, living things and since all living things have those structures because they were
adaptive for their prior ancestors, artifacts, which do not have a causal history involving
ancestors, do not have biological functions. Craig Delancey reiterates this point when he writes,
“Contemporary artifacts arguably do not have ancestors and so they fail to satisfy condition (3b)”
(Delancey, 2004, p. 176).
79
Since artifacts do not fulfill this condition, they do not have
biological functions. And since they do not have biological functions they also do not have
biological interests. Thus, biological functions can be separated from artifact functions on the
basis of differences in their etiology.
80
Varner gets his notion of biological function from Ruth Millikan’s etiological explanation
of “proper function”. In her paper “In Defense of Proper Functions” Millikan argues that a
natural selection account for the adaptedness of a structure is what identifies the functional
purpose or “proper function” of that structure.
81
Thus, she endorses a view of proper function
79
The use of the term ‘ancestor’ here is meant to denote a biological ancestor, one that is tied to
a thing’s descendants via a process of genetic reproduction of some kind. We may speak of artifacts
having certain ‘ancestorshowever it should be recognized that such usage is metaphorical. For
instance, we might say that the 1967 Corvette was the ‘ancestor’ to the 1968 Corvette. But all this
means is that the 1967 Corvette contained some feature(s) that were retained by the 1968. It doesn’t
mean that the 1968 was, literally, a genetically-reproduced descendent of the 1967.
80
An “etiology” is simply a causal story that explains how some structure or feature came into
existence.
81
Proper functions of biological structures are claimed to be the “purposes” of those structures.
As Millikan writes, “...the things that have “proper functions” do seem to coincide with things
56
that is etiological. Millikan’s defines a proper function in the following way:
“It does not seem to be so much the details of the definition of "proper function"
that need defense as its basic form or general plan, which looks to the history of
an item to determine its function [my emphasis] rather than to the item's present
properties or dispositions. At any rate, it is this historical turn in the definition that
I propose to defend...The definition of “proper function” is recursive. Putting
things very roughly, for an item A to have a function F as a "proper function", it is
necessary (and close to sufficient) that one of these two conditions should hold.
(1) A originated as a "reproduction" (to give one example, as a copy, or a copy of
a copy) of some prior item or items that, due [her emphasis] in part to possession
of the properties reproduced, have actually performed F in the past, and A exists
because (causally historically because) of this or these performances. (2) A
originated as the product of some prior device
82
that, given, its circumstances,
had performance of F as a proper function and that, under those circumstances,
normally causes F to be performed by means [her emphasis] of producing an item
like A. Items that fall under condition (2) have "derived proper functions",
functions derived from the functions of the devices that produce them. Because
the producing devices sometimes labor under conditions not normal for proper
performance of their functions, devices with derived proper functions do not
always have normal structure, hence are not always capable of performing their
proper functions-a fact, I claim, that is of considerable importance. (Millikan,
1989, p. 288).
Varner applies the first part of Millikan’s definition of proper function to identify the
functional purposes of biological structures. Because of this I will set aside discussion of whether
the second condition also pertains to the proper functions of biological structures. Items of
designed contrivance as well as biological structures can have proper functions under the first
condition of Millikan’s above definition. In a later chapter, I will address the subject of artifact
proper functions in the context of condition (1) of Millikan’s definition.
(omitting God) that have, in ordinary parlance, “purposes.” (Millikan, 1984, p. 18). Proper
functions are also what others have called “normative functions”. I argue that Millikinian proper
functions are not functional purposes in section VII of chapter four.
82
It is not entirely clear what Millikan means by the term "device" here. She does, however,
claim that one type of device is a "language device" which consists of "words and syntactic
forms" (Millikan, 1989, p. 289). It is not obvious that Millikan thinks that artifacts are likewise
"devices". But most of us would probably think that they are devices.
57
Natural selection etiologists, like Varner and Millikan identify biological functions
83
by
recourse to some undirected, selection etiology, most notably natural selection.
84
Presumably,
those structures that have proper functions acquired their functional purposes by reproduction
and natural selection. So on this view the heart has the proper function of pumping blood
because that heart once pumped blood in the past for one or more ancestors that also had a heart,
and those previous instances of blood pumping aided in the survival and reproduction of those
ancestors. As Jay Odenbaugh writes,
“Consider your heart. It has the function of circulating blood through your body.
That is, this is what it is supposed to do [my emphasis]. It came to have this
function because it was this effect for which it was selected against other heritable
variants. Insofar as your heart does not circulate blood it is malfunctioning. Thus,
one strategy of reducing normativity to natural properties is through evolutionary
biology” (Odenbaugh, 2015, p. 2)
Millikan is credited with providing a definition of proper function that can identify those
functions that a biological structure is “supposed” (in an impersonal or nonpsychological sense)
to perform. She writes, “Having a proper function is a matter of having been ‘designed to’ or
‘supposed to’ (impersonal) perform a certain function. The task of the theory of proper functions
is to define this sense of ‘designed to’ or ‘supposed to’ in naturalist, nonnormative, and
nonmysterious terms.” (Millikan, 1984, p. 17). So, on this understanding, the proper function of
the heart is to pump blood and is “supposed to” pump blood because the heart originated as a
83
Which in this section I will also call “proper functions”.
84
Millikan is not claiming that the existence of a proper function entails the claim that such a
function ought to occur, nor that living organisms have interests in the performances of these
functions, nor that having such functions makes a living thing valuable in and of itself, only that it
is a certain function that a structure was ‘designed to’ or ‘supposed to’ perform. Varner, on the
other hand, makes the ethically normative transition from having a biological function (which is a
proper function) to the goodness or moral standing of the living thing bearing the structure that has
that function by equating the fulfillment of a biological function with what is in a living thing’s
interests.
58
reproduction of some prior structure that, due in part to possession of the properties reproduced,
had actually performed pumping blood in the past. And the heart exists now because of these
past performances. The purposive nature of this function is, as she puts it, defined “in naturalist,
nonnormative” terms.
Ruth Millikan’s definition of proper function is meant then to explain the functional
purpose of a structure, as opposed to those functions that are not proper or accidental. She writes,
“The definition of "proper function" is intended as a theoretical definition of
function or purpose [my emphasis]. It is an attempt to describe a unitary
phenomenon that lies behind all the various sorts of cases in which we ascribe
purposes or functions to things, which phenomenon normally accounts for [her
emphasis] the existence of the various analogies upon which applications of the
notion "purpose" or "function" customarily rest” (Millikan, 1989, p. 293).
Thus, the proper function of an elephant’s trunk is also the purpose of the trunk. The
elephant’s trunk is for (has the purpose of) drinking water and if it failed to perform that function
we should say that it is malfunctioning or that it is not functioning properly. Those functions that
are not proper functions are ones that do not have the right kind of selection-based history to
make them proper and are ones which the structure in question was not selected to do.
It is for this reason that etiologies are an important feature of arguments on behalf of the
claim that all living things have interests but that artifacts do not. Artifacts, and their functions,
have a different etiology than natural living things. Only biological functions are the result of an
etiological process of natural selection. Artifact functions, however, are the result of a different
etiological process, one of intentional design or artificial selection.
85
IV. A Survey of Etiological Accounts of Living Organisms
85
As I will illustrate in chapter five artifact functions can also be proper functions and can have
functional purposes.
59
Before proceeding I want to provide an overview of four different types of etiology that
are relevant to the existence of living organisms (See Figure 1 below).
Figure 1. Four categories of etiologies for living things
The above list of the different etiologies is not a listing of all etiological account of
interests. Rather this list is given in the hopes of identifying all of those etiologies relevant to the
existence of living things.
Etiological accounts of interests claim that etiologies are relevant to the existence of
interests. All etiological accounts of interests reference some kind of causal process that is
thought to be responsible for the existence of a thing along with its interests. The causal
processes identified are in turn claimed to be relevant in determining whether something
produced by that causal process also has interests. In other words, etiological accounts of
interests all refer to some kind of etiology to explain why something exists which is in turn
claimed to explain why it has interests. They all do so by showing how a thing acquired its
interests in the light of the process that brought it about.
An etiological account of the interests of a butterfly, for example, would say that a
4. Design
Etiology
Non-teleological
Etiologies
2. Agent-
Selection, Non-
teleological
Etiology
ETIOLOGIES RELEVANT TO
THE EXISTENCE OF LIVING
THINGS
Selection
Teleological
Etiologies
3. Instant
Organism
Etiology
60
butterfly has an interest in its structures performing their functions because of the way its
structures were produced. Those structures were produced in the same basic way that the
butterfly itself was produced. Etiological accounts of interests as a whole do not claim that any
one particular etiology is necessary for having interests only that having an etiology bears on the
question of whether a thing will have interests.
There can exist numerous, etiological accounts of interests that invoke each of these
etiologies, but all of these accounts would share a common feature in that they all would make
reference to some etiological process for how a living thing was brought into existence.
For the remainder of this section I will explain the above five etiologies. Since
biocentrists are mainly concerned with accounts of interests for living things my discussion of
these etiologies will be limited to a discussion of how those etiologies could have produced
living things. I do not, however, wish to claim that the above list is entirely exhaustive. These
possibilities are the only ones that I could think of and which seem to be the only ones relevant
to the existence of living things. There may be other possibilities but I am not aware of them.
These possible etiologies are 1) a natural selection etiology
86
, 2) an agent-selection, non-
teleological etiology, 3) an “Instant Organism” etiology, or 4) a design etiology.
So, for example, a natural selection etiology is referenced in all natural selection
etiological accounts of interests. All natural selection etiological accounts of interests will make
reference to a natural selection etiology in determining whether a living thing has interests. On
these accounts the process of natural selection is claimed to be relevant in determining whether a
living thing has interests. Anything that has a natural selection etiology and has structures
produced by that etiology will have interests in their structures performing their functions. An
86
Other writers such as Delancey use the term “evolutionary etiological account”.
61
agent-selection non-teleological etiological account of interests, on the other hand, would claim
that being the product of that etiology would be relevant in determining whether a living thing
has interests. This would go for the other three etiological possibilities.
The first three possible etiologies are what I classify as "non-teleological" or "non-
design" etiologies. These etiologies, as opposed to teleological or design etiologies, do not make
reference to any intentional forethought, planning or design. That is they are “blind” when it
comes to the question of whether a living thing and its structures were planned out in some way
in advance. These three possible etiologies are a natural selection etiology, an agent-selection
non-teleological etiology and an “instant organism” etiology.
The first etiology, a natural selection etiology, refers to a causal history that explains the
emergence of a living thing and its biological structures entirely by recourse to an unguided,
natural process involving reproductively-favored, variant organisms produced by random
mutations. This type of etiology does not make any reference to conscious agents, be it God or
human beings, as the cause for some organism, or its biological structures and their functions.
All that is needed is some kind of non-teleological, process whereby some variant organisms are
more capable in passing their own genes on to successive generations than others. Nature then
non-teleologically "selects" those variants that are more successful at reproducing themselves.
87
87
Natural selection, like all natural processes is blind and undirected. For example, the view that
natural selection, a kind of natural process, is “blind” has been espoused by Richard Dawkins when
he writes,
“All appearances to the contrary, the watchmaker in nature is the blind forces of physics,
albeit deployed in a very special way. A true watchmaker has foresight: he designs his cogs
and springs, and plans their interconnections, with a future purpose in his mind’s eye.
Natural selection, the blind, unconscious automatic process which Darwin discovered, and
which we now know is the explanation for the existence and apparently purposeful form
of all of life, has no purpose in mind. It has no mind and no mind’s eye. It does not plan
for the future. It has no vision, no foresight, no sight at all. If it can be said to play the role
of watchmaker in nature, it is the blind [his emphasis] watchmaker.” (Dawkins, 1986, p.5).
62
Natural selection involves the work of natural law-like regularities which occur in the form of
randomly-generated mutations combined with the unguided selection of favored variants.
88
Some, however, might claim that any kind of natural process could be a process of
natural selection.
For example, some might claim that the assortment of rocks along a stream bed were also
the product of natural selection. An assortment of rocks along a streambed follows a gradient
from large boulders to very small pebbles. This gradation in the arrangement of rocks can easily
be explained as an outcome of simple, natural, law-like processes along with some initial
condition that occur when water moves over a collection of differently-sized rocks. Over time
the rocks are sorted out based on differences in size and weight. But this is not a form of natural
selection. Although we might say that the rocks were "selected" based on their size, those rocks
were not the result of some prior reproduction and rock are not reproductively-favored variants
generated by random mutations. Rocks are not capable of having genetic mutations and do not
have offspring at all. Compared to a simple gradient of rocks, living things and their structures
are much more functionally complex and integrated. Their structures require some kind of
continuous selection mechanism which 'selects' those randomly-produced genetic variants that
are more successful of leaving offspring over time. This is why natural selection-type
The undirected nature of natural selection also has ramifications for what one could predict if the
evolutionary history of life on earth could be “rewound” and played again. The aimless
contingency of the evolutionary process is famously illustrated by Stephen J. Gould in the preface
to his book Wonderful Life. He writes,
“…the ‘pageant’ of evolution [is] a staggeringly improbable series of events, sensible
enough in retrospect and subject to rigorous explanation, but utterly unpredictable and quite
unrepeatable. Wind back the tape of life to the early days of the Burgess Shale; let it play
again from an identical starting point, and the chance becomes vanishingly small that
anything like human intelligence would grace the replay” (Gould, 1989, p. 14).
88
Many biocentrists, including Varner, appeal to this etiology in order to explain the existence
of interests relevant to all living things.
63
explanations for the existence of living things are typically made on the basis of both law-like
regularity, in the form of numerous, random genetic mutations, and some sort of process that
selects those genetic mutants that are more successful at reproducing than other mutants.
The second possible etiology for the existence of a living thing is an "agent selection,
non-teleological" etiology. This etiology involves one possible way in which all living things
could have come about. An etiology of this sort involves selective choices made by an agent but
in which those choices were not directed towards some particular specified end by that agent.
These etiologies are instances of selection by an agent, but not of design or deliberation by that
agent. Here is an example of an agent selection, non-design etiology for a functioning system.
Tom lives just outside of a parts manufacturing plant. On a daily basis random
parts are discarded by the plant through a large, garbage chute. Some of those
parts collect in a huge pile from which Tom can remove individual pieces. Tom
does not put individual pieces together but only removes some pieces that he
thinks are undesirable. Tom decides which parts to remove based on what he
thinks is advantageous or interesting at the very moment he makes the choice.
Tom has no end goal in mind as to what he wants the final collection of parts to
be for. However, by happenstance one day Tom notices that a particular random
arrangement of parts allows rainwater to flow into his favorite bucket which he
then uses to water his garden. If some part from the plant’s chute landed in his
pile that either stopped or diverted the rain water away from his bucket he would
remove that piece from his collection. When Tom’s friends come to visit him Tom
explains that the pile of parts is “for collecting rainwater”. That is to say its
function is to collect rainwater.
This is a non-teleological account for the existence of Tom’s rainwater collector. The
important thing to recognize about this etiology is that although Tom’s collection of parts was
selected by Tom, we would not say that the rainwater collector was designed by Tom to collect
rainwater. Tom had no prior plans to create an object that collected rainwater. And all along the
way his selection process did not work toward that particular goal just in the same way that
natural selection does not “select” for the fulfillment of some future goal. So although the
collection of parts ended up collecting rainwater that collection of parts was not designed for that
64
function. This is basically analogous to Richard Dawkins’ “Blind Watchmaker”. Tom, in this
scenario, is not himself acting purposefully in order to bring about a rainwater collector as a
predetermined structure in accordance with his desires or intentions.
The above example is simply meant to illustrate what a basic agent-selection non-
teleological etiology might look like for the existence of a simple, functional structure. But an
agent-selection non-teleological account of interests would claim that the existence of interests
for a living thing would depend on it being brought about in that sort of way.
The third way in which a living thing could have come about is by recourse to some kind
of inexplicable and sudden natural event. This etiology is one of unforeseen and inexplicable
happenstance.
89
This is what I will call an “Instant Organism” type of etiology. If it were the
case that a living thing, or perhaps even all living things, suddenly sprang into existence by a
highly improbable, instantaneous natural event then we can ask if having that etiology would
make a difference in whether those things would have interests.
The remaining etiological possibility is teleological.
The fourth, and final, etiological possibility for the existence of a living thing is a design
etiology. A living thing could have been the result of some forethought, planning or design on
the part of an agent. A design etiological account of interests would claim that having a design
etiology is relevant to whether a living thing has interests. This etiology makes reference to one
or more designers and their intentions or plans in bringing about some living thing and its
89
The appearances are also regarded as rather sudden. See Ruth Millikan’s discussion in this
chapter regarding the mysteriously appearing double or Donald Davidson’s (1987) example of
“Swampman” in his paper “Knowing One’s Own Mind”. These are both example cases of
“Instant Organisms” that have a nonselection etiology. The primary means of accounting for the
interests of “Instant Organisms” is a non-etiological approach. A non-etiological account of
interest attempts to define what an interest is independently of whatever etiology or history
produced those interests. I critique this view in the next chapter.
65
biologically-relevant structures and functions.
90
These seem to be the only possible ways in which a living thing could have come about.
Whether all living things came about any one of these etiologies, however, is not a question that
I will attempt to address. Also, whether an account of interests is also able to establish that the
identified interests are morally considerable is another matter. In this dissertation I will use the
etiologies listed here in addressing the question of whether those etiologies are capable of
producing living things that have interests which are morally considerable, that is interests that
would give someone a reason to value or care about living things non-instrumentally.
V. Non-etiological Account of Interests
Some biocentrists claim that whether a things has interests does not depend on its
etiology. Those who accept this basic view appeal to "non-etiological" accounts of interests
91
for living things. Those who embrace a non-etiological account of interests argue that having
interests does not depend on a things etiology or causal history. Instead they argue that having
interests is a matter of having one or more structures that perform integrated functions that work
towards the overall maintenance of the whole system in which those structures are found. On
these accounts having interests is a matter of having a certain kind of internal organization
regardless of causal history.
92
90
In section I of chapter five I provide an account of what being "designed" means.
91
Before I continue I would like to provide a note of clarification. While there may exist non-
etiological accounts of interests, there cannot exist non-etiological accounts of living things. All
living things must have some kind of causal history or explanation for how they were brought
about.
92
I will address non-etiological accounts of biological interests in chapter three and will confine
my discussion of non-etiological accounts of interests to those advanced by Delancey and Holm.
66
If it really is the case that etiology is completely irrelevant in determining whether a
living thing has interests then a non-etiological account of interests should be in order if one
wants to show that a living thing has interests despite whatever etiology it might have.
With this background knowledge in hand let us return to a discussion of Varner’s natural
selection account of biological interests, most notably Craig Delancey's criticism of Varner's
account.
VI. Craig Delancey’s Criticism of Varner’s Etiological Account of Interests
Craig Delancey has criticized Varner's etiological account of interests. He thinks that
efforts to connect the existence of biological functions
93
to having interests in those functions
can be problematic. First, Delancey argues that it is possible to discern what an organism has an
interest in independently of the organism's etiology. Second, Delancey argues that biological
functions, as Varner defines them, are not always for the good of the organism.
First, Delancey thinks that a knowledge of what is of interest to a living thing, can be
acquired independently of any knowledge of that living thing’s etiology or causal history.
For example, Delancey thinks that in order to determine whether an elephant has an
interest in its trunk siphoning water we would normally only need to invoke a very weakly
possibly future event to explain that current interest (such as what the near-future siphoning of
water would bring to the elephant). On that basis we can know what would be of interest to the
93
Some have also called biological functions “teleofunctions”. They are essentially the same thing
since both are used in the literature to refer to functional purposes of organs and subsystems of
living things. So, the biological function of the heart is the purpose of the heart which is to pump
blood and the teleofunction of the heart is also to pump blood; See Delancey, 2004. A teleofunction
is a function that an organism possesses if it both enables and compels possible future events
available to the organism bearing it (hence the “teleo”). I will use the term “biological function”
and “teleofunction” interchangeably.
67
elephant. But a thoroughly scientific, natural-selection explanation of the actual historical
development of the elephant’s trunk invokes a long, causal explanation for why that trunk has
that function. An explanation of that sort, however, does not tell us anything about why that
function would be of interest to the organism. Much of the scientific or Darwinian accounts of
biological function simply do not refer to ‘very weakly possible future events’ in the explanation
of present functional purposes. Instead they refer to very ancient states of affairs regarding how
those functions arose as a result of a long history of natural selection.
94
Delancey wants to suggest that having an interest in a structure performing a function is
not really a matter of having a natural selection etiology at all.
95
On Delancey's view a plant
could have an interest in its phloem transporting sugar even if the phloem's function of
transporting sugar were not the product of natural selection.
96
So we could then ask further
questions such as “Couldn’t a plant have an interest in its phloem transporting sugar even if it's
phloem isn’t performing a biological function but is instead performing some other kind of
94
Natural selection is a very long process that for all appearances has very little to do with an
organisms daily existence or way of life. The history of living organisms on earth is generally
thought to span a period of 4.5 billion years. But the lifetime of most plants and animals does not
exceed a few hundred years at most. Most speciation events take millions of years to complete,
but the lifetime of most individual organisms can be measured in years or decades. Also, natural
selection starts with existing living things and preserves those variants that happen to survive. So
there is no direction to the evolutionary process. It is important to remember that the mutations
that occur in DNA, and which then give rise to the various biological structures found in living
things, are randomly generated. Hence, there is no directionality or planning that goes into what
will be of biological interest to living things. The ancient mutations that gave rise to the first heart,
for example, were themselves random and undirected. These kinds of changes occurred without
any concern for what might be or will be of interest to the current or future living things that live
on the earth. See also Delancey, 2006.
95
Or of any etiology as we will see later.
96
I put the term “biological interest” in quotes here because this usage of the term would be in
violation of Varner’s definition of what a biological interest is. What the term “biological interest”
here means is having an interest in some biological structure or sub-system performing a function
that is conducive to its self-regulation.
68
function? Couldn’t a plant have an interest in some structure performing a function that it
actually doesn't have or even that wasn’t particularly adaptive for its ancestors?” Or “Couldn’t a
plant have an interest in its phloem transporting sugar even if it were a plant that had no
ancestors at all?”
For Delancey, these questions point to a difficulty for equating biological interests with
whatever performs biological functions as defined by Varner. It seems reasonable to think that
we can identify what a living thing has (or would have) an interest in (whether we want to call it
biological or not) regardless of what its selection history was. And if this kind of assessment can
be made, then references to etiology are not necessary in order to speak about what is (or would
be) of interest to a living thing.
I will call this problem “the problem of etiology-independent interests” in that there can
exist instances of structures that perform functions that are in a living thing’s interests but that do
not or are not required to have any particular etiology in order for those structures to be of
interest to a living thing.
Delancey makes this kind of point in a different way. He argues that external, remote
explanations that invoke historically-long processes such as natural selection are simply not
necessary to explain the actual usefulness that a structure can make in the life of an organism. As
he puts it,
“The difficulty with the historical etiological account can be seen in a powerful
common sense criticism: it fails to explain how actual field biology works. An
ethologist, confronted with a new organism, is not stumped to explain what it is
up to in its everyday behavior. Rather, she observes its activities, and ascribes to
them purposes based on her understanding of organisms more generally
Biologists and the biological sciences do not posit teleofunctions as historical,
external entities, but rather as activities, generally of internal structures, that have
current utility [my emphasis] to the organism. If we can link a structure with its
teleofunction without reference to (distant) history, and if our determining criteria
are (or can be) sufficient to explain the existence of the teleofunction, then the
69
history is not essential to the property of being a teleofunction” (Delancey, 2006,
p. 74)
Delancey thinks that this problem can be solved by simply pointing out how an existing
structure actually contributes to a system's self-regulation not in how that structure arose by
natural selection. He thinks that the functions of structures, their normative functions, are not
essentially a matter of their history but a matter of how those structure fit together with each
other to construct a self-regulating type of system.
97
Second, Delancey argues that under Varner’s account it turns out that there could exist
biological functions that are positively, antagonistic or harmful to living things. Delancey uses
the example of “oncomice” as a real-world illustration of such a problem.
Oncomice are a genetic strain of mice that are artificially bred to be highly susceptible to
cancer formations. These mice are used by scientists for cancer research. They contain a spliced
gene known as an “oncogene” that facilitates cancerous tumor formation. Mice with the
oncogene are purposefully selected by scientists for sexual reproduction. Based on Varner’s
account, these mice possess a gene with the biological function of producing cancerous tumors
because 1) cancer-production is a result of the mouse’s oncogene and 2) the oncogene is there
because cancer-production was adaptive for the mouse’s ancestors.
These mice, according to Varner's definition of a biological function have a gene that has
the biological function
98
of cancer-production. Subsequently, we would also have to say that
97
This is what is known as the "systems-based" account of interests. The systems-based”
account, as I will describe in the next chapter tries to give an explanation for what the normative
functions of structures are not as a matter of the history or etiology of those structures or the
systems that have those structures.
98
This function, of course, would be one that was artificially-selected by a lab designer not
naturally-selected. Varner's etiological account, however, makes no distinction between
artificially-selected functions and naturally-selected functions.
70
these mice must also have a biological interest in their oncogenes producing cancer. They would
have an interest in getting cancer. But, it should be easy to understand that getting cancer is not
really good for the mouse. Cancerous tumors interfere with other systemic, biologically
functional processes that contribute to the overall self-maintenance of the mouse. Thus, under
Varner's account it looks like the mouse would have an interest in having an oncogene even
though it looks like having an oncogene is not really in the mouse's interests. The reason why
having an oncogene is not in the mouse’s interest is because it interferes with the other biological
processes that the mouse needs in order for it to regulate itself.
99
But these kinds of problems don’t just exist for artificially-selected forms of life.
Artificial selection of this kind is just like natural selection in that both of these selection
processes are not ultimately concerned with what contributes to, or would contribute to, the
health of an individual living thing. This is why there can arise problematic instances of
structures or behaviors that are "selected" by these processes but that are not really in the interest
of the individual organism that has those structures or exhibits those behaviors. Instead these
processes produce organisms for utilitarian purposes separate from their own biological needs or
what would be "good for" them. The process of artificially-selecting the oncomouse’s gene is a
historical, etiological process aimed at breeding and reproducing mice that have a certain kind of
gene. They are bred for their utilitarian value. But natural selection does this same kind of thing
too! It too "selects" those mutants that happen to be instrumentally better at reproducing their
genes than other mutants. Only those organisms that happen to be successful in spreading their
genes get to survive.
99
This, of course, does not mean that cancer formation would be the only interest of the mice,
merely that cancer formation is one of the things that would be of biological interest to the mice.
They have other interests, both preference and biological, in addition to this one.
71
Take the following as an example of how natural selection produces a Varnerian
biological function that is not really in the interest of an individual living thing. The gall aphid,
Nipponaphis monzeni, ruptures its own body wall in order to release its bodily fluids as a means
of patching up its plant gall shelter. This results in suicide for the individual aphid. Such a
behavior, on Varner’s account would have a biological function. As such the aphid would then
have an interest in rupturing its own body wall. But this does not appear to be in the individual
aphid’s biological interests at all.
100
Elliot Sober, addresses this kind of problem in the following way,
“For virtually any trait you please, there can be environments in which that trait is
selected for, or selected against. Diseases can be rendered advantageous, and
health can be made to represent a reproductive cost. And even, if we restrict our
attention to historically actual environments, we still encounter difficulties. A
perfectly healthy phenotype may be historically nonexistent; the optimum actually
attained might still be some diseased state [my emphasis]” (Sober, 1980, p. 377).
The “optimum” for the aphid might include a behavior that results in its suicide (if we are
to think of suicidal behavior as being sufficiently “disease-like”). Likewise the “optimum” state
for an oncomouse might be (or, more strongly, is) its possession of the oncogene. The point here
is to stress that even if a natural selection etiology produces structures with proper functions it
does not mean that those functions are also in the biological interests of the individual living
thing. Natural selection ultimately produces living things that are capable of reproducing and
spreading their genes. States that happen to be detrimental to or harmful to living things
themselves do not matter as long as genetic fitness is not compromised. So individual biocentric
flourishing and interests seem to be more of an "afterthought", one that cannot always be squared
100
See, "The suicide plasterer's - aphids that repair their homes with their own bodily fluids"
from the Not Exactly Rocket Science blog (Ed Yong, 02/25/09):
http://blogs.discovermagazine.com/notrocketscience/ 2009/02/25/the-suicide-plasterers-aphids-
that-repair-their-homes-with-their-own-bodily-fluids/#.U-pubvldWSo
72
with the findings of evolutionary theory.
101
And if that is the case then naturally-selected proper
functions or purposes in themselves cannot be sufficient to account for the existence of interests.
I will call problematic cases such as these instances of “harmful, selected functions” in
that under a natural selection etiology there can exist cases of naturally-selected functions that
are not in and individual living thing’s interests.
Those who would still like to endorse some kind of natural selection etiological account
of morally considerable interests might try to find a way of addressing these problems. For
example, they could adopt an altered view of Varner's original account of interests, one that
prevents harmful, selected functions from making it onto the list of biological functions and thus
of what an organism would have an interest in. Such a modified, Varnerian view might be
something like the following:
…an individual A has an interest in X if and only if
(1) A actually desires X,
(2) A would desire X if A were adequately informed and impartial across all
phases of A’s life, or
(3) X would fulfill some biological function of some organ or subsystem of A,
where X is a biological function of S [an organ or subsystem] in A if and only if
(a) X is a consequence of A’s having S and
(b) A has S because achieving X was adaptive for A’s ancestors and
(c) the performance of X is good for the organism.
The addition of clause (c) under part three of Varner's account of interests could help the
natural selection etiologist deal with the problem of harmful, selected functions. For example,
since the function of tumor production is not good for the oncomouse, those mice can then be
claimed not to have an interest in having the oncogene. On this modified view the oncogene
would not have a biological function. Thus, the mouse would not have an interest in producing
cancerous tumors.
101
I expand on this point later in this chapter in my discussion of the “genetic selectionist view”
73
But such an amended account would still be open to the problem of identifying what is
"good for the organism". For example, some might say that having an oncogene could actually
be in a mouse's interests after all. They could argue that even though the gene itself reduces the
mouse's long-term prospects for self-regulation these mice nonetheless do live longer when
compared to the other mice that do not have the oncogene. Supposing that a team of research
scientists selectively killed off all mice that did not possess the oncogene it seems reasonable to
think that under these circumstances having an oncogene really would be good for the organism
that bears it. Thus, it would still be the case that an oncomouse would have an interest in
producing cancerous tumors after all simply because having that gene enables them to live
longer!
On the one hand, it looks like an oncomouse would not have an interest in getting cancer
because cancer is detrimental to its overall biological self-maintenance. But on the other hand it
looks like there could exist some circumstances under which having an oncogene could be in the
mouse's interest after all.
102
Thus, even on an amended Varnerian, etiological account of interests the problem of the
oncogene, as a harmful, selected function, could only be solved if one adopts a particular
definition of what the "good of the organism" means.
Another possible problem remains for the amended Varnerian view. It looks as if clause
c, taken in isolation, already tells us what we need to know about what would be in an
102
I will address this problematic case further in the next chapter. Roughly, there is a distinction
between what would be in the mouse's "teleofunctional interests" and what would be in (what I
call) the mouse's "life-expectancy interests". Basically, having all teleofunctional interests met is
much more important to an organism than having all of its "life-expectancy interests" met. Some
teleofunctional interests are so vital to an organism that if they were not met the organism in
question would expect to have "zero life expectancy" meaning that it would die instantly.
74
organism's interest. If there exists some structure that is "good for the organism" to have then it
would seem rather straighforward to think that having such a structure would be in the
organism's interest. If there exists some structure that is "good for the organism" to have, then
why think that the organism should meet any other condition for it to have an interest? In other
words, why think that clauses a and b add of an amended Varnerian account tell us anything
significant about what would be in an organism's interest? What's the motivation for their
inclusion?
This lack of genuine motivation seems to be the problem for Varner's account.
Delancey has pointed out that we can know what is, or what would be, in a living thing's
interest without having to know anything about its etiology.
Consider the following case as an example of how a structure can have a Varnerian
biological function, but that does not necessarily contribute to a living thing's interests. Human
beings get “goose bumps” by contractions of small muscles that are located under the skin. These
muscles are known as arrector pili and they connect each hair follicle to an underlying layer of
connective tissue. When the muscle contracts it creates the characteristic goose bumps seen on
our skin.
The contraction of the muscle is its biological function. We inherited the arrector pili
muscles from our ancestors who presumably utilized them as part of a defense mechanism. Their
arrector pili raised their body hair, which in turn made them appear larger to would-be predators.
We inherited that functional characteristic from our ancestors and these muscles perform that
function in us because of these past instances of performing that same function. Thus, our
arrector pili serve a biological function. But does it follow that we have a biological interest in
our arrector pili performing this function? More to the point do we have a need for that function?
75
Is the functioning of our arrector pili “good for” us in that sense? Is it "bad for" us? It doesen't
look like the functioning of our arrector pili is either "good for" or "bad for" us. So what would
motivate us to think that we would have an interest in the functioning of our arrector pili?
Clauses a and b do not provide this motivation because they cannot give us guidance on what
counts as being "good for" an organism and what count as not being "good for" an organism.
VII. Conclusion
As we have seen a natural selection etiology is not a sufficient condition for the existence
morally considerable interests. In particular, Varner's etiological account of biological interests is
subject to two significant problems.
This account suffers from counterexamples in which some living organism could have a
biological structure that performs a biological function that is itself not in the biological interest
of the individual living thing that has that structure. The oncomouse rejoinder is the biggest
problem for Varner's view. The problem is that there can arise structures that have a selected
biological function which fits within an organism’s ancestral heritage, but which the selected
function in question might not appear to be in a living thing’s interest.
Varner’s etiological account of biological interests does not distinguish between
artificially selected functions and naturally selected functions in terms of what can bring about
biological functions. Varner’s account, however, is intended to serve as a natural selection
etiological account of biological interests. But as I have previously argued natural selection
etiological accounts of biological interests are not sufficient to account for the existence of
morally considerable biological interests. Natural selection can produce biological functions that
are just as harmful to the organism as any artificially selected biological function.
76
Thus, a biocentrist should reject this account of interests as a means of grounding the
claim that naturally selected functions indicate what a living thing has an interest in.
Because Dalancey thinks that the whole notion of normative functions or purposes of
individual living things should be abandoned in light of what evolutionary theory really tells us.
He argues instead that functions should be characterized by reference to a “systems-based
account”, an account which, according to him, is not one of identifying normative functions
based on etiological considerations but merely of functional contribution to some larger system.
This account of function makes no references at all to what some structure was "selected" to do
based on any past reproductive success but rather to what some structure is doing in contributing
to the maintenance and further functioning of some larger system of which it is a part. This
account of function does not explain why some structure exists where it is and has the function it
does. Nor does it even attempt to identify the historical or causal processes that could have
brought those structure and their functions about. In other words, for Delancey, there is no point
in talking about the history of the heart. Instead, we should talk about the actual functional role
that the heart plays in the systemic maintenance of the living thing that has it.
At this point the biocentrist trying to find and account of morally considerable interests
can choose between one of two options. Either, she can appeal to some other account of interests
or she can appeal to a non-etiological account of interests.
In the next chapter I will consider the latter option and its implications.
77
CHAPTER THREE
The Systems-Based Account and a Definition of Interests
In the previous chapter I highlighted some of the problems for Varner’s etiological
account of interests. These problems have led Delancey to drop etiological accounts of interests
altogether.
Authors such as Delancey and others, have offered an account of what biological
functions, or teleofunctions, are that does not define the normativity of functions by recourse to
an etiology. For them naturally-evolved structures don’t acquire their normative, functional
status because they evolved by natural selection. Rather normativity of function arises because of
the way in which a structure performs a function that is integral to the self-regulation of the
entire system of which that structure is a part.
In the first section of this chapter I will provide an explanation of Delancey's non-
etiological, "systems-based" account of interests. This account claims that living organisms have
interests by recourse to their teleofunctionality not their etiology.
In the second section I will bring further clarification to the definition of interests that I
provided in chapter one. I will use this section to present a comprehensive, unified definition of
interests. This amended definition will take into account the insights gathered from Delancey's
systems-based account.
In the third section I will defend the claim that given Delancey's systems-based account
of interests it turns out that any teleofunctional system, including any artificially-produced
teleofunctional system, would be a candidate for having interests. The systems-based account, if
applied by the biocentrist, cannot rule out systems of artificial contrivance as long as those
systems are teleofunctional. Specifically it cannot rule out non-biological, artificial contrivances.
78
If the biocentrist accepts a systems-based account of interests they must also accept the
proposition that all teleofunctional systems, whether biological or not, have interests.
In light of the fact that artifacts cannot be excluded from having interests I will, in the
fourth section, provide a defense of the claim that the term "biological functions" should be
replaced with the term "teleofunctions" and that the term "biological interests" should be
replaced with the term "teleofunctional interests" when describing the kinds of functions and
interests that belong to all living things. Since all living things are teleofunctional systems and all
teleofunctional systems have teleofunctional interests in their structures performing their
teleofunctions, then the kinds of functions that would be of interest to all living thing are
teleofunctions. The use of these terms is also consistent with another implication of a systems-
based view in that the functions that are integral to the self-regulation of a teleofunctional system
need not be specifically biological in nature. These functions need not be regarded as
"biological" in the sense that teleofunctional structures can belong to non-biological or inorganic
beings. Sophisticated robots, for example, could turn out to be teleofunctional systems, even
though they are not biological or organic beings.
In the fifth section I will consider some of the criticism's that have been made against the
systems-based view of interests. I will argue that all of these criticisms fail to show that all
teleofunctional systems do not or cannot have interests. I will also appeal to Sune Holm's
response to Varner's criticism. Holm argues that artificially-produced living things have interests
regardless of the fact that they were not produced by natural selection.
In the sixth section I will examine some criticisms of the view that artifacts could have
interests and provide some responses to the criticisms. In this section I explain the motivating
factor that lies behind these criticisms. Arguments against the moral value of artifacts are
79
partially motivated by the basic assumption that whatever is artificial is inferior and that
whatever is "natural" is superior. This assumption is motivated by what John Basl calls a "central
dogma" of environmentalism. This dogma claims that anything that is artificial or artificially-
produced is inferior to what is "natural" or naturally-produced. This distinction is then employed
in support of the argument that only "natural" or naturally-produced things can have interests. I
will argue that this distinction cannot be maintained because there can exist some natural things
that are bad or morally repugnant and other things that are artificial that are good or morally
commendable.
In the seventh section I provide a description of the current status of synthetic life
research. Here l show that current artificial life research is continually getting closer to
generating new, artificial forms of life from scratch. As such the "threat" of artificial forms of
life is a reality that is not as far off as some environmentalists might think.
In the eighth, and final, section I conclude that a non-etiological or systems-based view of
interests will not help the biocentrist in making any distinction between artificially produced
forms of life, naturally-evolved forms of life or "instant organisms" that suddenly "sprang" into
existence with regard to whether they have interests. The systems-based account would claim
that all of these teleofunctional systems have interests. What this means is that the systems-based
approach is quite adept at identifying systems that have interests, particularly teleofunctional
interests. Whether teleofunctional interests are morally considerable is another question, one that
I will address in the chapter four.
I. Delancey's Systems-Based Account of Interests
According to a natural selection etiological account, the functional norms of naturally-
80
selected structures are not specified by reference to the ongoing, systemic, integral role that those
structures play in the self-regulation of a larger system. All that is needed is that the structure in
question be a reproduction inherited from an ancestor that had that same structure and where that
structure was previously adaptive. But on a systems-based view, functional norms for structures
are specified by the integral, functional roles that those structures actually play in the overall
self-regulation of some larger system of which they are a part.
According to Delancey, an integral function that contributes to a system's overall self-
regulation is known as a teleofunction. A teleofunction is a function performed by some structure
that is itself part of a whole system of other structures that all work together to bring about a
living thing’s self-maintenance and regulation.
Delancey prefers to use the term “teleofunction” instead of the term "biological function"
as used by Varner. He departs from the use of the term "biological function" largely because
biological functions are defined on the basis of their etiology. Delancey thinks that teleofunctions
do not depend, and hence should not be defined, on the basis of, their etiology. But, just as
Varner thinks that biological functions are normative, Delancey also thinks that teleofunctions
are normative.
Many writers use the terms “biological function” and “teleofunction” interchangeably.
But Delancey uses the term teleofunction to emphasize of an important aspect of its connection
to interests, namely that teleofunctions serve the needs of living things, most notably their need
for self-regulation and maintenance. Varner, on the other hand, attempted to define biological
functions in purely etiological terms not in terms of a living thing’s self-maintenance. In the
second section of his paper “Teleofunctions and Oncomice” Delancey writes,
“To make sense of the notion of an organism having purposes arising from its
own biological form, we need to identify what it is for that organism to have
81
teleofunctions [his emphasis] (I use the term from here on to avoid any confusion
with the use of function in its other senses, and to recognize that such functions
need not be biological). Let us suppose that one of the teleofunctions of a mouse
is foraging, and that a mouse cannot flourish if it cannot forage (or at least play at
foraging). We might say that the mouse “wants” to forage, but doing so is likely
to obscure the issue. The claim is not that the organism must have a mental state
to have a teleofunction. Rather, although the mouse may indeed desire (e.g., have
some affective state which drives it) to forage, the point is that the life of a mouse
under normal conditions is in part composed of foraging, and that the organism
cannot have a full life without foraging [my emphasis].” (Delancey, 2004, p. 173)
In this passage Delancey links teleofunctions not just to what a living thing in some sense
“wants” (nonconsciously) to do, or to those functions that its structures actually perform, but to
what would bring about a “full life” for the living thing. I take it that Delancey is saying that
unless an organism performs its teleofunctions that it will not have a full life.
There can exist some biological functions that are not teleofunctions. The arrector pili is
an instance of a structure that has a biological function, but since it is not situated in the context
of the organism's overall self-maintenance, it might not be entirely appropriate to call the
function that it performs a teleofunction. The arrector pili in human beings is not necessary for
their continued self-maintenance.
103
In other words, I want to suggest that what is clearly a
biological function is not likewise clearly a teleofunction. The arrector pili's function is a case in
point.
We should also be aware that a full life does not only consist in the performance of
teleofunctions. The proposition that Delancey wants to advance is only that the performance of
teleofunctions is necessary for such a life. For example, there are certain reproductive behaviors
that upon inspection are not themselves teleofunctional. They do not contribute to the self-
regulation of the system that performs those behaviors. But they are still necessary for what we
103
Although it could have been necessary for the self-maintenance of the ancestors of human
beings.
82
might think would be a full life. For example, the behavior of a bird laying an egg is not itself a
teleofunctional behavior. Laying eggs does not contribute to the individual bird's self-regulation.
Yet laying eggs is nonetheless something that is in the bird's interest to do. It is good for the bird
to lay eggs because it is good for the propagation of its species.
In any event Delancey is, I think, identifying a necessary condition, although not a
sufficient condition, for what having an interest should mean. When it comes to teleofunctions it
means performing functions that meet the necessary requirements for one's own self-
maintenance. Without these requirements being met an organism cannot live a full life nor could
it reproduce. If those requirements are met then the organism benefits in some way.
Structures that perform teleofunctions, are what Delancey calls teleofunctional structures.
Living organisms are comprised of numerous, teleofunctional structures. These structures allow
living things to regulate themselves along a wide array of physiological parameters. The kinds of
systems that possess numerous, teleofunctional structures are what I call teleofunctional systems.
Living organisms would, thus, be prime examples of teleofunctional systems.
Delancey describes living things as instances of self-regulation in the midst of
unpredictable, external conditions. Living organisms are teleofunctional systems because they
involve a great number of diverse, interconnected structures, teleofunctional structures, that all
function in tandem with one another to keep the organism alive.
He writes,
“An organism is a complex system that has certain capabilities which we identify
as teleofunctions because they maintain certain features of the system. Prima
facie, biological organisms are adaptive and self-organizing complex systems.
The notion of a self-organizing system is not, unfortunately, very easily defined.
But we do not need it to be. What matters instead is that such systems do exist,
and that biological organisms are surely examples of them. That such systems
exist is most obvious when we consider homeostasis, a necessary feature of any
complex self-organizing system. The process of evolution produces systems
83
which act in their environments in a way that maintains a stable range of values
on many parameters of the organism: body temperature, water levels, physical
integrity (e.g., some avoid being broken in two), and many others. These
homeostatic functions are in part demonstrable in a simple empirical way. Given
the opportunity to drink water, many organisms will do so in a way that maintains
a range of the quantity of water in their bodies. Many organisms maintain a
constant narrow range of body temperature, and many also, when given the
opportunity to walk along a temperature gradient, will seek a place that allows
them easy thermoregulation, and so on. Of course, all organisms depend upon
their environment for stability on some dimensions. Thus, some organisms will
eat too much food if food is available in excess of what would normally be the
case in their environment. Organisms also have limited abilities to respond; they
can only travel a particular distance, or thermoregulate in a particular range of
external temperatures, etc. But within certain parameters, which can be expected
to be close to those in which they evolved, organisms demonstrate homeostasis
for much of their lives…the relevant parameters will only be maintained in
particular ranges which we can in principle empirically identify (a mouse heated
to 200º centigrade is not going to thermoregulate, or maintain its internal water
levels, and so on); we can identify independently the ranges of environmental
conditions in which the organism will succeed in various kinds of homeostasis.
Conversely, we can know as an experimentally demonstrable fact that an
organism will die if it does not stay in these ranges” (Delancey, 2004, p. 181).
This, for Delancey, illustrates a hallmark feature of a system that is teleofunctional. It is
its ability to regulate itself in the environment in which it is found.
But that is not all. Delancey thinks that teleofunctional systems must be complex. This
means that a teleofunctional system must contain numerous, teleofunctional structures in order to
count as teleofunctional.
“…we identify those systems as having teleofunctions that have components
which operate not as a simple, but rather as part of complex, [my emphasis]
application of laws of nature…Certain structures perform activities which support
other structures of the organism and their activities, which in turn, typically very
indirectly, support that original structure or other instances of that kind of
structure. That is, many of the parts of an organism are supporting each other
that is an essential part of what it is to be a self-organizing complex [my
emphasis] system” (Delancey, 2004, pp. 182-183).
So a teleofunctional system must have a certain amount of complexity before it can be
capable of regulating itself to at least the same degree as living organisms can.
Delancey also thinks that there should be a certain amount of functional independence
84
between the parameters regulated by the teleofunctional structures that a complex system has.
This independence is not absolute but rather involves partially-overlapping processes that, while
independent from each another to some degree, still support each other in other ways. As
Delancey writes,
"Another way of recognizing that a teleofunctional system must be complex is to
note that the parameters that we identify as demonstrating the effects of
teleofunctions need to be, to some degree, independent of each other
104
[my
emphasis]." Delancey, 2004, p. 182)
But what relevance does Delancey's notion of systems that are teleofunctional have to do
with the claim that those systems have interests?
A straightforward answer is found in understanding the vital role that teleofunctional
structures play in the self-regulation of a teleofunctional system.
According to Delancey’s systems-based account, a living thing has, or would have, an
interest in its teleofunctional structures performing their teleofunctions, those functions that are
integral to its self-regulation.
104
Here Delancey footnotes p. 273 of Ernst Nagel’s paper “Teleology Revisited: Goal Directed
Processes in Biology” in which Nagel gives an illustration of this kind of independence. For
instance, water maintenance in human beings is achieved by dual processes that are
teleofunctional. The kidneys absorb water from the bloodstream while the muscles and skin of
the body release stored water into the bloodstream. The variable for the amount of water that the
kidneys absorb and the variable for the amount of water that the muscles and skin release are in
Nagel’s words “independent of (or “orthogonal” to) each other, in the sense that within certain
limits the value of either variable at a given moment is compatible with any value of the other
variable at the same moment.” Kidneys indirectly contribute to healthy muscle and skin by
removing the body’s waste products (thus keeping the body alive) and the muscles and skin
indirectly contribute to healthy kidneys in that they move the body and protect the body which
also function in keeping that body alive. But many more subsystems can be at work. As Nagel
further writes,
“Although in this example the goal is the product of a homeostatic mechanism, and only two
variables were assumed to be relevant to the realization of the goal, the analysis can easily be
generalized to cover other types of goal-directed processes involving any number of variables”
(Nagel, 1977, p. 273-274).
85
For example, we can say that a plant, has an interest in its leaves gathering sunlight
because its leaves are teleofunctional structures. Its leaves are structures that are functionally
integrated into the whole, complex, teleofunctional system that is the plant itself. The leaves of
the plant have the teleofunction of absorbing sunlight which in turn contributes to the plant’s
production of sugars which in turn contributes to the plant's ability to make more leaf tissue
along with others tissues that it needs. Absorbing sunlight is good for the plant. It is vital to the
self-regulation of it. If the plant’s leaves were severed from it then those leaves would be
incapable of contributing to the plant’s overall self-regulation. The plant would thus be harmed if
its teleofunctional structures were to be damaged or removed. Thus, the plant has an interest in
its leaves performing the teleofunction of gathering sunlight.
On this view teleofunctional structures have normative functions, functions that in some
sense they are "supposed to" perform or "have the purpose" of performing in that if they fail to
perform these functions the teleofunctional system as a whole will not regulate itself and hence
will either become diseased or die. As Delancey writes,
“…teleofunctions are had by structures that perform certain kinds of sustaining
activities in kinds of systems. Their normative nature [my emphasis] comes from
the fact that (portions of) the systems that they constitute cannot exist or continue
without those activities. Systemic teleofunctions have a kind of normative force
[my emphasis] then akin to a Kantian hypothetical imperative. The structure in
question should [his emphasis] do such and such activities in order to [again, his
emphasis] maintain (some portion of) the complex system to which it belongs”
(Delancey, 2006, p. 80)
So on Delancey's view teleofunctional systems, of which living organisms are the prime
example, have interests because those systems have teleofunctional structures that have
functional purposes of contributing to the life and self-regulation of the system itself.
II. Further Clarification on the Definition of Interests
86
With the above understanding of what a teleofunctional system is and why it has interests
I will now turn to a discussion about the definition of interests that was previously presented in
chapter one. In this section I will attempt to provide a comprehensive definition of what an
interest is.
In chapter one I defined an interest as:
X has
105
an interest in Y (Y is an interest of X’s) if and only if Y is good for X
where “Y is good for X” means that:
1) If X does not have Y then X is harmed and 2) If X has Y then X is
benefited.
106
Some at this point may wish to object to the notion that having interests means being
capable of being harmed or benefited because there can exist some things that can be harmed or
benefited but that do not seem to have interests. A clock, for example, can be harmed if someone
damages its springs. But this does not mean that the clock has interests. If we go by the previous
definition of what constitutes having interests we would have to say that clocks have interests
because it is something that can be harmed.
So how exactly can this problem be solved? I want to suggest that relatively simple
objects such as clocks are not capable of being harmed in a kind of way that other things that do
have interests can be. Since things like clocks cannot be harmed in this way they do not have
interests.
Teleofunctional systems are capable of being harmed in a way that is distinctively
different from other kinds of objects such as clocks. Teleofunctional systems, unlike most
artificial contrivances, must engage in numerous, internal, self-regulating processes that if
105
Non-psychologically 'has'.
106
Please see the definition of interests in section VII of chapter one for particular examples of
how this definition applies to cases of harm and benefit.
87
interrupted cause either a complete cessation of their self-regulation or a substantial impedance
in their ability to self-regulate. Clocks, it might be suggested, have a number of self-regulating
structures, but they do not have numerous
107
structures. Hence, they are not teleofunctional.
Teleofunctional systems are the kinds of systems that can be harmed in this way. They are
harmed whenever one of their numerous, teleofunctional structures are damaged. This kind of
damage results in its self-regulation being either diminished or destroyed altogether.
For example, if someone were to damage a teleofunctional system such as a single cell by
puncturing its membrane, that organism would suffer from an inability to regulate various
physiological parameters that contribute to its self-regulation. The puncturing of its membrane
would cause, for instance, further changes in its effectiveness at maintaining its own internal
osmoregulation or in its ability to synthesize DNA. These changes would immediately affect the
cell's overall ability to maintain its self-regulation. The cell can be harmed in such a way that if
one of its teleofunctional structures or parts were damaged it would either be incapable of
maintaining its own self-regulation or its self-regulation would become greatly restricted or
impeded in some way (in a case, for example, in which one of its genes were to be removed).
This kind of harm is what I call systemic harm. Systemic harm as an instance of a harm
that brings about either an impedance of a teleofunctional system's self-regulation or a complete
cessation of that system's self-regulation. Clocks and everyday ordinary objects cannot be
systemically harmed because they are not teleofunctional systems. They do not engage in
numerous, integrated self-regulatory processes. They cannot be harmed in this way because they
are not teleofunctional systems.
107
Exactly how "numerous" the structures have to be in order for a teleofunctional system to be
capable of self-regulation I do not know. I do know that the number of structures that go into the
makeup of the simplest forms of life is at least in the thousands, if not hundreds of thousands.
88
Teleofunctional systems can also be subjects of systemic benefit. A systemic benefit is a
kind of benefit that sustains the overall, self-regulation of all aspects of the teleofunctional
system but does not positively enhance that system's growth or self-regulation beyond what is
necessary for its self-regulation. A properly-operating proboscis, for example, brings about a
systemic benefit to the butterfly. It systemically sustains the life of the butterfly as a whole self-
regulating system by delivering nectar to it. The proboscis sips nectar and nectar is a rich food
source for the butterfly. This food source is then utilized by the butterfly to maintain its
biological integrity and self-regulation in numerous ways. If the butterfly’s proboscis were to be
damaged then it would not receive a systemic benefit but would instead be systemically harmed.
To that end I would like to provide a replacement for the previous definition of interests
provided in chapter one that is able to account for the existence of interests of all teleofunctional
things.
X has an interest in Y (Y is an interest of X’s) if and only if Y is good for X
where “Y is good for X” means that:
1) If X is denied Y then X is systemically harmed and 2) If X is not denied Y then
X is systemically benefited.
All living things have an interest in avoiding systemic harm and in acquiring systemic
benefit. Teleofunctional systems, like all living organisms, are systems that are capable of being
systemically harmed and benefited and so on the above definition all systems of this type will
have interests.
But there might be other interests besides these interests that a teleofunctional system can
have. For example, there can exist cases were something, Y, can be good for X but in which if X
were denied Y, X would not be systemically harmed but would be benefited in some way other
than a systemic benefit. For example, a little bit of extra fertilizer might be good for a plant. But
if the plant is denied that little bit of fertilizer it is not systemically harmed. A little bit of extra
89
fertilizer, does contribute beyond what is necessary for the plant's growth and self-regulation. So
it seems reasonable to think that the plant has an interest in receiving a little bit of extra fertilizer.
That little bit of extra fertilizer, however, does not systemically benefit it. Instead the
plant is benefited in a different way, in such a way that we might say that the plant is "enhanced"
by a little bit of extra fertilizer. The plant has an interest in being enhanced in this way. Even
though a little bit of extra fertilizer does not systemically benefit it, it still has an interest in it. So
it looks as if the plant really does have an interest in getting a little bit of extra fertilizer.
What might we call these kinds of interests?
I will term these kinds of interests "systemic enhancement interests". A "systemic
enhancement interest" is an interest in receiving what is beneficial above and beyond what is
necessary for the overall self-maintenance and regulation of a teleofunctional system. If a plant
does not receive a little bit of extra fertilizer it is not harmed in any way, either systemically or
otherwise. But if it does receive it, it is benefited in such a way that its growth and self-
maintenance are enhanced. I will call this kind of benefit a "systemic enhancement". All
teleofunctional systems that receive something that brings them a systemic enhancement are
systemically enhanced by that thing.
To that end I provide the following definition of what a systemic enhancement interest is.
A systemic enhancement interest is an interest in acquiring a systemic enhancement.
Let us call the type of interests that all teleofunctional systems have teleofunctional
interests. All teleofunctional systems have an interest in avoiding systemic harm, acquiring
systemic benefit and in acquiring a systemic enhancement.
To that end I would like to provide the following as a definition of a teleofunctional
interest:
90
X has a teleofunctional interest in Y (Y is an interest of X’s) if and only if Y is
good for X where “Y is good for X” means that:
1) If X is denied Y then X is systemically harmed or 2) If X is not denied Y then
X is systemically benefited or 3) If X is not denied Y then X is systemically
enhanced.
From the standpoint a teleofunctional system it is much more important for it to receive a
systemic benefit than it is for it to receive a mere systemic enhancement. For example, it is more
important for a plant's phloem to transport sugar properly than it is for that plant to receive a
little bit of extra fertilizer. If its phloem cannot transport sugar properly then the plant will die.
But if a plant is denied a systemic enhancement in the form of a little bit of extra fertilizer the
plant will not die. The plant in all likelihood will continue to live and thrive. It only means that
the plant will not grow more than it might have otherwise.
Avoiding systemic harm and acquiring systemic benefit are essential to the overall self-
regulation of a teleofunctional system. Those teleofunctional interests in avoiding systemic harm
and in acquiring system benefit are thus what I will call "essential, teleofunctional interests".
Acquiring a systemic enhancement, however, is not essential to the overall self-regulation
of a teleofunctional system. A little bit of fertilizer, for example, is not essential to a plant's self-
regulation. A plant can continue to maintain itself if it is not given a little bit of extra fertilizer.
Thus I will call the teleofunctional interest in receiving a systemic enhancement a "non-essential,
teleofunctional interest". So, this means that all non-essential, teleofunctional interests are
systemic, enhancement interests.
All living things have both essential and non-essential, teleofunctional interests. I,
however, will not specifically refer to non-essential, teleofunctional interests in my discussion of
the biocentric case for inherent worth. Biocentrists are more concerned with what can damage or
kill a living thing or reduce its effectiveness at maintaining its own basic integrity than in what
might bring it a systemic enhancement. A little bit of extra fertilizer might be in a plants
91
teleofunctional interests, but for the biocentrist it is more important that the plant not die or be
subjected to a reduction in its overall self-regulation.
The above definition of teleofunctional interests should not be interpreted to mean that
there cannot exist other interests besides teleofunctional interests. The above definition of
interests, however, is meant to apply to all teleofunctional beings. And since all living things are
teleofunctional things the above definition applies to all living things.
Indeed there are other interests, besides teleofunctional interests, that can belong to some,
but not all, living things. An example of such an interest would be a "preference interest".
108
Preference interests belong to psychological beings such as ourselves that are also
teleofunctional, in that we are capable of having psychological states such as desires or wants in
pursuing various projects. Having a preference interest means at least having intentions, plans,
forethoughts or goals. And since only psychological beings can have preference interests, only
psychological beings can have intentions, plans, forethoughts or goals. But not all living things
are psychological beings. A plant, for example, has no psychological states such as desires.
On the other hand, my dog is a psychological being. He is capable of having
psychological states such as desires or wants for various things. For instance, to say that my dog
has
109
an interest in going outside is to say that my dog desires to go outside, or that he
"purposes" to go outside or that my dog intends to go outside. And I can tell that he has this
desire or intention by observing his attentive stare and waging tail. My dog intends to go outside
in large measure because he gets some happiness out of it. Likewise, a person can have a
108
Preference interests, also known as, 'desire interests' were previously discussed in the section
II in chapter two.
109
The use of the term "has" in this paragraph means having a certain preference or desire. On
this understanding, my do dog psychologically has an interest.
92
preference interest in writing poetry and intend to write poetry. All else considered equal it is
wrong to prevent a being from pursuing their own intended purposes especially if pursuing those
purposes makes that being happy. Likewise, if I were to prevent my dog from fulfilling his
intention to go outside, and such an intention of his is not in conflict with any other beings'
interests, such an action would be wrong. On the other hand, it would be right to allow my dog to
fulfill his intention of going outside, again assuming that his going outside would not interfere
with some other being's interests.
We can then provide a definition of preference interests as:
X has a preference interest in Y (Y is a preference interest of X’s) if and only if X
intends to bring about Y and Y is good for X where “Y is good for X” means that:
1) If X were denied Y then X would be non-systemically harmed or 2) If X were
not denied Y then X would be non-systemically benefited in some way.
Instances of "non-systemic harm" might include things such as anxiety, frustration,
depression, sadness, anger, being deceived, being insulted, etc. These kinds of harm come about
whenever a person's desires, intentions or plans are frustrated. Instances of "non-systemic
benefit" might include things such as happiness, contentment, elation, satisfaction, etc. These
kinds of benefit come about by the fulfillment of a person's desires, intentions or plans.
The basic problem for this definition of preference interests is that there can exist some
cases where a person may have a preference in undertaking an activity that is actually bad for
her. An example of this is illustrated by Gary Varner in his description of the case of “Maude”.
He writes,
“…consider the case of Maude, an unusually intelligent and generally farsighted
young adult who has a strong desire to smoke. Concerned for her welfare, we
bring to her attention the fact that the best available evidence indicates that this
smoking will shorten her life by a certain number of years. Suppose that Maude
really takes this fact to heart, that the consequences of her conduct are accurately
foreseen and adequately realized in her imagination at the present time, but that
she nevertheless goes right on smoking…[but] Maude’s smoking is bad for her
[my emphasis] that is, that it is contrary to her interests” (Varner, 1998, p. 58).
93
What Varner is saying here is that some of our preferences or intentions might not be
consistent with what is actually in our interests. The reason why Maude’s consummate smoking
is bad for her is because it could lead to systemic harm to her body. That is, her preference
interest in smoking is contrary to her teleofunctional interests. Smoking causes lung cancer,
emphysema and other health-related problems that are not good for her lungs. Her lungs are
teleofunctional structures that she has (non-psychologically 'has') a teleofunctional interest in
performing their teleofunctions even if she happens to have (psychologically 'have') a desire to
smoke or even if she happens to have a psychological aversion to smoking. In other words, a
person's preferences are not always consistent with their teleofunctional interests. Even if we
were to say that Maude “had a preference” in smoking it would still be the case that smoking
really is not in her interests in that she would actually be systemically harming herself regardless
of whether she had a psychological preference to smoke or not.
So on this understanding we can say that Maude might have a preference in smoking, but
she does not have an preference interest in smoking.
With this information in mind I propose the following definition of a preference
interest.
X has a preference interest in Y (Y is a preference interest of X’s) if and only if X
intends to bring about Y and Y is good for X where “Y is good for X” means that:
1) if X were not denied Y then X would not be systemically harmed by Y and 2) if X
were denied Y then X would be non-systemically harmed.
Given this definition of a preference interest we can construct a definition of interests that
unifies our understanding of both preference interests and teleofunctional interests, one that can
also handle the case of Maude. This definition is the following.
X has an interest in Y (Y is an interest of X’s) if and only if Y is good for X where “Y is
good for X” means that:
1) X has a teleofunctional interest in Y or 2) X has preference interest in Y where a) if X
were not denied Y then X would not be systemically harmed by Y and b) if X were
94
denied Y then X would be harmed non-systemically.
This definition would claim that Maude does not really have (non-psychologically) an
interest in smoking because the proposition “Smoking is good for Maude” means that "Maude
has a teleofunctional interest in smoking or Maude prefers smoking where if Maude is not
denied smoking then Maude is not systemically harmed by smoking and if Maude were denied
smoking then she would be harmed non-systemically." The first disjunct of that statement is
false. Smoking is not a teleofunctional interest of Maude's because it causes her systemic harm.
The second disjunct of that statement is also false because on the above definition Maude does
not have a preference interest in smoking. She does not have a preference interest in smoking
because if Maude is not denied smoking then it is not the case that Maude would not be
systemically harmed. Maude would be systemically harmed. Since both of these disjuncts are
false, the entire disjunctive statement is false. Thus, it is also false that "Smoking is good for
Maude" which means that Maude does not have a preference interest in smoking which also
means that she does not have an interest in smoking.
There may also exist still further interests beside teleofunctional interests or preference
interests.
There exists another type of interest which also belongs to some, but not all, living things.
This type of interest belongs to beings which are capable of feeling pain or pleasure more
generally. Beings that are capable of feeling pain or pleasure are what I call "sentient beings"
110
.
110
The use of the term "sentient" here may be somewhat non-standard. Sentience is generally
defined as the ability to have some perceptual awareness. The Merriam-Webster dictionary
defines sentience as "the ability to feel, perceive or experience subjectively". But there can exist
some beings that might be capable of having some perceptual awareness but that are not capable
of experiencing pain. For example, jellyfish seem to have some rudimentary perceptual
awareness but they do not have experiences of pain. Nonetheless I will use the term "sentient
beings" in this dissertation to refer to those beings that can have experiences of pain or pleasure.
95
Sentient beings "have an interest" in avoiding experiences of pain and/or pleasure.
Most, if not all, psychological beings are also sentient beings. But not all sentient beings
are psychological beings because some sentient beings cannot experience the same kind of non-
systemic harm such as distress, anxiety, sadness, etc. that psychological beings can experience.
Nonetheless they can experience pain that is more commonly associated with being physically
harmed or damaged. For instance, some invertebrate animals are incapable of having intentions
or goals for various things yet are still capable of experiencing pain. Even though these beings do
not have preference interests, because they do not have desires, they do have interests in
avoiding pain
111
. They have an interest in not experiencing pain. I will call all instances of an
experience of pain "sentient harm" and instances of an experience of pleasure "sentient benefit".
Pain causes sentient harm to sentient beings. Sentient harm and sentient benefit are types of non-
systemic harm and non-systemic benefit respectively.
Let us call these kinds of interests, interests in avoiding pain, sentient interests. All
beings that are capable of experiencing pain or pleasure have a sentient interest in not
experiencing pain and a sentient interest in experiencing pleasure. All else being equal
experiences of pain are bad for them and experiences of pleasure are good for them.
Some living organisms are capable of having sentient interests and teleofunctional
interests, but not preference interests. A crab, for instance, has a sentient interest in avoiding
pain. It is good for the crab to avoid that pain.
112
But it also has a teleofunctional interest in
111
I'm using the term "avoid" here in non-psychological terms. Many animals that can
experience pain try to "avoid" it by behaving in various ways to get away from the perceived
source of the pain. The ability to detect and perceive potential sources of pain is known as
"nociception". See, for instance, "Pain experience in hermit crabs" by Elwood and Appel, 2009.
112
Some might argue, however, that the crab "prefers" to avoid pain. This use of the term
"prefer" does not make reference to psychological states such as desires or intentions. On my
definition of what it means to have a preference, however, crabs do not have preferences because
96
keeping all of its legs intact. If one of the crabs legs were to be removed the animal would
experience systemic harm in the form of having one of its teleofunctional structures removed. It
would become less efficient at maintaining its own self-regulation.
Other living beings are capable of having teleofunctional, sentient and preference
interests. This is especially true for many of the higher forms of life. For instance, if someone
were to cut my hand off I would experience pain. I would experience the physical pain of having
a body part damaged. Thus I have a sentient interest in keeping my right hand. But I would also
experience some psychological distress or anxiety if my right hand were removed. I intend for
my hand to remain attached to my body. Thus, I also have a preference interest in keeping my
right hand attached to my body. But I also have a teleofunctional interest in keeping my hand
attached to my body. If my hand were cut off I would be the subject of a systemic harm in that
the removal of my hand would cause me to be less efficient at maintaining my own self-
regulation. I would, for instance, be less efficient at feeding myself or at managing other daily
activities.
Still other living things have teleofunctional interests but not sentient interests.
This is true of many of the lower forms of life found in nature that are incapable of
experiencing pain at all. I will refer to all beings that are incapable of experiencing pain or
pleasure as well as being incapable of having desires or preferences "non-sentient" beings.
Plants, for example, are non-sentient beings. They are incapable of experiencing pain or of
intending various states of affairs to come about. So these beings cannot have sentient interests
nor preference interests. But they do, however, have teleofunctional interests. In fact all living
they do not have desire-like psychological states. In order to have a preference one must be a
psychological being.
97
things have teleofunctional interests.
With the final addition of sentient interests we can further amend the above definition of
interests. This unified definition of interests is the following.
X has an interest in Y (Y is an interest of X’s) if and only if Y is good for X
where “Y is good for X” means that:
1) X has a teleofunctional interest in Y or 2) X has preference interest in Y where
a) if X were not denied Y then X would not be systemically harmed by Y and b) if
X were denied Y then X would be harmed non-systemically or 3) X is not a
psychological being and Y brings about an experience of pleasure for X.
For the remainder of this chapter I will refer only to teleofunctional interests and
specifically only essential, teleofunctional interests. All teleofunctional systems, including all
living things have essential, teleofunctional interests. These systems are all comprised of
numerous, teleofunctional structures that must function properly if those systems are to maintain
their own self-regulation and avoid systemic harm. In the next chapter I will address the question
of whether any of the interests mentioned in the above unified definition are also morally
considerable.
III. Artifact Inclusion
As I have previously documented, some biocentrists what to argue that all artifacts cannot
have interests. Given Delancey’s systems-based account of teleofunctions we can then inquire as
to whether that account will serve a biocentrist's attempt to ground the existence of interests for
all living things while at the same time excluding them from human-designed artifacts.
It turns out that it cannot.
Delancey himself thinks that it is possible for there to exist other teleofunctional systems
besides living organisms such as human artifacts that can have interests. But he argues that since
living organisms seem to be the only, or at least the primary, examples of teleofunctional
98
systems in existence biocentric individualism should still hold and that there is no need to invoke
a broader "teleocentric individualism" that acknowledges the interests of all teleofunctional
systems be they biological or not. In a footnote he writes,
"...we might best amend [sic] the term biocentric individualism to something like
“teleocentric individualism,” [my emphasis] but since I argue...that there are as
yet no known nonbiological systems with the kind of complexity that I believe is
needed for interests, my concern remains biological organisms, and I continue to
use the established term of biocentric individualism." (Delancey, 2004, p. 173)
I argue that this basic position, although advanced for perhaps pragmatic reasons, cannot
ultimately be maintained.
The systems-based approach allows that some possible future artifacts could be regarded
as having interests if those artifacts are teleofunctional systems. While it is true that many
currently-existing, human-designed artifacts are nowhere near as complex as even the simplest of
living creatures, and thus could not be regarded as teleofunctional, it is true that many artifacts
could have numerous, structures and subsystems that perform teleofunctions that contribute
toward their self-regulation. Thus, human-designed artifacts could become complex enough to be
teleofunctional.
The prospect of future-designed technologies makes it more probable that even greater
levels of complexity, and quite possibly teleofunctional complexity, can be achieved by human
beings. As such there can be no fundamental difference between a possible, future
teleofunctional artifact and a living thing when it comes to the question of whether they would
both be possessors of teleofunctional interests. Delancey himself recognizes this when he writes,
“There is no in-principle distinction between plants and any possible artifact. But
it is a contingent fact that there is no earthly artifact that is as complex in the
appropriate ways as even the most basic organisms. The self-regulating features
of even our most complex machines are incredibly simple compared to those of a
bacterium. The greatest successes of AI fail to manage to recreate the autonomy
and motor competency of a small insect arguably even of a single-celled
organism…it is empirically true that there is a profound difference between a
99
plant and any present human artifact; however, the difference is merely
contingent, since future artifacts might be so complex…I consider it acceptable
that some future machine, with highly complex self-regulating capacities, may
have teleofunctions [my emphasis]. Furthermore, note that the criterion that
appears to rule out artifacts in the evolutionary etiological account the ability to
self-reproduce is one which future artifacts may have…It is not that an
exogenous [my emphasis] cause for the existence of some structure rules out its
operation being a teleofunction” (Delancey, 2004, p. 184)
The criteria that Delancey advances for identifying teleofunctional systems could
reasonably apply to artificial, biological systems, such as “synthetic organisms”, to non-
biological systems, such as sophisticated robots, or to naturally-evolved organisms.
For instance, take the example that Delancey uses of the mouse “heated to 200°
centigrade”
113
. It is possible for us to independently identify the range of temperatures that a
naturally-selected mouse can tolerate. We know that mice cannot tolerate such thermal
conditions. But we could do the same thing for a sophisticated teleofunctional robot’s central
processing unit. We can independently identify the ranges of temperatures that it can tolerate too.
We know that both the robot and the mouse cannot tolerate being heated to that temperature. We
could do the same thing for a lab-designed, artificial mouse, one that is biologically identical to a
naturally-selected mouse. A synthetic mouse that mimics natural mice in every way is just as
subject to the damage of a 200° C fire as a non-synthetic, naturally-selected mouse. Hence, we
can independently and objectively identify the environmental conditions that are good for any
teleofunctional system be it an artificial cell, a sophisticated robot or a naturally-selected living
thing.
According to Delancey, a teleofunctional system must be complex so that it can maintain
its own internal, self-regulation. There are some currently-existing, designed systems that fit that
113
See the previous quote from Delancey on page 7 of this chapter.
100
description. An example of such a system is a high-wattage amplifier. Amplifiers are designed in
accordance with the known laws of physics regarding electricity, conductivity,
electromagnetism, etc. to be capable of maintaining their own internal temperature. Many high-
wattage amps are capable of generating enough heat to damage their own internal components.
As such they require the assistance of mounted fans that switch on and off in response to these
conditions. The fan cools the interior of the amp which in turn keeps the internal circuitry of the
amp functional which in turn keeps the fan operating properly. If these parts are damaged the
amp will not function properly.
But are systems like amplifiers really teleofunctional? Most likely Delancey would not
think so. Although designed contrivances such as amps are arguably simple and unsophisticated
compared to complex, living organisms, they nonetheless illustrate the prospect that
teleofunctional capacities could exist for possible future-designed systems.
Let us take it for granted, however, that there simply are no currently existing human-
designed artifacts endowed with what Delancy calls “highly complex self-regulating capacities”.
For instance, some may say that objects such as amps are ‘complex’ in some sense but not
‘highly complex’. That is they are not complex enough to be teleofunctional.
114
114
Delancey footnotes Ernst Nagel as providing an example of a system that is obviously not
complex but that does maintain the equilibrium of a parameter (and, thus seems to be
“homeostatic” to some degree). Nagel writes,
“When a ball at rest in hemispherical bowl is displaced from its equilibrium, restoring forces
come into play that in the end bring the ball to rest at its initial position. Is this a goal-directed
process, whose goal is the restoration of equilibrium?...On purely “intuitive” grounds, however,
the answer to the question just raised is negative an answer that is also in accordance with the
orthogonality requirement. For the controlling variables of the ball’s motion are not independent
of each other, since the restoring force is proportional to the magnitude of the displacement
force, though oppositely directed” (Nagel, 1977, p. 274).
But the amp case doesn’t seem to suffer from this counterexample. The variable of the fan’s
speed is not proportional to the variable of the amount of heat generated by the amps internal
components. So does the amp pass Nagel’s test?
101
What follows from this? Well, it may be argued that even if it turns out that currently-
existing technologies are not as complex as even the simplest of bacteria, it does not follow that
future-designed artifacts will not be so. Furthermore, the only thing that matters from a systems-
based perspective is that designed artifacts could in principle be that complex and thus would
have teleofunctional interests in their teleofunctional structures performing their teleofunctions
even if no currently-existing artifact is complex enough.
115
In any event what this means is that the biocentric individualism that Delancey is
advocating is based on a rather contingent fact that at the moment there simply aren't other
systems, besides living organisms, that happen to be teleofunctional. The basic problem is that
Delancey's systems-based account of teleofunctional interests cannot exclude possible, future
designed artifacts as bearers of interests. As such a consistent position must ultimately be one of
"teleocentric individualism" regardless of the current contingent fact that living organisms seem
to be the only teleofunctional systems in existence. In other words a position of teleocentric
individualism holds regardless of whether living organisms at the moment happen to be the only
instances of teleofunctional systems. The advocate of the systems-based view would do better to
simply say "I believe that all teleofunctional systems have interests. Thus I am a teleocentric
individualist. However, the only systems that at the moment qualify as teleofunctional systems
are living organisms."
This means that if the systems-based account were true the biocentrist would no longer be
able to limit the discourse of what has, or could have, interests to living things. They must give
up their allegiance to biocentrism. Biocentrism must give way to some kind of teleocentric
115
Later in this chapter I will address the issue of the role that complexity plays in accounting
for teleofunctional interests.
102
individualism.
IV. Replacing the term "Biological Functions" and "Biological Interests" with
"Teleofunctions" and "Teleofunctional Interests"
At this point I will argue that we should simply dispense with the term “biological” when
referring to the functions that all living things have an interest in and instead simply to refer to
teleofunctions as the functions that all living things have an interest in.
All teleofunctional systems, including all living things, have essential, teleofunctional
interests in avoiding systemic harm. But, not all teleofunctional systems are biological systems.
Most of us might be willing to accept the proposition that an artificial cell is a “living”
thing. But, the claim that a sophisticated, teleofunctional robot should likewise be considered a
“living” thing might seem a bit odd to some. Sophisticated robots are not biological beings. They
do not possess DNA, are not made of complex proteins and do not engage in cellular respiration.
And because of that it seems improper to call their interests and their functions biological. If
teleofunctional robots were to exist, they would have essential, teleofunctional interests.
116
As
such we can easily imagine a teleofunctional robot losing its ability to regulate one of its own
physical parameters if one of its teleofunctional structures were removed or damaged.
However, some might want to suggest that even if sophisticated robots are not biological
beings they still might be regarded as "alive" in some sense.
117
They might claim that what
makes something “alive” is its behavioral complexity or how it interacts with its environment,
116
This should not be taken to mean that robots cannot have preference interests or sentient
interests as well.
117
Some, however, may want to claim that an artificially-produced system is not “natural” or
naturally-produced and hence is not "alive" on that basis. Only naturally-produced organisms can
be regarded as "alive". This line of argumentation is based on the claim that "natural" things are
superior to "artificial" things. I will discuss this claim in a later section of this chapter.
103
not whether it is a "biological" thing. Take, for instance, the following commentary from Ian
Steadman about a new development in robotic intelligence in which a Lego robot had been
programmed to behave like a living organism, the nematode Caenorhabditis elegans. He writes,
“Since 2012, coders and computer scientists have been collaborating on the
OpenWorm project to simulate the entire biological existence of a specific, very
small worm known as Caenorhabditis elegans. It's about capturing the life of this
worm in software: 959 cells and 302 neurons, running in silicon...sticking a
simulation of the worm's neurons into a Lego robot made it act like a C. elegans
worm…When we consider something to be "alive" we often look to a set of key
behavioural attributes that distinguish, say, a tree from the mountain that the tree
grows on. It [the robot] doesn't have cells, but it does respond to stimuli, and if it
had a solar panel to provide energy then it wouldn't be too different from a plant
[my emphasis]. Reproduction isn't that insurmountable a challenge, either, as
there are plenty of machines out there which can make their own replaceable
parts, or even of making superior parts to the ones that they themselves use”
(Steadman, 2014).
Steadman is suggesting here that the concept of “life” as opposed to “non-life” may not
simply be a matter of whether that thing has cells, proteins or even DNA for that matter. All that
is really needed for a thing to be counted as “alive” is an incredibly high number of integrated,
multi-functional structures that contribute to its self-regulation as evidenced by its behavioral
ability to interact with the environment in characteristic ways. To put it yet another way,
something is "alive" if it is a teleofunctional system.
118
The above concerns regarding what is “alive”, and what is not, have implications for
whether we should call the teleofunctional interests of sophisticated robots “biological” interests
or something else entirely. I take it that while future sophisticated robots might someday be
regarded as “alive” by many, it does not make equal sense to call them biological beings.
118
It is sufficient to count something as alive if it is a teleofunctional system. This should not be
interpreted to mean that being a teleofunctional system is a necessary condition for something to
be alive. A disembodied spirit, for example, might be regarded as "alive" even though it is not a
teleofunctional system.
104
Likewise, it would not make much sense to call the kind of interests that they have biological
interests.
119
Robots are not “biological” in the everyday understanding of what that term means.
Robots do not possess DNA, they are not made of proteins, lipids or complex carbohydrates,
they do not metabolize sugars and they do not perform any of the other integrated biological
functions we normally associate with most, biological entities. It is not, however, farfetched to
think that sophisticated teleofunctional robots might one day exist that are, or could be, regarded
as "alive" at some future time.
120
In any event it is really beside the point whether artificial cells or sophisticated,
teleofunctional robots are regarded as "alive" by us. The main point is that these would have
teleofunctional interests because they are teleofunctional systems.
For these reasons I will henceforth refer to the interests that belong to all teleofunctional
systems, including all living things, as teleofunctional interests. Likewise, I will regard the kinds
of functions that the teleofunctional structures of teleofunctional systems can perform as
teleofunctions.
V. Criticisms of a Systems-based View and Some Responses
Gary Varner has made some criticisms against the proposition that artificially-designed
systems could have interests.
Varner argues that while artificially selected functions could end up replacing some
119
Although, as I have mentioned previously, robots could possibly have preference interests or
sentient interests.
120
Regardless of the current status of robotics research I will show in section VII of this chapter
that the current status of artificial life research suggests that the prospects for future, forms of
synthetic life are genuine.
105
biological functions, only naturally-evolved living things can have interests. Artificially-
designed systems, according to Varner, cannot have interests. Varner claims that this is true
because artificially-selected functions are simply not as numerous as naturally selected functions.
The vast majority of functions that exist in the natural world belong to naturally-selected living
things. Artifact functions are only a very small fraction of those functions that a living thing
could have.
121
Hence, artifact functions don’t pose a real challenge to the view that only
naturally-selected functions are what living organisms have interests in. He claims that
artificially-selected functions are,
“a very limited sort…neither selective breeding nor currently foreseeable genetic
research constitutes a significant challenge to the claim that all and only living
organisms have biological interests, where these interests are identified with the
fulfillment of the biological functions of their component subsystems and where
these functions are in turn identified using a standard
122
etiological account.”
(Varner, 1998, p. 70).
Varner gives an example of what such a limited case of artificial selection looks like. A
good example of an artificially selected function is the large breast muscles of selectively bred
turkeys. Varner writes,
“...suppose that a strain of domestic turkey is produced with breast muscles so
large that they cannot fly...In such a case I admit these turkeys’ breast muscles
have lost their original biological function due to selective breeding...in such a
case, it is true that the breast muscles have in the process acquired an artificial
function. Farmers’ getting more profit out of each turkey is a consequence of the
turkeys’ having larger breast muscles, and the larger breast muscles are there
precisely because farmers wanted more profitable turkeys.” (Varner, 1998, p.70).
The large breast muscles exist in these turkeys because their ancestors were selected by
breeders for their large muscles. And the turkeys that have large breast muscles have them
121
Note, that a previous objection to the existence of artificially-designed teleofunctional
systems is that they are not as complex as biological systems and their functions. This objection
is different. This objection claims that artificially-selected functions are not as numerous.
122
By “standard” here I take it that Varner means a natural selection or evolutionary account.
106
because that selected, desirable trait was possessed by their ancestors.
Although Varner writes of such cases of artificially-selected functions as being “very
limited” he, is silent on the question of whether such cases might constitute an actual biological
function, one that would be of interest to an individual living thing. However, if we have nothing
more to go on than Varner’s own definition of biological interests and his above argument we
would have to say that he would deny that any artificially-selected function could be a function
that a living thing could have an interest in.
The first problem with this kind of defense is that according to Varner’s own criteria we
would have to say that the artificially-bred turkey really would have a biological interest in
having large breast muscles because it has (under Varner’s own definition) a function that was
acquired under the conditions needed to have a biological function.
123
So whether an
artificially-bred turkey has a function that was brought about by artificial selection, as opposed to
natural selection, is irrelevant when it comes to the question of whether such a turkey would
have an interest in that function.
The second problem with this kind of defense is that in principle artificial selection, or
design, could bring about structures that fulfill the same functional role
124
that naturally-
selected structures do. Whether artificially-selected functions are as numerous as evolved
functions is really beside the point. Delancey illustrates this problem with the following thought
123
Although Varner admits that the turkey has an artificially-selected function that replaces a
biological function he does not admit that the turkey has a biological interest in that function, nor
does he admit that the turkey’s artificially-selected function should be counted as a biological
function.
124
Recall that teleofunctions are, according to Craig Delancey, “biological purpose[s] and other
kinds of normative functions” (Delancey, 2006, p. 69). So, teleofunctions, biological purposes,
normative functions and proper functions all describe what the functional purpose of some
structure is. For purposes of my discussion these terms are roughly synonymous.
107
experiment:
“Suppose two strains of an organism arose, one which was bred [artificially
selected] to have a structure which enabled and motivated it to exhibit behavior
B, and one which by sheer chance evolved [naturally selected] a structure which
enabled and motivated it to exhibit behavior B. There is no reason to suppose that
the structure in the former has no teleofunction, while the latter does, when they
could have no relevant internal differences” (Delancey, 2004, p.179-180).
That is, artificially-selected structures can be just as teleofunctional as those structures
that arose from some undirected process of natural selection. Both are appropriately
teleofunctional in Delancey’s terms and both have teleofunctional structures. And both would
have a teleofunctional interest in those structures performing their teleofunctions.
Sune Holm also criticizes Varner’s etiological account of interests for the same sort of
reason. He thinks that Varner’s account ignores those artificially-selected functions that for all
appearances really are, or would be, in the interest of the organism that has them. He poses the
following thought experiment:
“Consider Arto, an artefactual
125
organism
126
produced along the lines
suggested by protocell researchers, except that it has not been programmed to do
anything, but is able to survive and reproduce in a petri dish by virtue of having a
physical boundary delineated by a membrane, the capacity to transform energy
and grow (a metabolic network inside the boundary), and a genome that controls
metabolism and enables replication. One of Arto’s traits is its membrane, which
plays a crucial role for Arto’s survival and reproduction because it acts as a
selective filter that allows only certain kinds of matter to enter and exit the
cell…Imagine that at some point Arto’s membrane is “damaged” in such a way
that it is no longer able to control the inflow and outflow of matter to the degree
required for Arto’s survival, including Arto’s capacity for maintaining the
membrane itself. The aetiological
127
theory [of Varner] entails that Arto’s
125
The term “artifact” can be spelled as either ‘artifact’ (the American spelling) or ‘artefact’
(the British spelling). The term ‘artefactual’ is similarly synonymous with the American spelling
of ‘artifactual’ which is similar in some regards to the term ‘artificial’. I will use the spellings
“artifact” and “artifactual” interchangably throughout this dissertation. For a discussion of these
different spellings see http://www.world widewords.org/qa/qa-art1.htm.
126
In the next section I will argue that synthetic organisms pose other problems for natural
selection-etiological accounts of interests.
127
The word ‘aetiological’ is an alternative British spelling while the typical American spelling
108
membrane would not have a biological function because Arto is an organism
whose parts have not been shaped by natural selection, even if, in a purely
descriptive sense, this is what it does. This means that, according to Varner’s
theory, Arto does not have a biological interest in the filtering of matter by its
membrane…Since Arto’s membrane does not have “filtering” or any other effect
as its biological function, it is not a case of biological malfunction [my emphasis]
when it ceases to have that effect” (Holm, 2012, p.535-536).
128
Arto, does not have structures with biological functions because Arto did not evolve from
an ancestral population. Arto has no ancestors. Hence, Varner would have to say that it cannot
have a biological interest in its membrane performing that function.
But this doesn’t mean that Arto doesn’t have an interest in its membrane performing that
function. If anything it looks as if Arto’s biological integrity really is, or at least would be,
frustrated under conditions of malfunction or damage to its membrane. Damaging Arto's
membrane is bad for it. So given that Arto has its own complex, self-regulating organization, and
this organization is teleofunctional in nature, it has a teleofunctional interest in its teleofunctional
structures performing the jobs that they do.
129
John Basl, a critic of a systems-based account of interests, holds the view that if
something has interests it also must have some kind of coherent, selection etiology.
130
The title
as ‘etiological’.
128
Although Arto has a design etiology, Holm uses the example of Arto to show that his non-
etiological approach can cover cases of teleofunctional interests for both artificially-produced
living things and natural living things. Holm does not use the example of Arto to show that Arto
has interests because of its design etiology.
129
This should not be construed as implying that all structures of designed systems, including
designed forms of life, must have teleofunctions. Arto, for example, could have been designed to
produce a reddish hue by inserting a gene into it that makes a red protein. The red protein
performs the function of making the cell appear red. But the protein itself has no teleofunction.
The function of the red protein does not contribute to the other cellular processes of Arto that are
integral to its continued self-regulation.
130
Not to be confused with a natural selection etiology. Here Basl simply means to refer to
etiologies that involve some kind of selection process whether it be natural selection or design.
109
of his article, “Nothing Good Will Come from Giving Up on Aetiological Accounts of
Teleology” succinctly describes his position. This article, written in response to Sune Holm’s
organizational account
131
of interests, claims that etiologies are crucial for identifying whether a
thing has interests.
132
Holm and Delancey, on the other hand, maintain that etiologies are not
needed in order to determine whether a system has interests.
Basl provides two criticisms of Holm’s non-etiological view.
First, he responds to Holm’s claim that "instant organisms" could have interests.
Holm suggests that "instant organisms" are useful in illustrating why etiological accounts
of interests are insufficient and he references the example of “Swampman” as presented in
Donald Davidson's article “Knowing One’s Own Mind”. In it Davidson considers the prospect of
an instantly generated being (Swampman) with no apparent selection etiology whatsoever.
Swampman is a complex “instant organism.” Davidson writes,
“Suppose lightning strikes a dead tree in a swamp; I am standing nearby. My
body is reduced to its elements, while entirely by coincidence (and out of different
molecules) the tree is turned into my physical replica.
133
My replica, the
131
An “organisational account”is roughly the same thing as Delancey’s non-etiological
“systems-based account”. As Holm writes, “According to the organisational approach, the
teleological and normative dimensions of biological function ascriptions are analysed in terms of
the organisational features of organisms and not with reference to their origin in natural
evolution.” (Holm, 2012, p.536-537). Holm’s organisational account of biological interests is
that “Non-sentient organisms have a biological interest in X if and only if X contributes to the
organism’s self-maintenance.” (Holm, 2012, p. 538).
132
The etiological accounts that concern Basl are selection, etiological accounts. Basl does not
use the term "selection, etiological account" and he does not draw a distinction between selection
etiological accounts and non-selection, "instant organism" type of etiological accounts. Selection
etiological accounts involve some kind of causal history of selection to account for the existence
of a thing and its functions. But this should not be interpreted to mean that "instant organisms"
have no etiology. They do have an etiology. Their etiology is one of a singular, random event
rather than a causal history of selection.
133
Davidson’s use of the term “replica” here should not be construed as meaning that some
causal process was at work in generating Swampman out of some mechanism that replicates
Davidson. It, however, should not be construed in that way because there is no causal connection
110
Swampman, moves exactly as I did; according to its nature it departs the swamp,
encounters and seems to recognize my friends, and appears to return their
greetings in English. It moves into my house and seems to write articles on radical
interpretation. No one can tell the difference” (Davidson, 1987, p. 443)
Holm argues that Swampman is just as much of a challenge to a natural selection
etiological account of interests as is Arto. Swampman has no selection etiology yet appears to
have various interests. Swampman breathes, walks, homeostatically regulates its own body
temperature, and can track down its own food. The processes that allow it to pursue these goals
and goods are just as intricately and teleofunctionally connected as any of the processes that take
place in the body of a normal human being. And if Swampman were to acquire a disease that
shuts down its liver then it would be reasonable to say that its life would be endangered.
But on a natural selection etiological view it seems as if we would have to say that
Swampman has no interests in its structures performing their functions because none of its
structures have proper functions or Varnerian "biological functions". Its structures were not
inherited from a previous ancestor. On this view Swampman could not have a malfunctioning
liver because it doesn’t have a liver that has functions to begin with. Swampman's liver performs
various functions but it does not have those functions. Thus, Swampman cannot have an interest
in the performance of functions that its “liver” has.
134
Basl, however, does think that instant, conscious beings, such as Swampman do have
between Swampman’s physical body and Davidson’s body. Swampman just happened
coincidentally to be the same thing as Davidson in terms of its physical resemblance to
Davidson.
134
The claim I am making here is not that Swampman is morally considerable, but only that
Swampman has interests. As I will address later, the question of whether a thing has interests and
the question of whether a thing has interests that are morally considerable are two separate
questions. The natural selection-etiological view claims that Swampman would not have
biological interests and hence it could not be morally considerable by recourse to biological
interests. On this view Swampman does not have biological interests because it does not have a
natural selection etiology.
111
interests that would make it morally considerable, even if these interests are not, in Varner's
terms biological. He writes,
“…it is worth noting that instant organisms with a psychology will have as much
claim to psychological interests [my emphasis] as any other similarly constituted
organism. This means we shouldn’t be turned off by thinking that it won’t be bad,
for example, to torture an instant or swamp “dog” because the dog lacks
biological interests. That just isn’t so.” (Basl, 2012, p. 545).
In other words, the reason why it would be wrong to torture an instant, swamp “dog” or
Swampman is not because they have Varnerian, biological interests, but because they have
preference interests or sentient interests.
While such a response allows instant, sentient forms of life to count as having interests, it
does not allow instant, non-sentient beings to have interests. For Basl, such instant beings,
despite all appearances to the contrary, would not have interests.
We should remember, however, that biocentrists defending the concept of inherent worth
claim that all living beings have interests and not just sentient ones. So, if they believe that any
instant organism is a living being, and that all living beings have interests, then they must reject
the specifically etiological view of interests as endorsed by Basl. Hence, Basl’s response here is
not likely to satisfy them.
But, Basl’s second criticism of Holm is more interesting and noteworthy. This criticism
attempts to draw a parallel between instant, non-sentient organisms and what he calls “instant
artifacts” in order to show that all non-sentient entities produced by an "instant organism" type
etiology do not have interests. He writes,
“I think a similar example having to do with artifacts is equally, if not more,
compelling. It is the purpose of or end of a clock to tell time; there are things that
promote that end and things that frustrate that end. However, let’s imagine that
while digging through a box of gears in search of a tool I had lost I throw a series
of parts behind my head that, completely by chance, fall into place in an order that
gives rise to something identical to a clock (perhaps a sun-dial is more probable).
This “instant clock” is not a clock at all. It is not teleologically organized to tell
112
time. Its failing to be wound does not frustrate the end of telling time; it has no
such end. Insofar as in both cases teleology is grounded in a selection process,
instant organisms are like instant artifacts [both lack any kind of selection
process]; they both lack teleological organization and, thereby, interests” (Basl,
2012, p. 545).
Basl’s argument is basically the following:
1) If instant non-sentient organisms can have interests, then instant artifacts also
can have interests.
2) But instant artifacts, such as ‘instant clocks’, cannot have interests.
3) Therefore, instant non-sentient organisms cannot have interests.
I want to argue that Basl is incorrect regarding the claim that all artifacts produced by an
"instant" or haphazard etiology
135
do not have interests. Let us look more closely at Basl’s
instant clock thought experiment.
Basl wants to say that the instant clock has no interests. On the face of it this seems to be
a reasonable conclusion. However, even if we were to grant that the instant clock does not have
interests, it would still be a factual matter as to whether any randomly-generated object could
have highly integrated and complex teleofunction(s) which contribute to its overall self-
maintenance. If there were to exist such a complex and integrated instant “clock” we would be
able to recognize when its spring (for instance) ceased contributing to the clock's ability to tell
time. We would be able to make that determination even if that “clock” were not particularly
complex at all. Whether a clock has interests should be a matter of its level of complexity and
integration, not how it was produced. But if we are not concerned about the level of complexity
that this clock has we would have to say that it has interests.
For many of us the claim that clocks could have interests seems rather strange. The
reason why we might be skeptical of such a claim may have more to do with our normal
135
Again, when Basl talks about an etiology he is really talking about a selection etiology of
some kind, an etiology that selects a structure for the purpose of performing a particular job.
113
understanding of what clocks are. Most clocks, if not all clocks, do not possess the requisite
degree of teleofunctional complexity and functional integration that could make them true
interest bearers. They are much less complex that even the simplest of living things. Recall that
on the systems-based view an entity with an interest is one that has a high enough level of
complexity so that its structures contribute to its self-regulation and in which the larger system in
turn contributes back to the further functioning of those very structures.
For example, Swampman has an interest in possessing a "heart" that performs the
functions of pumping blood because the pumping of blood by that structure contributes to its
self-maintenance in a highly integrated and complex way. Swampman’s other teleofunctional
structures (also supported by its "heart") in turn contribute to the maintenance of that same
structure. Clocks, on the other hand do not have teleofunctional structures that are integrated in
that way. A clock’s spring, for example, conduces to the further function of its ability to tell
time, but the clock itself does not contribute back to the maintenance of the spring. On a
systems-based view an instant clock can have interests only if it were to have functions that work
together in numerous, complex ways to contribute to its self-maintenance which in turn
contributes to the future functioning of its own structures.
Swampman, although a product of sheer chance, has very complex functions that are
conducive to its continued self-maintenance. There is a non-trivial difference in functional
complexity between Swampman and an instant clock. However, this difference in complexity is
not brought out in Basl’s thought experiment. The functional processes that contribute to
Swampman’s self-maintenance and integrity run across multiple levels of organization that
support one another as well as the larger system. Swampman has organ systems comprised of
organs that are further comprised of tissues that are made up of cells that require their own
114
subcellular structures, etc. The higher one goes up the organizational hierarchy of Swampman
the more interconnected the various lower levels become. So for example, Swampman has an
interest in a having a "heart" that pumps blood because the pumping of blood circulates oxygen,
which in turn contributes to healthy muscle tissue, which in turn contributes to the formation and
sustenance of healthy heart muscle cells that in turn work collectively to pump blood. An instant
clock on the other hand is incapable of doing the myriad of physiological processes that
Swampman can. It cannot regulate its own internal temperature, cannot pump blood, cannot
metabolize sugar and has no sense perception. It cannot perform these multi-level functions
because it does not possess the relevant teleofunctional structures that enable such interactive
and self-supporting functions. It has virtually no complex teleofunctional processes in common
with living things at all.
My main objection to Basl’s instant clock argument is this. The reason why the instant
clock scenario seems to be a persuasive rebuttal to the view that instant non-sentient organisms
can have interests may (at least in part) be because the functional complexity of things like
clocks does not faithfully represent true teleofunctional complexity as is found in even the
simplest of non-sentient, living things.
Cases of instant, non-sentient organisms and instant artifacts need to take these
differences in complexity into consideration. To that end I propose the following thought
experiment that levels the playing field of teleofunctional complexity:
Imagine that a scientist, while rooting around in his reagent cabinet for a pipette,
haphazardly throws various vials of nucleic acids, peptides, lipids, enzymes and
carbohydrates randomly behind his head. As the vials hit the floor they break
spilling their contents onto the floor in random patterns. The chance mixing of all
of these chemicals generates an instant organism, “Instant Arto”. Instant Arto is
a single-celled living organism that has the exact same amount of complexity and
biological functionality as the original, lab-designed Arto. Both are capable of
significant self-maintenance and have various metabolic processes that are
115
independent yet partially-supportive of each other. The metabolic functions that
Instant Arto performs are the same for Arto.
Instant Arto has all of the same functions that Arto has except its functions came about by
an etiology of sheer chance as opposed to conscious selection. Yet despite their differences in
causal history they both seem to have the same teleofunctional interests in their structures
performing the functions that they do. Arto has a teleofunctional interest in its membrane
performing its teleofunctions. Instant Arto also has a teleofunctional interest in its membrane
performing the same teleofunctions. If either of their membranes were to be punctured their self-
regulation would come to an end.
Thus, instant non-sentient organisms have teleofunctional interests that do not depend on
their etiology
136
. If we grant that both Arto and Instant Arto have teleofunctional interests it
must not be because of some selection etiology. That is, a natural selection etiology is not a
sufficient condition for something to have an interest. But, neither is a design etiology either. A
clock is surely designed but that fact alone has nothing to with whether or not it has
teleofunctional interests. The interests of instant organisms, of designed organisms, and of
naturally selected organisms, are grounded in the nature of the kind of complex, teleofunctional
systems that they are, not in how they were produced.
If we take the case of Instant Arto to be analogous to Basl’s case of the instant clock then
we should count both Instant Arto and the instant clock to be examples of ‘instant artifacts’
because they both were produced by the random movements of some agent or person as a causal
factor in their construction.
136
I will, however, argue that the possession of morally significant interests does depend on
etiology and that the moral significance of interests is tied to an etiological story involving the
intentions of one or more designers.
116
The problem with Basl’s thought experiment is that it doesn’t make a distinction in
teleofunctional complexity between the clock and the living cell.
137
We could ask the following
question as a means of clarifying the implications of Basl’s thought experiment: ”Is instant Arto
an instant artifact or an instant organism?” At first blush it seems reasonable to think that Instant
Arto is unlike any regularly-produced artifact that has ever been contrived by human beings. Its
high level of teleofunctional complexity suggests that we should instead put it in the category of
“organism” and not in the category of “artifact”. This is because most, if not all, current artifacts
are simply not as complex as organisms are. Hence, the distinction that Basl makes between an
artifact and an organism is off the mark.
But, there is another, more substantial reason for thinking that Instant Arto is not a true
“artifact”, but that Arto is.
Some might claim that an instant clock is not really an instant artifact at all because it did
not come about by the careful planning of a designer. They might claim that the instant clock
looks like an artifact but it isn’t really an artifact. Basl’s instant clock came about by the random
movements of a human being. But so did Instant Arto. There was no intentionality or design
involved in the production of either of them. An instant clock could just as well have been
produced by the random movements of gears brought together by a passing tornado. So why did
Basl insist on calling the instant clock an instant artifact? The likely reason may lie in the fact
that we would normally think that an instant clock would have the same general level of
functionality, complexity and overall appearance as normal, human-designed clocks.
What we, of course, should realize is that a haphazardly-produced instant clock, however
137
This is not to suggest that complexity is the only thing that matters to what makes a system a
teleofunctional one. It is, however, a necessary condition.
117
similar it might be to human-designed clocks, is not designed at all even though some person
was involved in 'bringing it about'. The random movements of the gears and other parts that
eventually came together to make the clock were brought about by some person but those
movements were not directed by that person, in accordance with their intentions or plans for a
final end product. Genuine artifacts don’t come about that way. They are constructed on the
basis of some design plan. Hence, we should say that neither Instant Arto, nor an instantly-
produced clock should be regarded as artifacts in the true sense of the word since both were not
made in accordance with some plan or purpose.
Basl’s instant clock thought experiment, however, is meant to draw some parallels
between instant clocks and instant organisms as a means of implying that neither of them should
count as possessors of interests.
However, once we set aside the deceptive term “artifact” and instead focus on
teleofunctionality there remains a substantial difference between an instant clock and an instant,
non-sentient organism that can be appealed to in arguing that one, but not the other, has
teleofunctional interests.
In terms of their integrated, functional complexity they are not similar.
Instant Arto operates at a much higher level of functional complexity than an instant
clock. It is a teleofunctional system that has many more functionally integrated structures than
normal artifacts that human beings routinely produce
138
. If anything, Instant Arto is more like
Swampman and less like an instant clock in this regard.
But Basl’s instant clock scenario hides this difference. The argument seems to undermine
138
However, the prospect of human beings routinely generating living organisms would
undermine this normal view of what biological designers are capable of.
118
the systems-based account of function by suggesting that an instant organism is like an everyday
artifact in a significant way when in fact they are not.
This kind of oversight has also made its way into other arguments against non-etiological
views regarding proper functions or functional norms. For instance, Ruth Millikan and Karen
Neander have directed their criticisms toward Cummins’ non-etiological account of functional
analysis.
139
These criticisms are similar to Basl’s in that they claim that non-etiological
accounts of functions can impute functional purposes to very simple systems that by most
appearance have no functional purposes at all.
Holm is up front about this kind of trouble for his own non-etiological view. He writes,
“Perhaps surprisingly, the organisational account also claims that flames are
teleological systems. By virtue of causing the combustion of gasses in its vicinity,
a flame continues to create the conditions under which it is capable of performing
that very activity…there are certain effects that a cell or a flame [my emphasis] is
supposed to [my emphasis] bring about in order for it to persist” (Holm, 2012, p.
537).
Millikan and Neander do not address the question of whether simple systems can have
interests. Rather they think that simple systems, such as flames, cannot have structures that
perform proper functions.
140
The critiques from Millikan and Neander claim that a systems-based approach to
functions cannot account for proper functions because it unduly allows for problematic cases
such as clouds, flames or geological plate movements to count as structures that have proper
functions, or in Delancey’s terms, teleofunctions.
This leaves the defender of the systems-based account open to the charge that instant
139
Cummins is regarded by many to be one of the first defenders of the account of systemic-
capacity functions which is very similar to Delanceys systems-based account.
140
As a reminder, many biocentrists think that having interests requires the possession of
structures that have proper functions.
119
organisms, instant clocks, clouds and flames could have structures that perform proper functions
or have proper teleofunctions. The problem for the systems-based view, it is argued, is that
virtually any system that has some self-sustaining function would turn out to have structures with
proper functions, even those structures that upon reflection don’t really seem to have functions at
all.
For instance, Millikan criticizes Cummins’ systems-based approach to functions in the
following way. She writes,
“…according to Cummins’ definition
141
it is, arguably, the function of [my
emphasis] clouds to make rain with which to fill the streams and rivers, this in the
context of the water-cycle system, the end result to be explained being, say, how
moisture is maintained in the soil so that vegetation can grow. Now it is quite true
that, in the context of the water cycle, clouds function to produce rain, function as
[my emphasis] rain producers: that is their function in that cycle. But in another
sense of “function”, the clouds have no function at all – because they have no
purpose” (Millikan, 1989, p. 294).
In a similar vein Karen Neander argues that Cummins' approach allows geological plate
movements to count as having functions while everyday common sense suggests that they do not
have functions. She writes,
“According to one important theory of functions, they are causal contributions to
complexly achieved overall activities of the containing organism or system
(Cummins 1975). According to this theory, functions are relative to our interests,
and both the boundaries of the containing system, and which of its overall
activities we focus upon, will vary with our current concerns. Now instant
lions
142
could be analyzed as complex causal systems, in effect organized toward
the achievement of certain activities like hunting, consuming deer, birthing
cubs, and so on. So instant lions would have proper functions if this theory
accurately described what proper functions were. But note that this kind of causal
analysis can be done on any complex causal system (plate movements that
141
Cummins defines a function as, “x functions as a ϕ in s (or: the function of x in s is to ϕ)
relative to an analytical account A of s’s capacity to ψ just in case x is capable of ϕ-ing in s and A
appropriately and adequately accounts for s’s capacity to ψ by, in part, appealing to the capacity
of x to ϕ in s” (Cummins, 1975, p. 762).
142
I will address the problem of "instant organisms" for a systems-based account of interests in
a later section of this chapter.
120
culminate in earthquakes, intergalactic motions, for examples). So, this theory
bestows proper functions on instant lions only at the expense of bestowing them
upon a vast range of systems to which we do not normally attribute to them”
(Neander, 1991, p. 180-181).
143
I now argue that both Millikan and Neander have not taken the teleofunctional
complexity of relatively simple systems such as clouds and flames into consideration in their
criticism of a non-etiological view of proper teleofunctions. Things such as clouds or plate
tectonic systems are rather simple entities that exhibit very low levels of integrated complexity.
As such they cannot have the same kind of multi-functional integration that is needed for them to
have teleofunctional interests. A cloud simply isn’t complex enough in itself to count as a
teleofunctional system. That is, clouds and other simple entities like them, do not have interests
because they do not have numerous structures that are multi-functional and integrated.
In response to these kinds of criticisms Delancey writes,
“The systematic account will require that the relationships be complex [my
emphasis]; this will include that the various interdependent teleofunctions will be
of distinct kinds…the systemic account alone offers a clear explanation of how to
interpret these trivial or degenerate cases [cases such as instant clocks, clouds,
etc.] in such a way that they are not successful examples of a reductio ad
absurdum [his emphasis]” (Delancey, 2006, p. 85)
However, it could be reasonable to think that clouds might be capable of beings parts of
some larger, teleofunctional, atmospheric system. Clouds make rain, which in turn contributes to
providing moisture to the soil, which contributes to evapotranspiration, which contributes back to
cloud formation. But clouds don't just make rain. It might be argued that clouds are
multifunctional
144
not in the sense that they themselves have numerous, integrated,
143
One small note of clarification: The question of this dissertation, of course is not whether
lions (instant or otherwise) have functions, but whether the structures of lions have functions.
144
Multifunctionality, although a controversial prospect for things such as clouds or plate-
tectonic interactions, is not controversial at all when it comes to living organisms. The living
world contain a variety of structures and systems that make many different functional
121
teleofunctional structures, but in the sense that they can fulfill different teleofunctional roles
within a larger teleofunctional system. Clouds have many different functions. They regulate
global temperatures, recycle nutrients, influence whether patterns and regulate a whole host of
other atmospheric conditions. If clouds are functionally analyzed in this more comprehensive,
multi-functional context, rather than in the context of a simple water cycle, then perhaps they
could be conceived as being part of a teleofunctional system. The presence of their integrated
functions in that context could be used to argue that an entire atmospheric system could have
teleofunctional interests.
145
Mossio et al. in their response to critics of a systems-based view of interests differentiate
contributions to organisms and cells. As Christensen and Bickhard write,
“Empirical examples are not hard to come by. Amundson and Lauder point to the vertebrate jaw
as an example (1998). In hamsters the medial extended amygdala is known to play roles in the
control of sexual behavior, maternal behavior, grooming, and aggression (Newman, 1999).
Multifunctionality is highly prevalent in cellular physiology: A great deal of protein evolution
occurs through variations in the assembly of complex macromolecules out of pre-formed
subunits. In other words, just as a chair may be used either for sitting on or as a platform for
reaching a book on a high shelf, a particular protein domain that in type of enzyme acts to
catalyze and a digestive reaction may in another enzyme facilitate blood clotting…extracellular
signaling molecules typically act on multiple target cells and have different effect in each type of
target cell. Acetylcholine, for instance, acts in skeletal muscles cells to stimulate contraction, but
serves to decrease [his emphasis] the rate and force of contraction in heart muscle cells (Alberts
et al., 1989, p. 684)”. (Christensen and Bickhard, 2014).
Also, multifunctionality has been documented for some species as components of communities
or ecosystems. According to Roger Findlay, mycorrhizal fungi make multiple functional
contribution to the biotic community of which they are a part. Regarding his research Findlay
writes,
As we have acquired greater knowledge about fungal species diversity, so we have become
more aware of the potential functional diversity [my emphasis] of mycorrhizal fungi. The new
multifunctional perspective includes mobilisation of N and P from organic polymers, possible
release of nutrients from mineral particles or rock surfaces via weathering, effects on carbon
cycling, interactions with myco-heterotrophic plants, mediation of plant responses to stress
factors such as drought, soil acidification, toxic metals and plant pathogens, as well as a range of
possible interactions with groups of other soil microorganisms.” (Findlay, 2004, p.91).
145
This is simply meant to serve as a thought experiment. Whether or not an entire atmospheric
system really has teleofunctional interests is not a claim I wish specifically to defend.
122
teleofunctional systems from other systems that are not teleofunctional by means of appealing to
major differences in their “organisational differentiation”. They defend this way of thinking as a
means of determining whether simple systems such as flames can have proper functions. They
write,
“…functional attributions to components of the flame, as well as to all dissipative
structures, are not meaningful. It is for this reason, we argue, the we do not
attribute functions to simple forms [my emphasis] of self-maintaining systems,
whatever their material complexity may be…A self-maintaining system is
organizationally differentiated if it produces different and localizable patterns or
structures, each making a specific contribution to the conditions of existence of
the whole organization” (Mossio et al., 2009, p. 826).
Sune Holm also thinks that organisational differentiation and complexity can make a
crucial difference between objects that have teleofunctional interests and others that do not. He,
like Mossio et al., thinks that organisational differentation is what can allow the proponent of a
non-etiological view of interests to claim, on the one hand, that some, but not all, possible
artifacts can and should be regarded as having interests. He writes,
“To begin with, I agree that we should recognize that being an artifact does not
rule out having interests, but I think my organizational account does a better job
discriminating between artifacts that do and artifacts that do not have interests of
their own. While the organizational account does not exclude artifacts from
having interests of their own, as is clear from the case of Arto, it does not entail
that all [my emphasis] artifacts such as cars and parking lots have interests of
their own either. It thus avoids the apparently absurd consequence that a parking
lot can be said to have an interest in being cleared of snow, an interest that might
be frustrated even if there was no agents around who took an interest in using the
parking lot. Instead of claiming that all artifacts have interests, the organizational
approach can recognize that some, e.g. artifactual organisms and selfmaintaining
robots
146
, will have interests of their own. That is to say, the organizational
approach can accommodate future living technologies as bearers of interests,
without ascribing interests to hammers and anvils, because interests are generated
146
A good example of a present-day teleofunctional robot is the famous “PETMAN” from
Boston Dynamics. This robot can self-regulate its own movements in response to external forces
such as being pushed to one side. The robot “corrects” its stride in response to being pushed. For
more information see the article from Nelson et al. (2012) “PETMAN: A Humanoid Robot for
Testing Chemical Protective Clothing”.
123
by the organizational capacities of the entity, not by its origin.” (Holm, 2013, p.
248)
Before proceeding I wish to make a few additional comments regarding the conditions
necessary for a system to count as teleofunctional.
A system can have numerous structures in it yet not have teleofunctional interests. A
collection of items in a typical garbage heap, for example, has numerous parts to it. But garbage
heaps do not have structures that are functionally integrated in such a way that they contribute to
the self-regulation of the garbage heap. So having numerous structures, is only a necessary
condition for a thing to have teleofunctional interests. It is not a sufficient condition.
A system can be self-regulating yet also not have teleofunctional interests. There can
exist some things that have some degree of self-regulation yet not have interests. The “flame”
example from Neander above is a case where there exists something that is self-regulating in
some sense, but that doesn’t have teleofunctional interests. So, self-regulation is also a necessary,
though not a sufficient, condition for a thing to have teleofunctional interests.
Something can also be multi-functional or have structures that are multi-functional yet
not have teleofunctional interests. For example, a simple bowling ball could be regarded as
multi-functional. A bowling ball can be used as a doorstop, a paper weight, a ball bearing or a
weapon. But a bowling ball does not have interests. Also, multi-functional structures can be
integrated with other structures yet still not result in a system that has teleofunctional interests.
For example, a door has hinges that can serve multiple, different functions such as a plank for a
mouse trap. And a door contains a doorknob that could also be used as a paper weight or even a
weapon. Hinges and doorknobs are multi-functional. Both the hinges and the doorknob work
integrally to contribute to a functioning door. But this does not mean that the door itself has
teleofunctional interests.
124
VI. Criticisms of, and Responses to, "Artifact Interests"
Defenders of natural selection etiological account of interests, such as Varner, want to
exclude all artifacts as possessors of interests. They do this by making an etiological distinction
between naturally-selected functions and artificially-selected functions. They claim that only the
process of natural selection can generate biological functions and that living things can only have
interests in their structures performing their biological functions. They argue that processes of
artificial selection cannot generate structures that perform biological functions and hence the
living things produced by that process cannot have interests in their structures performing those
functions.
Advocates of the systems-based view, however, regard Varner’s natural selection
etiological approach to be insufficient in accounting for interests. As mentioned in the previous
chapter, Varner’s account, 1) allows for certain cases of living organisms to have biological
interests in a function that clearly is not in the organism’s interests (i.e. ‘oncomice’, etc.) and 2)
it does not provide a compelling defense against the criticism that some artificially-selected
structures (such as Arto’s membrane) can nonetheless still be regarded as being genuinely
functional (and, indeed, teleofunctional) and also in some living thing’s interest.
But biocentrists who want to switch to a non-etiological account of interests, must be
willing to accept the implication that even artificially-produced teleofunctional systems,
including artificial forms of life, can have interests. But if a biocentrist accepts that claim and
they also accept the claim that having interests entails having interests that are morally
considerable, then that biocentrist must also believe that artificial, teleofunctional systems have
inherent worth.
125
But many biocentrist do not believe that artificial systems can have interests that are
morally considerable. Thus, those biocentrists who believe that interests are inherently morally
considerable are not willing to accept the implication that teleofunctional artifacts have interests.
But why should a biocentrist be unwilling to accept that view? And more importantly
what is the motivation behind this unwillingness?
An answer lies in what John Basl has called a “central dogma” of environmentalism.
This dogma, endorsed by many environmentalists, claims that only natural things can
have interests. Artificial things cannot. This why many environmentalists favor natural selection
etiological accounts of interests. Natural selection is a natural process and those who favor
natural selection etiological accounts of interests think that living entities that are produced by
artificial means, i.e. have a design etiology, cannot have interests because they were not
produced by a natural process. Naturally-evolved living organisms are the only proper candidates
for moral value because they are produced by a natural process. John Basl claims that this dogma
of environmental ethics is grounded on the view that “…there is some fundamental difference
between artifacts and organisms such that the latter have goods or interests of their own that are
due moral consideration while the former do not” (Basl, 2012, p. 543).
The basic environmentalist argument against the claim that artificial forms of life can
have interests is something akin to the following:
1) Anything that is artificial is inherently inferior to what is natural.
2) Anything that is inherently inferior in this way doesn't have interests.
3) Thus, artificial forms of life do not have interests.
I will call this argument the "natural interests" argument.
In order to evaluate this kind of argument we need to address the question of whether
premises one and two are true. Premise one gives voice to the central dogma. So in evaluating
premise one I will in turn be evaluating this central dogma. If it turns out that the central dogma
126
is correct then we are still left with the question of whether premise two is correct. However, if
both of these premises are true then things that are artificially-produced cannot have interests. If
so, then much of what is typically regarded as artificial life simply cannot have inherent worth no
matter how much they might be "like" natural living things.
I will assess this argument by addressing premise two first.
Some environmentalists find the prospect of artificial life disconcerting. To them it is
another instance of anthropocentric tampering with the natural order. But as the technology and
the means to create various complex forms of synthetic life get more sophisticated, such
prospects have a greater chance of becoming reality.
147
Environmentalists might say that they find synthetic biology repugnant because it
involves the practice of consciously manipulating already existing living organisms for the
benefit of some human designer.
148
Synthetic biology treats these living organisms as a mere
means. Such a practice should be discouraged because it interferes with the goals and goods of
147
The ethical implications of synthetic biology are now being widely discussed. See
Gutmann’s 2011 article “The Ethics of Synthetic Biology: Guiding Principles for Emerging
Technologies.” as well as Schmidt et al.’s 2008 commentary SYNBIOSAFE e-conference:
online community discussion on the societal aspects of synthetic biology.” Many
environmentalists view manipulative ventures such as synthetic biology and GMOs to be
particularly risky. They say that these kinds of endeavors might lead to harmful forms of life that
cannot be contained. They say that synthetic biology violates the ‘Precautionary Principle”
which states that if there is some intended action in which the unknown but possible
ramifications could be catastrophic or dire, one should take much ‘precaution’ regarding that
action and not run headlong into that project without a deep awareness of its possible future
effects. That sentiment is captured by Schmidt et al. as
"We may think that we can accurately predict the consequences of our actions with respect to
living organisms - but history tells a different story. Hence a sensible degree of respect for the
precautionary principle should remain...Can we pull the plug? Can we stop our project before it
spirals out of control? That is an ethical question." (Schmidt et al., 2008, p. 8).
For a further discussion of the Precautionary Principle as it applies to synthetic life see Attfield’s
(2012) “Biocentrism and Artificial Life.”
148
Other environmentalists have argued that synthetic biology amounts to “playing God”. For
criticisms and discussions of that issue see Dabrock, 2009, van den Belt, 2009, and Link, 2013.
127
natural, living organisms. The practice of synthetic biology, according to these
environmentalists, is an inherently unethical tampering with the natural order. Hence, the
products of synthetic biology are inferior and likewise without moral standing.
However, even if one were to grant that the practice of synthetic biology routinely and
unethically manipulates existing living organisms, it is not true that manipulated forms of life are
likewise without interests. Forms of life that donate their DNA through genetic manipulation are
just as capable of being helped or harmed as the manipulated recipients of that DNA.
Consider the following thought experiment:
A research scientist wants to see if one bacteria, “B”, can acquire another
bacteria, “A’s”, ability to rapidly metabolize sucrose. A can metabolize sucrose a
little more rapidly than B can because of a gene that it has but that B does not
have. The scientist deletes B's sucrose metabolizing gene, removes A's sucrose
metabolizing gene, and then splices it into B's DNA. During the splicing process,
A is needlessly killed. The scientist could have kept A alive but instead he
carelessly punctured A's membrane just after its gene was removed. While the
gene from A is being inserted into B, B is neither harmed nor killed. The spliced
gene from A enables B to metabolize sucrose a little more rapidly than it could
before. It thus benefits from having A’s gene. Does B have an interest in having
A’s gene perform the function of rapidly metabolizing sucrose? It certainly seems
as if it does. B had interests before receiving A’s gene and B has acquired new
interests after receiving A’s gene. The fact that one of B’s interests came about by
an (arguably) unethical process of manipulating life in which A was killed
needlessly does not show that A did not have an interest before being needlessly
killed or that B itself does not have a newly-acquired interest after A's gene was
given to it.
On a systems-based view, designed artifacts with sufficient complexity and self-
maintenance could qualify as interest-possessors. Hence, even if some designed artifact were
brought about by an unethical process of manipulation, that in and of itself would not disqualify
that artifact from having interests.
This kind of argument also applies to cloned human beings.
149
A cloned human being
149
Many argue that the practice of human cloning is prima facie unethical. See the Council of
128
has just as many interests, needs, etc. as any naturally-produced human being untampered by the
hand of other human beings. A cloned human being has just as much ‘dignity’ as a "natural"
human being. As Bearnard Baertschi addresses this,
“…human dignity is not something that can be lost because of human
intervention; human dignity is an intrinsic value grounded on intrinsic properties,
and the properties relevant to the moral status of a child remain the same, be it
procreated by cloning or by sexual intercourse (or by IVF)” (Baertschi, 2012, p .
14).
This same kind of argument can be made for the claim that all artificially-produced
sentient beings have interests in avoiding pain. As Eliot Sober has recognized, most animal
welfarists think that sentient creatures, whether ‘natural’ or artificially-bred, are just as able to
feel pain hence they both have an interest in avoiding pain. He writes,
“…environmentalists think that the distinction between wild and domesticated
organisms is important, in that it is the preservation of “natural” (i.e., not created
by the “artificial interference” of human beings) objects that matters, whereas
animal liberationists see the main problem in terms of the suffering of any
organism domesticated or not” (Sober, 1986, p. 175).
150
But that is not all. An artificially-produced bacterium, for instance, has a teleofunctional
interest in its membrane serving as a selective barrier because if that membrane were damaged
the cell would be subject to a systemic harm. Having its membrane punctured is bad for it. Even
non-sentient, artificially-produced forms of life can have interests. An artificially produced
bacterium would have this interest regardless of whether it was made in the lab or evolved by
natural selection. As Ronald Sandler puts it,
“What is determinative of a nonsentient entity’s good (and a psychologically
Europe’s (1998) position, “…the instrumentalisation of human beings through the deliberate
creation of genetically identical human beings is contrary to human dignity and thus constitutes a
misuse of biology and medicine.” I do not wish to debate this issue only to point out that it is a
contentious one.
150
For further discussion of animal welfarism and the interests of sentient beings see also J.
Baird Callicott’s (1980) “Animal Liberation: A Triangular Affair.”
129
complex entity’s biological good) is whether and how they are teleologically
organized, not the mechanism by which they came to be that way. The
derivativeness of artifactual organisms that is, that they are the product of
human intentions or created to be used by us [my emphasis] does not justify
denying that they have a good of their own.” (Sandler, 2012c, p. 191).
Thus, any kind of living organism that was designed has just as many interests as their
equally-complex "natural" counterparts.
151
For the above reasons we can be fairly confident in thinking that premise two of the
"natural interests" argument is false. Even if something is made by an unethical process, that
does not mean that it has no interests.
Showing that premise two is false is enough to show that the "natural interests" argument
is unsound and hence does not pose a substantial challenge to the advocate of a systems-based
understanding of interests.
Nonetheless, I will address the problems for premise one next.
The root of many of the environmentalist's criticisms of synthetic biology is found in the
central dogma. Environmentalists, wedded to this dogma want to say that Holm's Arto, or cloned
human beings, or any other artificial forms of life are simply not eligible for moral consideration
under an environmental ethic because they did not come about by a purely natural process. For
them Arto is without interests not because it is without an etiology, but because it has the wrong
kind of etiology, an unnatural etiology that invokes a human designer.
For the purposes of clarifying our understanding of the central dogma I will provide an
overview of the various issues which bear on the natural/unnatural distinction that are of concern
to the environmentalist.
The project of synthetic biology, according to Christopher Preston “usurps” Darwinian
151
Whether those interests are morally considerable is another matter.
130
selection which, up until the advent of modern biotechnology, was the sole explanation for the
existence and form of all living organisms including their interests. He writes,
“The idea that synthetic biology usurps Darwin is true only in the sense that lab-
built organisms will henceforth exist that inherited none of their actual DNA
through Darwinian processes. In those specific organisms, Darwinian
explanations of the physical origin of an organism’s DNA will play no part. It is
in this very restricted sense that Darwinism is usurped. So the threat to Darwinian
processes is, at best, simply a threat to its ubiquity as an explanation for the
genomes of existing organisms” (Preston, 2013, p. 111).
152
Markus Schmidt, Malcolm Dando and Anna Deplazes echo the basic point that modern
synthetic biology has now made untenable the claim that naturally evolved DNA is the only kind
of DNA that can exist. They write,
"Those who think of naturally evolved DNA as an unalterable biological axiom
will be surprised by recent efforts to release life (as we know it) from its
evolutionary constraints." (Schmidt, Dando and Deplazes, 2011, p. 324).
This prospect is troubling to some environmentalists. Biocentrists, such as Varner,
believe that etiologies that invoke design processes, such as human manipulation, are not
etiologies that can generate interests because they do not invoke a purely natural process (such as
natural selection) to explain them. Somehow design etiologies just cannot generate living beings
with interests.
Many environmentalists think that the processes of human design are inherently suspect,
meddlesome and too different from natural processes to be regarded as praiseworthy. Bernard
Baertschi summarizes this view when he writes,
“Frequently, we hear claims about the goodness of what is natural and the badness
of what is synthetic, chemical or artificial. Such claims are in general not voiced
in relation to status, but to agency. Nature does good, but human beings do
152
Preston also writes that “…living organisms have until now enjoyed a category of being
entirely separate from machines” (Preston, 2013, p. 109). That is, synthetic biology invites the
view some “living” organisms can really just be sophisticated machines.
131
not
153
. Since ‘artificial’ denotes a mode of production and [his emphasis] its
product, the negative evaluation associated with the first contaminates the
second” (Baertschi, 2012, p. 10)
154
.
Hence, designers of artificial life cannot produce living things with morally considerable
interests because the manipulative hand of the designer has either compromised or corrupted the
“true” biological function that a living thing ought to have.
But what is it about synthetic biology that environmentalists object to? Presumably it is
because the teleofunctional capacities of living artifacts aren’t the result of a natural process. The
interests of these manipulated forms of life are ultimately just extensions of whatever some
designer’s interests were. Natural history’s relevance in determining what the normative
functions of what a living thing's structure are is threatened. Christopher Preston describes the
situation in the following way,
“These biotic artifacts [synthetic organisms] depart from a core principle of
153
An advocate of this negative view of man’s presence in the natural order is Jean-Jacques
Rousseau. In his book Emilie he writes,
“God makes all things good: man meddles with them and they become evil. He forces one soil to
yield the products of another, one tree to bear another’s fruit. He confuses and confounds time,
place, and natural conditions. He mutilates his dog, his horse, and his slave. He destroys and
defaces all things; he loves all that is deformed and monstrous; he will have nothing as nature
made it, not even man himself, who must learn his paces like a saddle-horse, and be shaped to
his master’s taste like the trees in his garden” (Rousseau, 2007, p. 6).
154
Baertschi mentions some examples as instances in which the natural/non-natural distinction
is used as a debating point in discussions of controversial environmental issues. These are: the
“classic medicine” vs “natural medicine” debate, the “GMO” vs “natural/organic farming”
debate and the debate over the moral status of biotechnological practices. Regarding the
biotechnology debate Baertshi writes,
“In a study concerning genetic engineering, Rob De Vries states that, in the Netherlands, 57 per
cent of the respondents think that biotechnology is non-natural, and consider that it constitutes a
problem; and these respondents were not lay people, but people involved in biomedical science”
(Baertschi, 2012, p. 10, see also De Vriend, 2006, pp. 218-220).
Another debate, not mentioned by Baertschi, is the debate of whether environmental mitigation
is best handled by human beings actively engaging in the restoration of damaged habitats [where
human beings try to “fix” an environmental problem of some kind] or whether humans should
take a completely ‘hands off’ approach to restoring environmental integrity, one in which nature
“fixes” itself.
132
Darwinian natural selection descent with modification leaving them with no
causal connection to historical evolutionary processes. This departure from the
core principle of Darwinism presents a challenge to the normative foundation of a
number of leading positions in environmental ethics. As a result, environmental
ethicists with a commitment to the normative significance [my emphasis] of the
historical evolutionary process may see synthetic biology as a moral ‘line in the
sand’…With the threat provided by these technologies looming, those for whom
the ideas of ‘nature’ and the ‘historical evolutionary process’ comes with any kind
of normative punch have some serious self-reflection to do.” (Preston, 2008, p.
23).
For many environmentalists the concept of ‘nature’, and of man’s apartness or
separateness from nature, provide grounds for the protection and valuing of natural living
things.
155
Aldo Leopold, one of the founders of modern environmentalism, claims that the
‘natural’ should start taking precedence in the lives of men over the ‘unnatural’ as a means of
focusing our conscience away from resource use and towards respect for the land. In 1949 he
writes, “Perhaps such a shift of values can be achieved by reappraising things unnatural, tame,
and confined in terms of things natural, wild, and free” (Leopold, 2013, p. 4). Accordingly, we
should regard the unnatural objects of man’s own creation and manipulation as being utterly
different and inferior to those things that comprise the “wild”.
Environmentalists such as Robert Elliot, Eric Katz, Bill Throop and Ned Hettinger all
argue in one form or another that a large part of the moral appeal to what is natural stems from
its independence from man. That is nature is valuable if it has not been blemished by the hand of
man. To put it another way, nature has value because it is independent from man and his
155
Some environmentalists think that anything that is natural has intrinsic value. The main
reason is that they claim that naturalness itself is the central, morally significant property that
makes a thing valuable. Teresa Kwiatkowska sums up this view when she writes,
“A central issue of various theoretical disputes and conservation/restoration practices revolves
around the ‘naturalness’ of living organisms, species or ecosystems. Many argue that natural
[her emphasis] things, whether they are organisms or inert mat[t]er, have intrinsic value that
obliges humans to morally consider plants, animals and ecosystems” (Kwiatkowska, 2008, p.88).
133
modifications. Elliot writes, “We value the forest and river in part because they are
representative of the world outside our dominion, because their existence is independent of us”
(Elliot, 1982, p. 86)
156
. Similarly Katz writes, “Value exists in nature to the extent that it avoids
modification by human technology” (Katz, 1992, p. 265). Hettinger and Throop write, “As we
use the term, something is wild in a certain respect to the extent that it is not humanized [their
emphasis]
157
in that respect” (Hettinger and Throop, 1999, p. 12).
158
Bill McKibben argues that the very idea or concept of nature is under attack.
159
He
claims that the emergence of all kinds of new human technology and of man’s widespread
156
To be fair, Elliot thinks that not all natural entities have value simply in virtue of their
naturalness. He does, however, think that naturalness can be a value-adding property among
other value-adding properties. He writes, “…within certain constraints, the naturalness of a
landscape is a reason for preserving it, a determinant of its value…naturalness is one factor in
determining the value of pieces of the environment” (Elliot, 1982, p. 87).
157
As an aside, Preston documents how this natural/unnatural distinction ultimately finds its
basis in an Aristotelian philosophy. He writes, “…environmental ethicists have put great stock in
the distinction tidily made by Aristotle more than two thousand years ago. Aristotle characterized
a natural object in The Physics as one which ‘has within itself a principle of movement and of
stationariness (in respect of place, or of growth and decrease, or by way of alteration’ (1925b8-
11) (Aristotle, 1941). Any change the object undergoes over time is determined from wholly
within the object’s nature…An artefact, by contrast, lacks ‘the source of its own
production…that principle is in something else external to the thing’ (192b28). The external
source to which Aristotle refers is the intentional action of a human” (Preston, 2008, p. 25). In
his book The Natural and the Artificial, Keekok Lee summarizes the Aristotelian view of the
‘natural’ as
“whatever exists which is not the result of deliberate human intervention, design, and creation in
terms of its material, efficient, formal, and final causes…The natural comes into existence,
continues to exist, and goes out of existence entirely independent of human volition and
manipulation…[B]y contrast, ‘the artefactual’ embodies a human intentional structure” (Lee,
1999, p. 82).
158
One might also wonder if the value that nature has really intrinsic value as opposed to some
relational or extrinsic value. If nature has value insofar as it is not humanized then the value that
nature has is one based on its relationship with man. But this would then mean that nature does
not have intrinsic value, but rather some sort of relational value. If nature had intrinsic value then
it would still have value independently of its relation to man and of man’s modification of it.
159
The title of McKibben’s book in which he argues for this view is entitled The End of Nature.
134
manipulation of the natural world, threatens the natural-artificial distinction. Due to man’s
presence such a distinction has become much more difficult to maintain
160
in that large portions
of the biosphere have already been tainted by man’s presence. As man exerts more of his own
control over nature, the autonomy and separateness of nature becomes more absorbed into this
new, artificial mode of existence. McKibben, thinks that the concept of nature means “the
separate and wild province, the world apart from [my emphasis] man to which he adapted and
under whose rules he was born and died” (McKibben, 2006, p. 41).
Another reason why environmentalists admire the natural is because the processes that
produced species, land, ecosystems, etc. are very old or primordial. Nature has a certain primeval
quality about it that should strike us a morally significant. Mountains, valleys, trees, rivers and
entire species are all beautiful and splendid works of the natural order that were produced by the
ancient, evolutionary processes that were at work long before man emerged on the scene and will
continue to work long after man is gone. Eugene Hargrove puts a finger on this admiration for
natural processes when he writes, “Nature aesthetically is not simply what exists at this point in
time; it is also the entire series of events [my emphasis] and undertakings that have brought it to
that point. When we admire nature, we also admire that history (Hargrove, 1989, p. 195).
Environmentalists also like to appeal to the natural as a means of calling others to
political action. Appeals to the natural tend to stir people up to speak out against those things that
threaten earth's integrity. Christopher Preston points out the place of the appeal of the natural to
political motivation when he writes,
“As a matter of political reality, the idea that wild nature is morally significant is
one that motivates millions. Images of polar bears prowling arctic ice-flows,
humpback whales breaching in front of snow-capped mountains, and lionesses
160
For analyses of the claim that synthetic biology further blurs the natural/unnatural distinction
see de Vriend, 2006.
135
lounging with their young on the African savannah adorn the walls of bedrooms
and boardrooms across the world. Denying the moral significance of the
biologically natural is almost inconceivable for environmentalists
161
” (Preston,
2008, p. 26).
It is for these reasons that many environmentalists view the works of nature and its
processes as awe-inspiring, original, authentic and pristine. The unnatural, on the other hand, as
typified by human manipulation or alteration, can only attempt to replace what nature has
already made or destroy it.
162
With this background in mind I will now argue that the central dogma of
environmentalism, what I also call the "natural/unnatural distinction" cannot be maintained.
Accordingly, premise one of the "natural interests" argument, like premise two, is false.
There are some serious difficulties for the environmentalist’s natural/unnatural distinction
as a means of separating what is good from what is bad.
First, there is a rather obvious difficulty with this distinction in that human beings really
seem to be just as much natural objects as nonhumans are. We, like the rest of the biological
world, are the products of natural selection and have our own natural history as a species.
Consequently, it’s reasonable to think that everything that man does is in some sense ‘natural’ or
an instance of natural processes of some sort. So, for example, when human beings design works
of art, make skyscrapers and manufacture designer drugs these activities take place within the
confines of the laws of nature that not only produced man but also his inclinations, abilities and
161
An example of this view comes by way of Holmes Rolston III. He writes, “"No one has
learned the full scope of what it means to be moral until he has learned to respect the integrity
and worth of those things we call wild" (Rolston 1979, p. 25). I take it that what Rolston means
by the term “wild” includes the “biologically natural” but it also includes non-biological entities
such as soil, water, etc.
162
Keekok Lee makes a distinction between those technologies that simply mimic nature and
those technologies that cause disruption or harm to the natural order. These are “nature-replacing
technologies” and “nature-polluting technologies” respectively. (See Lee, 1999).
136
desires to embark on them.
This is what Christopher Preston calls a ‘paradox’ for environmentalism. How is it
possible for man, who is himself a product of nature and natural forces, to embark on activities
that can nonetheless be called ‘unnatural’? Furthermore, how can the works of man as products
of these naturally-endowed abilities, be regard as ‘artificial’ as well? It ultimately doesn’t seem
as if they can be. In 1885 John Stuart Mill highlighted the problems for this way of thinking
when he wrote,
“Art is as much Nature as anything else; and everything which is artificial is
natural Art has no independent powers of its own; Art is but the employment of
the powers of Nature for an end. Phenomena produced by human agency, no less
than those which as far as we are concerned are spontaneous, depend on the
properties of the elementary forces, or of the elementary substances and their
compounds…The corn which men raise for food, grows and produces its grain by
the same laws of vegetation by which the wild rose and the mountain strawberry
bring forth their flowers and fruit…Even the volition which designs, the
intelligence which contrives, and the muscular force which executes these
movements, are themselves powers of Nature” (Mill, 1885, p. 7-8).
Likewise, in 1666 Robert Boyle suggested that this distinction was unwarranted when he
wrote,
“I know not why all the productions of the fire made by chymists [chemists]
should be looked upon as not natural, but artificial bodies; since the fire, which is
the grand agent in the changes, doth not, be being employed by the chymist, cease
to be and to work as a natural agent: and since nature herself doth, by the help of
the fire, sometimes afford us the like productions that the alchymist’s art presents
us” (Boyle, 1666, p.51)
Mill's and Boyle’s observations here puts the environmentalist’s distinction at risk.
163
In
addressing Mill’s analysis Christopher Preston writes,
“Mill’s recognition of this central paradox was just an early hint of a whole raft of
problems for environmentalists’ use of Aristotle’s nature/artefact distinction. The
163
Teresa Kwiatkowska also writes, “Anything that humans do is natural, no matter whether
better or worse. Warsaw skyscrapers are as natural as corrals feeding underwater off Australia
shores” (Kwiatkowska, 2008, p. 91)
137
distinction cannot do the work modern environmentalists want it to do.” (Preston,
2008, p. 26).
Second, even if one were to grant some version of the natural/unnatural distinction, there
seem to be many cases of human actions that are not only natural but actually good for the
environment. If we are to believe the claims of the central dogma then we should expect virtually
every human intervention in the environment to be unnatural and hence bad for the environment.
But this seems wrong too. There are a fair number of cases of human-designed artifacts that are
actually good for the environment. Not all human intervention in the environment is bad. The
problem is that there is considerable difficulty in finding some principled means for establishing
why one act, such as preserving a wetland, for example, should be regarded as ‘good’ while
some other act, such as damming a river for agricultural usage, should be regarded as ‘bad’.
Preston highlights this difficulty when he writes,
“…human intention is clearly responsible for creating some artefacts that are
environmentally harmful and others that are environmentally beneficial…A
restored wetland
164
or an landscape created by a prescribed burn are clearly
artefacts on Aristotle’s terms, likely containing more human planning and
theoretical sophistication than, say, a Walmart parking lot. Yet environmentalists
will advocate for the restored wetland and forests while campaigning against the
parking lot” (Preston, 2008, p. 26).
Also, human beings eat food and excrete wastes, but should we consider this to be
unnatural? It doesn’t seem to be. These activities are just as natural as the activities of snakes and
birds eating their food and excreting their wastes.
Third, the very definition of the term ‘natural’ is simply too ambiguous to be very
164
Manipulated ecosystems such as restored wetlands, conservation areas, etc. have the same
basic structure as unimpacted environs. According to Teresa Kwiatkowska “there is no evidence
that unaffected pristine, or heirloom ecosystems exhibit properties of structure, function, or
design, which differ from those of less ‘natural’ ones…the predicate ‘natural’ adds no new
information” (Kwiatkowska, 2008, p. 88).
138
helpful.
165
John Stuart Mill distinguishes between four different definitions of what natural
means in his essay “On Nature” (Mill, 1885). Teresa Kwiatkowska argues that when
environmentalists use the term ‘natural’ they are very prone to use it equivocally between all of
these different senses. If one is not careful to define nature with precision the term itself is likely
to become confused. In addressing Mill’s distinctions on the different definitions of nature
Kwiatkowska writes,
“In one sense, nature is simply the totality of existing things, everything in the
universe. In another, it is God’s handiwork, as distinct from humans, while in a
third; it is that which is independent of human influence or contrivance. The
fourth sense in which something can be natural is the sense of being authentic or
true to itself”…Each speaker abstracts ‘nature’ out of the blooming [sic] buzzing
confusion of myriads of encounters with whatever is actually out there”
(Kwiatkowska, 2008, p. 91)
Since each person uses the term ‘nature’ so differently the term itself is likely to become
ambiguous in normal discourse.
There is another reason to think that the program of producing artificial life is not entirely
unnatural, or unethical. This comes from an insight that Christopher Preston made regarding
man’s own history and his long-standing practice of manipulating nature. According to Preston,
man has been
“…creating biotic artefacts for thousands of years. The hybridization of crops and
the domestication of animals is a perennial thorn in the side of those wishing to
make deontological arguments against biotechnology” (Preston, 2008, p. 30).
How does the modern practice of synthetic biology substantially differ from the activity
of genetically-manipulating crops or animals? Furthermore, human beings have always
manipulated and rearranged the environment to some degree or other to suit their ends. So, why
should genetic manipulation be seen as "unnatural" or different? Preston further writes,
165
See Kwiatkowski's (2008) article “The Natural: So Ambiguous A Word.”
139
“Rearranging naturally occurring materials whether these materials be carbon
atoms or tree limbs, is something humans have been doing for millennia. Even if
nanotechnology aims to change nature by working at the level of the atom or
molecule rather than at larger, more familiar scales, it is not obvious why this
should have any particular moral import” (Preston, 2008, p. 29).
Finally, Elliot Sober has made the observation that not only is the effort to domesticate
living organisms ‘natural’ but so are all of the other instances of naturally-evolved living things
that exploit other species for their benefit. He writes,
“When we domesticate organisms and bring them into a state of dependence on
us, this is simply an example of one species exerting a selection pressure on
another. If one calls this “unnatural,” one might just as well say the same of
parasitism or symbiosis (compare human domestication of animals and plants and
“slave-making” in the social insects” (Sober, 1986, p. 180).
So, since human beings and all other living organisms on the planet are natural and
exhibit natural tendencies to use other living beings for their own ends, the natural/non-natural
distinction does not hold between human beings and other living organisms. Such a distinction is
arbitrary at best.
Michael Shellenberger and Ted Nordhaus sum up the problem for a central dogmatists
view when they write,
“The concepts of ‘nature’ and ‘environment’ have been thoroughly deconstructed.
Yet they retain their mythic and debilitating power within the environmental
movement and the public at large. If one understands the notion of the
‘environment’ to include humans, then the way the environmental community
designates certain problems as environmental and others as not is completely
arbitrary" (Shellenberger and Nordhaus, 2004, p. 12).
166
As such Steven Vogel exhorts environmentalists to simply give up on using the concept
166
Similarly, Elliot Sober writes, “It is the dichotomy between artificial (domesticated) and
natural (wild) that strikes me as wrong-headed. I want to suggest that to the degree that “natural”
means anything biologically, it means very little ethically. And, conversely, to the degree that
“natural” is understood as a normative concept, it has very little to do with biology” (Sober,
1986, p. 180).
140
of ‘nature’ altogether. He writes,
"I call for...an environmental philosophy that no longer employs the concept
nature. First the term is too ambiguous and philosophically dangerous and second,
McKibben and others who argue that nature has already ended are probably right
- except that perhaps nature has always [his emphasis] already ended" (Vogel,
2002, p. 23)
For these reasons the central dogma that animates much of the reluctance of
environmentalists to grant interests to designed teleofunctional systems including artificial forms
of life cannot ultimately be maintained.
It is for these further reasons that we should regard premise one of the "natural interests"
argument false. If the natural/unnatural distinction cannot be made then environmentalists must
find some other way of arguing that forms of synthetic life do not have inherent worth. Designed
forms of life can have genuine interests that are of biological relevance regardless of whether we
might happen to call the processes that generated them ‘natural’ or ‘unnatural’.
According to Basl, if synthetically-produced forms of life are possible, then they would
have interests too. He writes, “…there is no reason to think that the only aetiologies capable of
grounding teleology and thereby interests are natural selection etiologies…natural selection is
not necessary for teleological organization” (Basl, 2012, p. 544). So for Basl what makes it the
case that both Arto and, say, a butterfly have interests is that both of them are products of an
etiological process that specified their "teleological organization". He further writes,
“For my own part, I’m unsympathetic with the central dogma. I believe that
nonsentient organisms and artifacts are both capable of having interests or goods
and that those goods or interests are non-derivative in both cases” (Basl, 2012, p.
544).
Hence, for Basl, both a design etiology and a natural selection etiology are capable of
141
generating teleofunctional systems that have interests.
167
VII. The Status of Synthetic Life Research
Some biocentrists at this point might argue, "Okay, I will grant you the point that
artificially-produced living things can have teleofunctional interests. But, the prospect of actually
generating artificial forms of life is so far out of the domain of what is possible I don't need to
really worry about whether designed forms of life really would have interests."
This response might ring true for those environmentalists who see the entire field of
synthetic biology as perhaps a futile attempt to mimic anything as grand as what nature has
already made.
If the field of synthetic biology is some odd form of "fringe" science that has virtually no
prospect of successfully creating new, living things then perhaps we might agree with the
biocentrist and think that we shouldn't really be too concerned with the question of whether
artificial forms of life could have interests. After all, realistically they cannot exist!
If, on the other hand, it turns out that the field of synthetic biology is not a form of fringe
science, but an active research program that is well on its way to producing artificial forms of
life, then the reluctant biocentrist will indeed have to worry about whether these forms of life
have interests. She will have to consider this prospect whether she previously believed that such
forms of life were possible or not.
So what exactly is synthetic biology?
167
Basl’s acceptance of such a view puts him at odds with much of the demands of many
environmentalists. Later I will discuss design-etiologies vs natural selection etiologies in the
debate regarding interests of living organisms. That debate centers on the problem of synthetic
organisms like Arto.
142
According to Sune Holm, synthetic biology is the endeavor,
“...to develop the ability to rationally design and fabricate organic systems or
parts of such systems that have no natural counterparts [my emphasis]. Two
approaches are standardly distinguished: a top-down approach that aims to create
new forms of life by modifying extant life forms and a bottom-up approach which
aims to create living systems from nonliving materials (“from scratch”)” (Holm,
2012, p.532).
That is, synthetic biology attempts to design living things either de novo ("bottom-up") or
by taking some existing form of life and modifying it in some way so that it performs a novel
function ("top-down").
A good example of the bottom-up approach in synthetic biology comes from the
emergence of ‘protocells’ and protocell research. Protocells are created de novo by mixing
various organic and inorganic compounds together under very precise, laboratory-controlled
conditions. Bedau and Parke describe protocells this way:
“Protocells are alive; they are similar to single-celled organisms like bacteria, in
that they grow by harvesting raw materials and energy from their environment
and converting it into forms they can use, they sense and respond to their
environment and take steps to keep themselves intact and pursue their needs, and
they reproduce and ultimately evolve” (Bedau and Parke, 2009, p. 1)
Protocells, according to Holm, are a major step towards creating novel organisms that are
capable of basically doing everything that other cellular forms of life can do. If protocell research
is ultimately successful, we will have the emergence of artifactual organisms. These organisms,
according to Holm,
“will be self-assembling and self-organising systems which are complex enough
to instantiate crucial life processes such as metabolism, replication and the
capacity to evolve without relying on components of natural life forms” (Holm,
2012, p. 535).
Artifactual organisms like protocells are the result of a ‘bottom up’ approach to synthetic
biology while “synthetic organisms” are the result of ‘top-down’ approach.
The vast majority of current, synthetic biological research is of the top-down variety.
143
Biologists are readily capable of splicing, transcribing and translating DNA. They are capable of
removing and exchanging various other cellular components. And they are also capable of
synthesizing DNA and inserting novel genes into various forms of life. The inserted genes enable
the modified organism to perform new metabolic tasks such as “generating hydrogen for fuel or
capturing excess carbon dioxide in the atmosphere” (Holm, 2012, p. 532).
But top-down research isn’t just interested in making novel, individual genes. It is also
interested in synthesizing and creating whole new genomes.
168
A good example of a chemically
synthesized genome is found in the collaborative work of synthetic biologists from the J. Craig
Venter Institute.
169
These biologists sequenced the genome of a microbe, made a copy of it
themselves by chemical means
170
and then inserted that same genome into a living cell that had
its original genome removed (Gibson et al., 2010,).
171
But is it really possible for top-down research to create an entirely new form of life?
Consider these words form Michael Specter in a piece that he wrote for The New Yorker entitled,
"A Life of Its Own: Where will synthetic biology lead us". He describes one of Venter's
experiments in the following way. He writes,
"In the mid-nineties, Craig Venter, working at the Institute for Genomic Research,
and his colleagues Clyde Hutchison and Hamilton Smith began to wonder
whether they could pare life to its most basic components and then use those
genes to create such an organism. They began modifying the genome of a tiny
bacterium called Mycoplasma genitalium, which contained four hundred and
168
A genome is the entire sequence of nucleotides that is found in a living thing’s DNA.
169
Venter is also famous for being the first to sequence the human genome.
170
For example, these researchers use existing synthesized DNA sequences with known
properties in the synthetic process of constructing the genome. These sequences are known as
‘bio-bricks’.
171
Other authors have discussed synthetic biology’s prospect using DNA samples to re-create
either extinct forms of life or endangered forms of life. This topic is discussed in the ETC Group
(2007) report “Extreme Genetic Engineering” as well as by scientists from the Frozen Ark
Project; see www.frozenark.org.
144
eighty-two genes (humans have about twenty-three thousand) and five hundred
and eighty thousand letters of genetic code, arranged on one circular
chromosomethe smallest genome of any cell that has been grown in laboratory
cultures. Venter and his colleagues then removed genes one by one to find a
minimal set that could sustain life...Venter called the experiment the Minimal
Genome Project. By the beginning of 2008, his team had pieced together
thousands of chemically synthesized fragments of DNA and assembled a new
version of the organism. Then, using nothing but chemicals, they produced from
scratch the entire genome of Mycoplasma genitalium. “Nothing in our
methodology restricts its use to chemically synthesized DNA,” Venter noted in
the report of his work, which was published in Science. “It should be possible to
assemble any combination of synthetic and natural DNA segments in any desired
order.” That may turn out to be one of the most understated asides in the history
of science. Next, Venter intends to transplant the artificial chromosome into the
walls of another cell and then “boot it up,” thereby making a new form of life that
would then be able to replicate its own DNAthe first truly artificial organism.
(Activists have already named the creation Synthia.) Venter hopes that Synthia
and similar products will serve essentially as vessels that can be modified to carry
different packages of genes. One package might produce a specific drug, for
example, and another could have genes programmed to digest carbon in the
atmosphere." (Specter, 2009).
The top-down approach, though arguably not as ambitious as the bottom-up approach, is
genuinely capable of generating entirely new forms of life. Holm describes the prospect this way,
“…it is now possible for humans to initiate a lineage of cells with genomes
descending from a synthetic genome. An implication is that this will result in
organisms and forms of life that have never existed before, and depending on how
we draw the distinction between modifications of existing life and the creation of
entirely new forms of life, this may be technically true of [this research]” (Holm,
2012, p. 533).
That is, both entirely novel organisms, like protocells, and other forms of synthetic life
could be brought about by the practices of synthetic biology. Accordingly, the designers of these
forms of synthetic life would be capable of bringing about living, teleofunctional systems with
teleofunctional interests that nature up until that point did not produce.
In fact, the main drive behind much of synthetic biology research is to find ways of
creating new organisms that up until now natural selection had been incapable of producing.
Synthetic biology, as it were, seeks to direct the production of novel forms of life that could then
145
be used for various purposes. Synthetic biology, according to Christopher Preston, aims to
“create an entirely new organism with DNA constructed in its entirety according
to human plan. The products of synthetic biology do not borrow any genetic
function from genomes produced by the historical evolutionary process. To the
contrary, synthetic biology is guided by the idea of leaving evolution and existing
genomes behind in order to do a better job of creation with human goals in mind.”
(Preston 2008, p. 33).
Given that protocells have already been synthesized in the lab along with the success of
Venter's research program it is a genuine possibility that future scientists will bring about new
forms of life that up until that point had not been produced by natural means. Synthetic biology
is not an odd form of fringe science with no prospect of success. On the basis of its current status
synthetic biology is capable of making artificial organisms that would be exemplars of novel
teleofunctionality. They would be teleofuncional systems capable of having teleofunctional
interests.
In any event, even if the prospect of artificial life turns out to be a failure. It would still be
true that if such forms of life were to exist they would have teleofunctional interests.
VIII. Conclusion
In this chapter I have attempted to show that a systems-based account can be successful
in explaining how all teleofunctional systems, most notably all living things can have
teleofunctional interests. This approach to understanding what would be a living thing's interest
adequately represent teleofunctional interests as a matter of a system's overall, internal
organization. This account would claim that any appropriately teleofunctional system will have
teleofunctional interests. Artificially produced teleofunctional systems, naturally-selected
teleofunctional systems, "instant" teleofunctional systems all have teleofunctional interests
because of their internal organization.
146
I have also attempted to show that attempts to keep designed, teleofunctional artifacts off
of the list of interest possessors all fail. Artificially produced, teleofunctional systems have
teleofunctional interests in the same way that naturally-selected, teleofunctional systems do.
In the next chapter I will attempt to address the question of what could make the interests
of all living things morally considerable and whether, in the final analysis, all living things have
interests that are morally considerable.
147
CHAPTER FOUR
The Moral Considerablity of Interests
In the previous chapter I attempted to show that a systems-based account of interests is
quite capable of explaining how all living things can have interests. A systems-based account of
interests would claim that any system that has numerous, interconnected teleofunctional
structures that all contribute to the self-regulation of it is also a system that has teleofunctional
interests.
I also attempted to show that living artifacts can have just as many teleofunctional
interests as their naturally-selected counterparts. It is just as “good for” a designed
teleofunctional system to be able to regulate itself as it is "good for" a naturally-evolved
teleofunctional system to be able to regulate itself. I have also attempted to argue that the
possession of teleofunctional interests requires the possession of numerous, multi-functional
structures that contribute to a thing’s self-regulation. Those structures that are integrated, multi-
functional and contribute to the system of which those structures are a part are teleofunctional
structures. The possibilities for artificial life as well as insights from the systems-based account
have raised the prospect that teleofunctional interests can belong to all teleofunctional systems
regardless of their etiology.
However, just because these teleofunctional systems all have teleofunctional interests it
does not necessarily mean that those teleofunctional interests are also morally considerable. As
Sune Holm writes, “…the fact that the organisational approach entails that inorganic systems are
teleological
172
systems that have interests need not [my emphasis] commit us to the claim that
172
The use of the term “teleological” here by Holm simply means that inorganic systems
(systems that are not carbon-based) can be teleofunctional.
148
these interests are morally considerable” (Holm, 2012, p. 540). That is, should it turn out that
some teleofunctional system (in this case a teleological “inorganic system”) has interests it is a
separate question as to whether its interests are morally considerable.
Varner, on the other hand, claims that anything that has biological interests automatically
has interests that are morally considerable. But, as I demonstrated in chapter two, there are good
reasons to think that not all naturally-selected biological functions count as functions that would
be in the interests of the individual organism.
In the first section of this chapter I wish to stress the importance of the moral standing for
non-sentient living beings for biocentrism. In this section I will provisionally grant that the
teleofunctional and sentient interests of sentient beings are directly morally considerable
independently of etiology. Interests that are directly morally considerable are ones that give the
possessor of those interests direct moral standing. Likewise I will grant that the preference
interests of rational agents are directly morally considerable independently of etiology too. As
such all conscious agents and sentient beings are granted to have interests that are directly
morally considerable independently of their etiology.
In the second section I will address the question of what could make it the case that non-
sentient teleofunctional beings can have directly morally considerable teleofunctional interests.
Key biocentrists think a sufficient condition for a non-sentient being to have directly morally
considerable interests is if it has a "goal of its own". These goals are directly morally
considerable because they are self-directed goals. If there exists a being that has these self-
directed goals then other agents have direct moral obligations to these beings not to harm them.
In the third section I will address the question of what would be a necessary condition for
a non-sentient teleofunctional being to have a goal of one's own. I will argue that a necessary
149
condition for having a goal of one's own is having teleofunctional structures that have
teleofunctional purposes. Non-sentient beings that do not have teleofunctional structures with
teleofunctional purposes are not one's that can have a goal of their own.
In the fourth section I will address the question of whether a non-etiological, systems-
based account is capable of showing that the teleofunctional interests of non-sentient beings is
morally considerable. According to a systems-based view a non-sentient teleofunctional living
thing has an interest in its structures performing their teleofunctions because of the internal,
functional role that its structures play in the self-regulation of it. Etiological explanations for how
those structures acquired their teleofunctional purposes or functions are not required. I argue that
under a systems-based view there can exist some cases of teleofunctional organisms that have
teleofunctional interests that are not morally considerable because there can exist some cases
teleofunctional beings that do not meet a necessary condition for having a good of its own
namely the condition of having teleofunctional structures that have teleofunctional purposes.
The systems-based account cannot discriminate between organisms that have that necessary
condition for having a good of their own and those that do not have that necessary condition. As
such I conclude that the systems-based approach cannot reliably be used as a means of
identifying which living things have morally considerable interests and which ones do not. While
the systems-based view of interests opens up the possibility that teleofunctional interests can
belong to any appropriately complex system, it fails in providing explicit guidance on the
question of just what could make the teleofunctional interests of non-sentient beings morally
considerable.
Recall that in chapter two I presented some background information on four possible
150
categories of etiologies for the existence of living things.
173
They were 1) a natural selection
etiology, 2) an agent-selection non-design etiology, 3) a design etiology and 4) an “Instant
organism” etiology.
In the fifth section I will address the question of whether non-sentient beings produced by
an "Instant Organism" etiology can have a good of their own and thus have directly morally
considerable teleofunctional interests. An "Instant Organism" etiology is one in which some
teleofunctional system was brought about by an undirected, instantaneous natural event that
occurred by happenstance or a series of such events. I will argue that the teleofunctional interests
of instant organisms are not morally considerable. In short, organisms produced instantaneously
do not have structures that have teleofunctional purposes. Hence, their teleofunctional processes
are not ones that can be labeled as malfunctioning. Hence, no moral agent can cause these
teleofunctional systems to malfunction. Hence, their teleofunctional interests are not morally
considerable.
In the sixth section I will address the question of whether non-sentient, teleofunctional
being produced by an agent-selection, non-design etiology could have a good of their own and
thus have morally considerable teleofunctional interests. This etiology is one in which some
agent is involved in the selection history of a complex, teleofunctional system but in which there
is no actual directing, planning, forethought or design taking place by that agent.
174
This
etiology cannot produce non-sentient, teleofunctional beings that possess morally considerable
teleofunctional interests for the same reason that an "instant organism" etiology cannot produce
non-sentient being that possess morally considerable teleofunctional interests. This etiology
173
See also Figure 1 from chapter two.
174
As a reminder see the example of “Tom’s rainwater collector” from chapter two.
151
cannot produce non-sentient, teleofunctional beings that have structures with teleofunctional
purposes.
In the seventh section I address the question of whether a natural selection etiology can
produce non-sentient teleofunctional beings that have structures with teleofunctional purposes. I
will argue that a natural selection etiology cannot produce such organisms because it cannot
select some teleofunctional structure for performing a teleofunctional task. As such, non-sentient
teleofunctional beings produced by natural selection cannot have a good of their own because
they lack structures that have teleofunctional purposes. Consequently, naturally selected
teleofunctional interests of non-sentient, teleofunctional beings are not morally considerable.
Thus, a natural selection etiological account of interests cannot succeed in showing that all
naturally-selected, living things have inherent worth.
In section eight I take up the task of analyzing those arguments put forward for the claim
that natural selection can generate non-sentient teleofunctional beings that have their own goals
or a good of their own for reasons other than the claim that they have structures that have proper
functions or functional purposes. Some claim that the process of natural selection is capable of
generating non-sentient beings that have a good of their own because the process of natural
selection is guided by some directionality toward an ultimate Aristotelian "telos" or final end or
that nature itself has its own kind of purposefulness or preordination. I argue that these claims
are inconsistent with the basic Darwinian view that life is the result of an unguided process of
natural selection acting on random variation. As such the claim that natural selection is
inherently teleological is false.
In the ninth section I consider the question of whether genes have some kind of inherent
tendencies or goals that they seek to bring about. I argue that this claim is not support by
152
biological data and that naturally-selected "genetic interests" in reproduction are not always in
the interests of the individual organism.
In the tenth section I turn to a discussion of what the naturalistically-minded biocentrist
must face if they accept the view that all living things arose by the process of natural selection.
Here I argue that such a biocentrist cannot argue for the claim that all living things have a "good
of their own" and as such they must appeal to some other reason for why we should think that
naturally-selected, non-sentient teleofunctional beings have morally considerable interests.
In the eleventh section I argue that all non-sentient living things simply do not have goals
of their own. As such they do not have interests that are directly morally considerable.
In the twelth section I argue that while non-sentient living things do not have goals of
their own it is not true that their teleofunctional interests cannot be morally considerable.
Although their teleofunctional interests are not directly morally considerable they can still be
indirectly morally considerable. Their teleofunctional interests can confer upon them some kind
of indirect moral standing if their teleofunctional interests are the subject of a rational agent's
preference interests.
In the thirteenth section I address the question of whether all naturally-selected non-
sentient living things could be guaranteed to have teleofunctional interests that are indirectly
morally considerable. I argue that they would not because there is little reason to think that
human beings are capable of having such preference interests in the teleofunctional interests of
all non-sentient living things.
I then conclude with a brief recap of the chapter.
I. Granting Morally Considerable Interests to Conscious Agents and Sentient Beings
153
In chapter three I made a distinction between three different kinds of interests. They are
1) preference interests, 2) sentient interests and 3) teleofunctional interests. Many living
organisms have all three of these interests. Others have both sentient interests and teleofunctional
interests. Still others only have teleofunctional interests. But all living things, whether sentient or
not, have teleofunctional interests. All living things are comprised of numerous interconnected
parts that work together for their self-maintenance.
Typical examples of living things that have all three interests are human beings, primates
and many other mammals. These are beings that have preferences for various states of affairs,
can feel pain and have numerous interconnecting parts that all work together for their self-
maintenance. Examples of living things that have both sentient interests and teleofunctional
interests include such beings as insects and various other invertebrates. These beings have
various forms of sense perception and also are comprised of numerous interconnecting parts that
all work together for their self-maintenance. Examples of living things that have only
teleofunctional interests are plants, single-celled organisms and sponges among others.
In order for the biocentrist to show that all living things have inherent worth they must be
able to show that teleofunctional interests are morally considerable.
175
That is, they must show
that teleofunctional interests provide a reason for why all moral agents should care about
possessors of those interests non-instrumentally. It must be shown that these interests are ones
that we, as moral agents, must take into account when deciding what the proper treatment of the
beings that have those interests should be. A biocentrist project that attempts to show that all
living things have inherent worth cannot succeed unless this requirement is met.
175
As a reminder, I provide a definition of inherent worth in section VII of chapter one. In
short, something has inherent worth if it has interests that provided a reason to care about it non-
instrumentally.
154
For the purposes of this dissertation I will grant that both sentient interests and preference
interests are morally considerable independently of etiology. This is not an unreasonable
concession. Most of us would probably think that it is just as wrong to torture or maim an
"instant dog" as it is to torture or maim a naturally-selected dog. Both of them can equally feel
pain. It seems reasonable to think that both of these animals have sentient interests in avoiding
pain that confer upon them some degree of direct
176
moral standing and respect. Likewise most
of us probably think that violating another being's preference interests is prima facie wrong
regardless of how those beings came about
177
and that their preference interests give them some
degree of direct moral standing too. One reason to think that preference interests are morally
considerable is because preventing some other being from fulfilling their desires or wishes
strikes many of us as being morally impermissible.
178
Likewise, it would be just as wrong to
176
It is direct in that sense that we have obligations to these beings not to cause them to feel
pain for no good reason.
177
Conscious agents are prime examples of beings that have preference interests. But this
should not be interpreted to mean that they are the only beings that can have preference interests.
It looks as if many types of animals are capable of having preference-like states such as goals or
purpose. For example, Tyler Burge has commented on the existence of apparently goal-directed
behavior of spiders in the genus Portia. These spiders have the ability to make plans and change
routes when tracking down prey. Regarding these spiders Burge writes, "There is substantial
evidence that Portia can set and hold in memory a detailed route [to capturing prey]. Following
the route often involves extensive detour behavior. Portia commonly forages in a jungle tangle of
branches and vines. In such an environment, detours are often necessary." (Burge, 2010, p. 515)
178
Some might object to the notion that violating someone's preference interests would
necessarily cause that person to be unhappy. For instance, a person could have a very slight
preference interest in not having the bumper of their car scratched by another person. But having
their bumper scratched wouldn't cause this person any significant unhappiness. Hence it seems
like preference interests, if violated, don't necessarily result in unhappiness. This is probably
because very slight or 'weak' preference interests (such as this person's interest in not having
their bumper scratched) are not significant contributors to a person's happiness. On the other
hand, 'significant' or 'strong' preference interests would cause a person to be unhappy if violated.
Still someone could reasonably argue that even if a person has a very weak preference interest
that violating that preference interest would cause that person to experience some unhappiness
(however slight it may be) that they would not have otherwise experienced.
155
thwart the intentional plans of an instant, rational agent (such as "Swampman") as it would be to
thwart the intentional plans of a naturally-evolved human being. Both beings have their own
plans and intentions that confer upon them some degree of moral standing and respect.
For non-sentient beings, however, it is not true that if their teleofunctional interests are
violated then their sentient interests are also violated. After all they have no sentient interests to
violate! Also, non-sentient beings certainly cannot make plans or have intentional states like
conscious agents can. So if their teleofunctional interests are violated their conscious plans and
intentions cannot be violated either for the same reason. They have no intentional states. Non-
sentient beings such as plants or single cells can be systemically harmed. But they cannot
experience pain, nor can they make conscious plans that can be frustrated.
In order for the biocentrist's project in showing that all living thing have inherent worth is
to succeed it needs to show why the teleofunctional interests of non-sentient living things should
be regarded as morally considerable that is as providing reasons for why they should be cared
about non-instrumentally.
II. A Sufficient Condition for Having a Morally Considerable, Teleofunctional Interest
To that end we should ask whether the teleofunctional interests of non-sentient beings
are, like preference interests and sentient interests, morally considerable to the extent that they
confer direct moral standing to non-sentient beings. If their interests are morally considerable
independently of etiology then we do not need to assess whether any of the various etiological
options presented in chapter two are relevant to their moral status. They would have moral
standing independently of their etiology. But if the moral considerability of their interests is
etiology dependent then we need to address the question of what necessary conditions these
etiological options must fulfill in order for non-sentient beings with teleofunctional interests to
156
have morally considerable teleofunctional interests.
So why should we think that the teleofunctional interests of non-sentient beings are, or
could be, morally considerable? What condition, if any, would make the teleofunctional interests
of non-sentient beings ones that all moral agents should take into account?
A good place to start is by examining what reasons other biocentrists have offered in
defense of the claim that non-sentient beings, particularly plants, have morally considerable
interests, the kind of interests that give them moral standing.
179
Paul Taylor has argued that if some being can be meaningfully said to be harmed or
benefitted then it has moral standing even if it cannot consciously value its own good. Taylor
argues that all living things are the kinds of subjects that can either be benefited or harmed.
Consequently, we should take their interests into account regarding our treatment of them.
180
179
The kind of moral standing that Paul Taylor has in mind is direct, moral standing. Direct
moral standing is that moral standing that belongs to beings that we have direct obligations to.
On this view, for example, we would have an obligation to a tree not to harm it because it has
interests that give it direct moral standing.
As a side note others think that all living things have moral standing that is minimal. On this
view if something has minimal moral standing then its interests should be taken into account
where they deserve some basic, or minimal, level of moral regard. It is minimal in the sense that
beings with this moral standing qualify for a degree of moral respect that is just enough to regard
them as beings that ought not to be harmed especially if those beings are doing no harm to other
beings or impeding their interests. The minimal level of moral standing is best expressed by what
Kenneth Goodpaster calls “regulative moral consideration” which is distinct from what he calls
“operational moral consideration”. He writes,
“It seems to me that there clearly are limits to the operational character of respect for living
things. We must eat, and usually this involves killing (though not always). We must have
knowledge, and sometimes this involves experimentation with living things and killing (though
not always). We must protect ourselves from predation and disease, and sometimes this involves
killing (though not always). The regulative character of the moral consideration due to all living
things asks, as far as I can see, for sensitivity and awareness [my emphasis], not for suicide
(psychic or otherwise). But it is not vacuous, in that it does provide a ceteris paribus
encouragement in the direction of nutritional, scientific, and medical practices of genuinely life-
respecting sort.” (Goodpaster, 1978, p. 324).
180
Taylor did not specifically endorse the view that non-sentient beings had interests per se but
that they had a “good of their own” which gives them moral standing. As I have argued
157
He writes,
“Concerning a butterfly, for example,…we would probably deny outright that it
values [my emphasis] anything in the sense of considering it good or desirable.
But once we come to understand its life cycle and know the environmental
conditions it needs to survive in a healthy state, we have no difficulty in speaking
about what is beneficial to it and what might be harmful to it. A butterfly that
develops through the egg, larva, and pupa stages of its life in a normal manner,
and then emerges as a healthy adult that carries on its existence under favorable
environmental conditions, might well be said to thrive and prosper…Once we
acknowledge that it is meaningful to speak about what is good or bad for an
organism as seen from the standpoint of its own good, we humans can make value
judgements from the perspective of the organism’s life, even if the organism itself
can neither make nor understand those judgments….We can intentionally act with
the aim of helping a plant to grow and thrive, and we can do this because we have
genuine concern for its well-being. As moral agents we might think of ourselves
as under an obligation not to destroy or injure a plant. To do this would involve
our using as the standard of evaluation the preservation or promotion of the
plant’s own good.” (Taylor, 1986, p. 66-67)
Here Taylor is presenting the view that so long as we can talk about the conditions that
can contribute to a living thing’s health and other conditions that can harm it or degrade it
independently of whether it comprehends those beneficial or harmful conditions, we should give
consideration to its good in light of our understanding of what can harm or benefit it. We have
obligations to all living things not to harm them.
But the basic problem with this kind of argument is that we can also speak about those
conditions that can harm or benefit artificially-produced, non-living things that upon reflection
we do not have direct obligations to. For instance, we can meaningfully talk about what can harm
an automobile or degrade its functioning (such as removing its spark plugs) and we can also talk
about what can benefit it (such as keeping it well-oiled). But most of us would probably not think
elsewhere it is reasonable to talk about what is in a being’s interest even if that being does not
have an interest in the sense of having a conscious awareness of what is good for it. Taylor’s use
of the term “good of one's own” or “good of its own” is roughly synonymous with having an
interest in the sense of the definition of interest that I provided in chapter three which describes
interests as existing independently of whether some being has conscious awareness of its
interests.
158
that we have an obligation to our cars to keep them well-oiled or not to harm them. Furthermore,
it might likewise seem strange to think that we have obligations to non-sentient, teleofunctional
robots to refrain from interfering with their teleofunctional processes if doing so would cause
them systemic harm.
Taylor, however, argues that designed artifacts such as cars do not have the same kind of
moral standing that living things do, not because those artifacts could not be harmed, but because
those things are not goal-directed toward their own ends. According to Taylor, beings that are
directed toward their own ends have direct moral standing. All natural, living organisms, it is
argued, are goal-directed toward their own ends. A car, for example, is not organized to bring
about its own end, but rather is organized for the ends of human beings. A living cell, conversely,
is organized in such a way that it is goal-directed toward its own end, its own well-being.
181
On
Taylor's view, beings that are goal-directed toward their own ends have “a good of their own”.
Designed artifacts such as non-conscious robots do not have “a good of their own” because they
were not brought about with their goals in mind. Rather, they were programmed to bring about
the goals of their designer.
Living organisms, Taylor claims, have a good of their own in that they did not acquire
their goal-oriented activities from some source external to themselves. Their goals are "original"
to them. He writes,
“This point holds even for those complex mechanisms (such as self-monitoring
space satellites, chess-playing computers, and assembly-line “robots”) that have
been constructed by humans to function in a quasi-autonomous, self-regulating
manner in the process of accomplishing certain purposes. Though such machines
are understandable as teleological systems, they remain in actual fact inanimate
objects. The ends they are programmed to accomplish are not purposes of their
own [my emphasis], independent of the human purposes for which they were
181
Here I am not endorsing Taylor's view that all living things have goals of their own but
rather analyzing his claim that all living things are goal-directed toward their own ends.
159
made. This is not to deny in certain contexts it is perfectly proper to speak of what
is good or bad for them [my emphasis]. These would be conditions that add to or
detract from their effectiveness as instruments for bringing about the (human)
ends they were made to serve. But it is precisely this fact that separates them from
living things…The goal-oriented operations of machines are not inherent to them
as the goal-oriented behavior of organisms is inherent to them. To put it another
way, the goals of a machine are derivative, whereas the goals of a living thing are
original... A living plant or animal...has a good of its own in the same sense that a
human being has a good of its own. It is, independently of anything else in the
universe, itself a center of goal-oriented activity. What is good or bad for it can be
understood by reference to its own survival, health, and well-being. As a living
thing it seeks its own ends in a way that is not true of any teleologically structured
mechanism. It is in terms of its goals that we can give teleological explanations of
why it does what it does. We cannot do the same for machines, since any such
explanation must ultimately refer to the goals their human producers had in
mind.” (Taylor, 1986, p. 123-124)
Taylor does, however, think that should there exist some artificially-produced being that
has human-like consciousness it would have a good of its own. He writes,
"I should add as parenthetical note that this difference between mechanism and
organism may no longer be maintainable with regard to those complex electronic
devices now being developed under the name of artificial intelligence. Perhaps
some day computer scientists and engineers will construct beings whose internal
processes and electrical responses to their surroundings closely parallel the
functions of the human brain and nervous system. Concerning such beings we
may begin to speak of their having a good of their own independently of the
purposes of their creators. At this point the distinction drawn above between
living things and inanimate machines may break down" (Taylor, 1986, p. 124-
125)
Thus, on Taylor's view, conscious robots would have a good of their own even though
such conscious activity would be derivative of the designer's goal of creating such a being
capable of conscious activity.
182
Taylor himself is silent on the question of whether an
artificially-produced, non-sentient, teleofunctional being would have a good of its own. He does,
however, suggest that the distinction between "living things and inanimate machines may break
182
Note that this view of Taylor's is consistent with the provisional assumption that conscious
agents have moral standing independently of whatever etiology brought them into existence.
160
down" in which case there could exist a case of an artificially-produced, non-sentient
teleofunctional being that could have a good of its own.
On Taylor's view it appears as if the real difference is not between those beings that can
be harmed and those beings that cannot be harmed but rather between those beings that have
goods of their own and those that do not. A non-sentient being that is more machine-like would
presumably not qualify as a being that can have a good of its own because machines cannot carry
out their own goal-directed activities. Whereas, if something is more like an "organism" then it
has a good of its own because it can carry out its own goal-oriented activities. For instance, heat-
seeking missiles, it might be argued "have the goal" of seeking out sources of heat, but that is not
a goal of their own because that goal is oriented toward an external state of affairs and not toward
its own well-being. Heat-seeking missiles do not have goals of their own because they are not
sufficiently complex and "organism-like" to carry out their own self-directed activities only those
activities that have been assigned to them by an external designer.
Taylor thinks that since the non-sentient, living things that exist in the natural world have
such self-directed activities then they do have goals of their own and that we should thus think of
them as "striving", "trying" or "aiming" to do what is good for themselves. In order to have a
good of one's own one must at least be directed toward some goal or at least be capable of being
goal-directed toward its own well-being. According to Taylor, all living organisms are
"teleological centers of life" in that they are goal-directed and direct themselves towards their
own self-preservation and maintenance. Taylor writes that we should
“…conceive of the organism as a teleological center of life, striving [my
emphasis] to preserve itself and realize it good in its own unique way. To say it is
a teleological center of life [my emphasis] is to say that its internal functioning as
well as its external activities are all goal-directed [my emphasis], having the
constant tendency to maintain the organism’s existence through time and to
enable it successfully to perform those biological operations whereby it
161
reproduces its kind and continually adapts to changing environmental events and
conditions. It is the coherence and unity of these functions of an organism, all
directed toward [my emphasis] the realization of its good.” (Taylor, 1986, p. 121-
122).
On Taylor's view all living things are in some sense active participants in sustaining their
own well-being. This view of non-sentient living things as active, purposive, or goal-oriented is
also espoused by other biocentrists as well. Robin Attfield, for example, writes that plants have
“latent tendencies, direction of growth and natural fulfilments
183
” (Attfield, 1981, p. 49) that
warrant the claim that they should have moral standing. Also, J. L. Arbor has written that
“Trees, like animals and other plants, but unlike machines, have end-states [my
emphasis] which are not decided by human beings. Given the right conditions and
barring interference they will in the course of natural events reach this state.”
(Arbor, 1986, p. 337)
And finally, Albert Schweitzer, a defender of a life-centered ethic, also endorses the view
that all living things are purposive, goal-directed beings and he uses the language of
intentionality to describe them. He writes, "The tiny beetle lies dead in your path - it was a living
creature, struggling for existence like yourself, rejoicing in the sun like you, knowing fear and
pain like you." (Schweitzer, 1969, p. 115).
184
The basic claim that is being promoted here is that trees, and other non-sentient living
things, have some kind of intrinsic teleology that gives them their own natural end-states which
183
Outside of the U.S. fulfillment is the preferred spelling while inside the U.S. the preferred
spelling is fulfillment.
184
Some commentators argue that Schweitzer's use of this kind of intentionalist language
unduly anthropomorphizes all living things by likening them to conscious, emotive beings, most
notably human beings. Mike Martin made the following comments on the charge of
anthropomorphism against Schweitzer. He writes,
"...Schweitzer is widely criticized for anthropomorphism (even as he renounces
anthropocentrism), in personifying non-human organisms as literally possessing human qualities.
Specifically, he shifts from (a) 'will to live' in the minimal sense of tendencies to survive and
develop to (b) 'will to live' in the robust sense of having intentions, purposes, values and
conscious experiences..." (Martin, 2007, p. 34).
162
are the goals that their biological processes are aimed at bringing about.
Some at this point may wonder whether ecosystems could have goals of their own too.
They might use the following argument by analogy:
1) Single cells are teleofunctional systems with multiple, integrated parts and have
goals of their own.
2) Ecosystems are likewise teleofunctional with multiple, integrated parts.
3) Thus, perhaps ecosystems also have goals of their own.
I do not wish to defend the conclusion that ecosystems have goals of their own. Nor do I
wish to defend the claim that all single-celled organisms have goals of their own. However, there
are at least some reasons to think that ecosystems could be teleofunctional.
185
First, ecosystems are self-regulating to some degree. They are capable of maintaining
feedback loops that contribute to stable nutrient availability and other environmental parameters.
Bernard Patten and Eugene Odum have identified several such regulated aspects under control
by ecosystemic processes. They write,
“…in every ecosystem can be found a set of variables that are relatively time
invariant or that change in repeatable temporal patterns (e.g., total system
production, P, and respiration, R, P/R ratios, total chlorophyll, total biomass,
ambient nutrient concentration, species diversity, population size, etc.)” (Patten
and Odum, 1981, p. 889).
Second, ecosystems exhibit self-maintenance as a result of the various feedback loops
that they produce and sustain. According to John Petersen, “Feedback control has received
considerable recent attention as a result of its posited role in a variety of contemporary
environmental issues, including global warming, introduced toxins, biodiversity, exotic species
and periodicity in ecological dynamics” (Petersen, 2001, p.534). That is ecosystem processes
keep constant a variety of higher-level environmental parameters that are regulated by the
185
The claim here is not that ecosystems are as teleofunctional or are as teleofunctionally
complex as living things are, only that ecosystems might be teleofunctional.
163
interactions of lower-level elements of the ecosystem.
186
This stability in turn facilitates a
healthy environment at the organismic level.
Other environmentalists have pointed to the homeostatic or self-regulating nature of
ecosystems as an important, note-worthy feature. Since, ecosystems have the ability to
dynamically regulate the environment to some degree they contribute to the health of its
constituent members as well as to overall biospheric stability. Disruption of one of the system’s
regulatory functions by human efforts could contribute to increased instability and further
disruptions elsewhere in the system. As Don Marietta writes, "The integrity of the ecosystem is
held to be a dynamic homeostasis which can be comprehended through ecological science.
Ethical treatment of the environment requires that human beings not disturb this homeostasis..."
(Marietta, 1979, p. 197).
So there are some reasons to think that ecosystems can be somewhat teleofunctional in
nature in that they are capable of some degree of self-regulation.
187
In any event, if it terms out
that ecosystems really are teleofunctional and have goals of their own then they too would at
least have a characteristic that fulfills a sufficient condition for having morally considerable
teleofunctional interests that would give them direct moral standing.
186
For further discussions of the homeostatic functions of ecosystems and their self-maintaining
processes see Przemysław Trojan’s book Ecosystem homeostasis (1983) and Dyke and Weaver’s
2013 article “The Emergence of Environmental Homeostasis in Complex Ecosystems.”
187
The insight into ecosystem homeostasis should, however, be tempered with what other
ecologists have said regarding ecosystem instability. Ecological scientists have noted that the
romanticized view of ecosystems as paragons of stability is false. Although ecosystems have a
certain degree of homeostatic control they are also subject to large, natural fluctuations and
disturbances too. As Colleen Clements writes, "It is simply an ordinary feature of ecosystems
that stasis is not indefinitely maintained and that, therefore, major and highly significant change
occurs in biotic systems leading to both value and disvalue from a human point of view"
(Clements, 1976, p. 137). For another take on the view that ecosystems are not stable see John
Kricher's "The Balance of Nature: Ecology's Enduring Myth" (2009).
164
But why think that beings that have "intrinsic teleology" or have "goals of their own"
have morally considerable interests? Consider the following example. Forrest, my dog, has
certain goals of his own that if fulfilled are good for his self-maintenance. If he is thirsty he will
seek out water. Obtaining water is a goal for him and achieving this goal is good for his
continued health. But now let us suppose that someone were to put him on a lease so that his
water bowl is just beyond his reach. Forrest would still "have the goal of his own" of drinking
water and drinking water would still be good for his health. If someone prevents him from
obtaining water, when there is no good reason to do so, then they are thwarting his goal, a goal
that is good for him to achieve and that does not interfere with the goals of other beings.
What the biocentrist basically wants to do is claim that all living things have goals of
their own and if so then all non-sentient, living things have goals of their own which in turn
means that they have morally considerable interests that gives them some direct, minimal moral
standing. In other words, it is a sufficient condition for those beings to have direct, minimal
moral standing. All things considered, it is basically wrong to interfere with another being's goals
especially if its pursuit of those goals does not interfere with the goals of other beings.
That kind of argument looks something like the following.
1) If some non-sentient, teleofunctional being x, has a goal of its own, then x has
direct, minimal moral standing.
2) If some non-sentient, teleofunctional being x has direct, minimal moral
standing then x has a morally considerable teleofunctional interest.
3) Thus, if some non-sentient, teleofunctional being x, has a goal of its own, then
x has a morally considerable teleofunctional interest.
Some might want to claim that having a goal of one's own is also a necessary condition
for a non-sentient being to have a morally considerable teleofunctional interest. For instance, if it
is true that a tree has a morally considerable teleofunctional interest in its leaves enabling
photosynthesis then that tree must have its own goal of enabling photosynthesis. Photosynthesis
165
is, in some sense, what the tree "aims" or "tries" to do.
Likewise, if there should exist some non-sentient, teleofunctional being that does not
have a goal of its own then it would not have morally considerable teleofunctional interests. For
example, if a tree does not have its own goals then its own goals cannot be frustrated. After all,
there are no aims or goals available to frustrate! Hence, a tree that does not have its own goal of
obtaining sunlight (for example) cannot be morally violated if someone were to prevent its leaves
from obtaining sunlight.
The argument for this proposition looks like the following:
1) If some non-sentient, teleofunctional being x, has a morally considerable
teleofunctional interest, then x has direct, minimal moral standing.
2) If x has direct, minimal moral standing then x has a goal of its own.
3) Thus, if some non-sentient, teleofunctional being x, has a morally considerable
teleofunctional interest, then x has a goal of its own.
At this point I want to further examine the question of what having a goal of one's own
means. As mentioned previously, biocentrists such as Taylor and Attfield hold this position. I
will also provisionally accept the conclusion of the above argument that if some non-sentient,
teleofunctional being has a goal of its own
188
then it has a morally considerable teleofunctional
interest in pursuing that goal, they have an interest that would give them direct, minimal moral
standing.
If it is true that having a goal of one's own is both a necessary and sufficient condition for
a non-sentient being to have morally considerable teleofunctional interests, then we will need to
consider what necessary condition must be met in order for it to have a goal of its own. If it
should turn out that non-sentient beings are incapable of meeting this necessary condition, then
188
In a later section of this chapter I challenge the view that all living organisms have goals of
their own.
166
whatever else might be said in defense of their moral standing, they will not have a goal of their
own. Hence, they will not have teleofunctional interests that give them direct, minimal moral
standing.
With this concern in mind I want to focus on the question of what would be a necessary
condition for non-sentient, teleofunctional beings to have a goal of their own.
III. A Necessary Condition for Having a Goal of One's Own
As I showed in chapter three, teleofunctional systems have numerous, interconnected
parts that all contribute to their self-maintenance. What I want to show in this section is that if it
really is true that some non-sentient, teleofunctional system has a goal of its own then its
teleofunctional parts must have teleofunctions.
The basic structure of my argument is the following:
1) If a non-sentient, teleofunctional system, x, has a goal of its own, y, then x has
the goal of y.
2) If a non-sentient, teleofunctional system, x has the goal of y, then x is capable
of malfunctioning with respect to y.
189
3) If x is capable of malfunctioning with respect to y, then x has the functional
purpose of y.
4) If x has the functional purpose of y then x's teleofunctional structures are
capable of malfunctioning with respect to contributing to y.
6) If x's teleofunctional structures are capable of malfunctioning with respect to
contributing to y, then x's teleofunctional structures have the teleofunctional
189
Note that this premise applies only to non-sentient beings. It does not apply to sentient
beings or rational agents. There can exist instances of sentient or rational beings, such as human
beings, that can "have a goal" but that are not therefore capable of malfunctioning with respect to
that goal should they fail to reach that goal. For instance, if Timmy, a human being, has the goal
of becoming an astronaut it wouldn't be proper to say that he is therefore capable of
malfunctioning with respect to becoming an astronaut. If Timmy failed to become an astronaut it
would not be because he malfunctioned with regard to becoming an astronaut but because he
failed to perform a set of actions that if completed would have resulted in him becoming an
astronaut. On the other hand, if a tree has the goal of obtaining sunlight then it is capable of
malfunctioning with respect to obtaining sunlight in that it is capable of functioning improperly
with regard to its ability to reach that goal.
167
purpose of contributing to y.
7) Thus, if a non-sentient, teleofunctional system, x, has a goal of its own, y, then
x's teleofunctional structures have the teleofunctional purpose of contributing
to y.
When we say that some object or structure "has a functional purpose" we normally mean
that that object has a function. For instance, screwdrivers have the functional purpose of driving
screws into wood. This is because driving screws into wood are what screwdrivers are for. That
is their function. Likewise, computers have various functional purposes that we would also say
are their functions. Many computers have the functional purpose of facilitating the typing and
production of documents. That is one of their functions. That is one of the things that they are
for. Likewise, if a teleofunctional structure, such as a cell membrane, has the teleofunctional
purpose of selectively filtering matter, then that structure is for selectively filtering matter.
Selectively filtering matter is the function of that teleofunctional structure.
However, beings that have goals of their own have purposes in a different sense than
beings that do not have goals of their own do. For example, screwdrivers have the purpose of
driving screws into wood. But it seems strange to think that they also "have the goal of their
own" of driving screws into wood. Screwdrivers are not the kinds of things that have their own
goals at all. Beings that have a goal of their own are capable of aiming, at various states of
affairs. This sense of "having a purpose" belongs to beings that have their own goals. For
example, should my dog, Forrest, form the desire to drink water then drinking water would be a
goal of his very own. This would also mean that drinking water would be one of his own
purposes. But my dog "has the purpose" of drinking water in a different sense that screwdrivers
"have the purpose" of driving screws into wood.
The kinds of purposes that belong to objects such as screwdrivers and computers are what
are known as extrinsic purposes. An extrinsic purpose is a purpose that is extrinsic to the thing
168
that has it.
190
These are also what we could call functional purposes. The functional purpose of
a screwdriver is extrinsic to the screwdriver because its purpose was assigned to it by a being
other than itself. A screwdriver is for driving screws into wood because that is what its designer
intended it to do.
Daniel Nicholson defines extrinsic purposiveness in the following way.
"A machine is extrinsically purposive in the sense that it operates towards an end
that is external to itself. Its telos is imposed from the outside and it is of use or
value to an agent other than itself. A machine does not serve its own interests [my
emphasis] but those of its maker or user." (Nicholson, 2013, p. 671).
The kinds of purposes that belong to beings that have a goal of their own are known as
intrinsic purposes. Intrinsic purposes are those purposes that arise from the being that has those
purposes. Intrinsic purposes exist when a being, x, brings about one state of affairs, y, in order to
bring about some other state of affairs for its own good. Screwdrivers do not have intrinsic
purposes because they are incapable of bringing about one state of affair in order to bring about
some other state affairs for themselves. Screwdrivers do not perform various tasks in order to
bring about their own ends. Conscious agents and other intentional beings, however, do perform
various tasks in order to bring about their own ends.
191
For example, my dog has the intrinsic
190
Designed objects that only have extrinsic purposes, however, do not necessarily have to only
bring about the interests of the designer or agent that brought it about. For example, a
teleofunctional system can have the purpose of maintaining its own self-maintenance even if
such self-maintenance doesn’t bring about or serve the utilitarian interests of its designer. A
robotics engineer can design a robot with the capacity to regulate the charging and re-charging of
its own power supply. This purpose, however, is extrinsic and so did not come from the robot
(assuming that the robot did not have mental states or representations) but rather the robot's
designer. Nonetheless, this extrinsic purpose serves the robot's own teleofunctional interests.
Such an extrinsic purpose exists because an engineer had his or her own intrinsic purpose of
designing a system with certain self-regulating capacities.
191
A intrinsic purpose, however, can be aimed at serving the interests of beings other than the
being that has the intrinsic purpose in question. For example, a mother might have the intrinsic
purpose of aiming to feed her infant. But that intrinsic purpose of hers is not simply for her
benefit because her aim is to feed the infant and being fed is in the infant's interests. So there is a
169
purpose of drinking water in order to quench his thirst which is pleasing to him. These kinds of
purposes are imposed from within the thing that has those purposes and that bring about the ends
of the thing that has them.
Nicholson defines intrinsic purposiveness this way. He writes,
"...an organism is intrinsically purposive in the sense that it acts on its behalf,
towards its own ends. Its telos is internal, arising from within..." (Nicholson,
2013, p. 671).
So to say that the author of this dissertation “has the purpose” of eating lunch at noon is
entirely different from the claim that a screwdriver “has the purpose” of driving screws into
wood. To say that the author of this dissertation “has the purpose” of eating lunch at noon is to
say that the author is capable of bringing about one state of affairs (driving home) in order to
bring about some other states of affairs for himself (eating lunch). According to Taylor non-
sentient living things have purposes in this sense. But to say that a screwdriver “has the purpose”
of driving screws into wood does not mean to say that it also aims at bringing about one state of
affairs in order to bring about some other states of affairs for itself.
For the remainder of this dissertation, and for purposes of shorthand, I will refer to
intrinsic purposes as goals of one's own while extrinsic purposes will be referred to as functional
purposes. To say that I have the intrinsic purpose of driving home means to say that I have the
goal of driving home in that it is a goal of mine to drive home. Likewise, to say that a heat-
seeking missile "has the goal" of seeking out sources of heat means that it "has the extrinsic
purpose" of seeking out sources of heat which in turn means that seeking out sources of heat is
its functional purpose, but not a goal of its own.
distinction between the origin of an intrinsic purpose and the interests that that purpose aims to
bring about. Or, to put it another way, there is a distinction between that which is the source of
the purpose and that which the purpose is aimed at.
170
Let us assume that a naturally-evolved, living tree has the goal of its own of growth in the
way that Taylor argues and that it is directed toward its own ends.
192
Obviously if the tree has
its own goal of growth, then certainly it has the goal of growth. For instance, let us say that it is a
goal of my own to consume food. If this is true then it must also mean that I at least have the
goal of consuming food. Similarly, a tree that has a goal of its own of growth also has the goal of
growth.
If the tree has the goal of growth this would also mean that the tree is at least capable of
failing to achieve that goal. But this in turn means that it is capable of failing to perform the
functions that it needs to in order to fulfill that goal. For instance, if a tree has the goal of growth
then it is capable of failing to reach that goal. And if it is capable of failing in that way then it is
likewise capable of failing to fulfill those teleofunctional purposes that contribute to its growth.
So, for instance, should its leaves malfunction in gathering sunlight then the tree could not obtain
its goal of growth. A tree with malfunctioning leaves is a malfunctioning tree. It is a tree that has
structures that are not fulfilling their functional purposes. So if the tree itself is capable of
malfunctioning then surely its structures also have functional purposes. Those functional
purposes are what its leaves, as teleofunctional structures, are supposed to do.
On the other hand, if something does not have a functional purpose, but only performs
that function, it is not one that is capable of malfunction with regard to its function. For instance,
let us suppose that on one unfortunate occasion my neighbor accidently backs his car into my
home resulting in a large hole in my living room wall. This hole allows a considerable amount of
sunlight into my living room. In fact, the hole in my living room wall causes the interior of my
192
The target goal or aim of growth, however, need not be regarded as the only goal of a tree.
On this assumption a tree could presumably have other goals such as reproduction, acquiring
sunlight, absorbing water, fighting various diseases, etc.
171
living room to be exceedingly well lit. This hole performs the function of allowing in sunlight.
But, of course, allowing in sunlight is not the functional purpose of the hole in my living room
wall. The hole was not made with that function in mind even if it happens to allow in sunlight
very well. So although this hole performs the function of allowing in sunlight, and even performs
that function well, it does not have the functional purpose of allowing in sunlight.
Should my neighbor take it upon himself to patch up the hole in my living room wall then
it would no longer function as a "sunlight allower". But his action would not result in the hole
malfunctioning with respect to allowing in sunlight precisely because the hole itself never had
the functional purpose of allowing in sunlight to begin with. So no matter how excellently the
hole in my living room wall might perform the function of allowing in sunlight, it does not have
that as its functional purpose. Hence, nothing that my neighbor could do to the hole could cause
it to malfunction. His actions could, however, cause it to no longer function as a "sunlight
allower".
Imagine that I were to dam up a naturally-formed creek that just so happened to supply
water to a nearby wetland. Let us further imagine that the creek performs the function of
supplying water to the wetland but it does not have the functional purpose of supplying water to
the wetland. It was not made with that purpose in mind. My action of damming up the creek is
one of causing it to function differently say, as a retention pond, but not one of causing it to
malfunction. I did not cause the creek to "function improperly as a wetland water provider" or to
“not function as it was supposed to”. In terms of whether my action of damming up the creek
violates the creek's goal of providing water to the wetland it must at least be the case that the
creek had the goal of providing water to the wetland. In other words in order to violate the
creek's goal it must at least have a goal for me to violate. And so causing the creek to no longer
172
function as it was supposed to is precisely what I did not do. This is because the creek never had
the functional purpose of supplying water to the wetland. It is not for providing water to the
wetland although it happens to perform that function quite well.
However, let us suppose that I dam up a ditch that was constructed by a farmer as his
means of draining water away from his farmland. This constructed ditch clearly has the
functional purpose of draining water away from the farmer's property. By damming it up I cause
it to malfunction as a "farmland drainer". It no longer functions in the way that it was supposed
to function.
Consider yet another example. Suppose that a small pile of boulders were to function as a
dam in a city ditch. The boulders wound up in their location by the movements of water currents
in the ditch. This pile of rocks function as a dam, but they do not have that as their function.
Sally, a local child, loves to play in the deep water next to the dam. Billy, another neighborhood
child, smashes this particular collection of rocks so that it no longer functions as a dam. Some
might say that Billy's act of causing the pile of rocks to function differently was morally wrong
because that action resulted in Sally no longer having a place to swim. But notice that Billy's act
of smashing the pile of rocks was not an act of "causing it to no longer function as it should". We
might say that Billy’s act of causing the pile of rocks to function differently was wrong (in that,
for instance, it made Sally feel unhappy for no good reason) but it would not be because he
caused that pile of rocks to malfunction.
Or suppose that a sophisticated, autonomous, non-sentient teleofunctional robot was
designed by a team of research scientists. This robot was designed for being goal-directed toward
its own long-term self-maintenance. This robot is capable of finding its own sources of energy
and even of repairing itself. In light of the scientist's aim of generating a self-maintaining,
173
teleofunctional robot they invented the robot’s central processing unit for coordinating input data
from various external sensors. The central processing unit and the external sensors have their
respective functional purposes because the team of research scientists intended those structures
to have those functions which in turn contribute to the overall goal of the robot’s self-
maintenance.
If the robot's central processing unit fails at making the right sort of causal contribution to
the robots self-maintenance we would rightly say that this structure is malfunctioning and not
that it simply "no longer performed the function" of coordinating input data. But in order for that
claim to make sense its central processing unit must at least have had the functional purpose of
coordinating input data.
Consider once again the case of Instant Arto, a non-sentient, instant cell. This cell has
numerous, teleofunctional interests in all of its parts contributing to its self-maintenance. But due
to its instantaneous, essentially random etiology this cell does not have any structures that have
functional purposes. Its cell membrane, for example, performs the function of selectively
filtering matter but it does not have that as its functional purpose. In fact none of its
teleofunctional structures have functional purposes. It just happened to pop into existence by an
act of sheer chance.
If someone were to puncture Instant Arto’s membrane such an act could not be claimed
to be one in which that person caused the cell's membrane to malfunction or to function
improperly since the cell's membrane doesn't have a functional purpose.
193
By puncturing its
membrane they may cause it to cease functioning as a highly-selective barrier or to function
193
Some of us might not like for someone to puncture Instant Arto's membrane, but that is a
different question from whether puncturing its cell membrane is an act of causing it to
malfunction.
174
differently as a less-selective barrier. In turn the cell dies because the membrane can no longer
selectively filter matter to the degree necessary for its homeostasis. If the cell dies it dies because
its membrane functions differently not because it malfunctioned or no longer functioned as it
should.
In order for someone to cause the cell's membrane to malfunction, and where causing it
to malfunction is morally wrong (as biocentrists suggest), then it must be the case that the
membrane had a functional purpose. But that is the very thing that Instant Arto’s membrane does
not have.
In his essay “Of Suicide” David Hume remarks that "It would be no crime in me to divert
the Nile or Danube from its course, were I able to effect such purposes. Where then is the crime
of turning a few ounces of blood from their natural channels!" (Hume, 1799, p.8). Here Hume
suggests that in order for it to be morally wrong to divert “a few ounces of blood from their
natural channels” there must something about that action that is morally evaluative. But since
there is nothing evaluative about causing the Nile River to flow differently there is likewise
nothing evaluative about causing a person’s veins to flow blood differently. The Nile, he
suggests, might function as a “transporter of water to the Mediterranean Sea” but there is nothing
inherently wrong with causing it to function differently as a “transporter of water to the Gulf of
Suez”. Likewise, the flow of blood in a person’s veins could be diverted from their “natural
channels” so that they no longer function as an “oxygen suppliers to the brain” but instead
function differently as “the blood’s escape route from the body”. In the case of the Nile River and
in the case of venous blood flow, a person caused something to function differently than it did
before. But they did not cause those structures to malfunction.
Many of us would probably favor the view that veins have the functional purpose of
175
transporting blood, whereas the Nile River does not strike us as having the functional purpose of
transporting water to the Mediterranean Sea. Nonetheless, if it were the case that both the Nile
River and a person's veins had the functional purposes of transporting water to the Mediterranean
Sea and supplying oxygenated blood to the brain respectively we might be in a position to call
such acts of changing their function to something else to be acts of causing those structures to
malfunction.
When someone causes a thing to malfunction that person causes it to no longer function
as should or as it was supposed to. We can physically describe what happens when water is
diverted from a naturally-formed channel and when blood is diverted from its proper course in
someone’s veins. But this does not mean that such physical descriptions necessarily preclude a
normative assessment of whether those structures have functional purposes and so are capable of
malfunctioning.
In any event, what is needed for the normative assessment of malfunction is whether
something has a functional purpose. In order for someone to make the evaluative claim about
whether a person’s veins are malfunctioning or no longer functioning as they should they must at
least be in a position to say that those veins had a functional purpose or were supposed to
channel blood in a certain kind of way.
Let us assume, for the sake of argument, that a tree has leaves that do not have any
functional purposes. So, for instance, its leaves do not have the functional purpose of gathering
sunlight but rather simply perform the function of gathering sunlight. Let us further suppose that
these leaves perform that function rather well and that such performances positively contribute to
the tree’s ability to grow and maintain itself. Let us now suppose that an art student picks all of
these leaves from the tree and uses them as ornaments in her art collage. Since these leaves do
176
not have the functional purpose of gathering sunlight they are not now malfunctioning with
respect to gathering sunlight. Rather they are merely functioning differently than they did before.
As such her action of removing the tree's leaves is not one of causing those leaves to
malfunction. But if the art student is not in a position to cause them to malfunction then surely
her removal of those leaves cannot be claimed to be a morally impermissible violation of the
trees interests. It is not a morally wrong act against the tree's interests to cause its leaves to
function differently than they currently are functioning in the same way that it is not a morally
wrong act against the Nile River's interest to cause it to function differently.
Both acts are not morally wrong acts against the tree’s interests or against the river’s
interests.
194
And if it is not a morally wrong injunction against tree's interests to cause its leaves
to function differently then surely the tree does not have a morally considerable interest in its
leaves gathering sunlight, an interest that provides moral agents a reason to value the tree
intrinsically and to treat it as an object of direct moral concern. There is no moral injunction
against the proper versus improper treatment of its leaves.
Conversely, if we assume that a tree's leaves can be caused to malfunction then those
leaves must have a functional purpose. Leaves that are malfunctioning are ones that are not
performing their function tasks. Leaves of this sort are said to be defective, diseased, malformed,
etc. A leaf that is performing its function of gathering sunlight is a properly functioning leaf.
Leaves of this sort are said to be healthy, flourishing, etc.
A tree that has malfunctioning leaves is one that cannot achieve its goal of growth. It will
in turn be a malfunctioning tree. In like manner, a car that has a malfunctioning engine is a
194
Recall that in order for something to have an interest it must at least have a preference
interest, a sentient interest or a teleofunctional interest.
177
malfunctioning car. This means that a tree's function can either be hindered or furthered by
whether its teleofunctional structures are performing their functions. If a tree has leaves that are
defective or malfunctioning, then the tree itself will not grow properly. It will malfunction.
Conversely if a tree has leaves that are performing their functional jobs then it will grow
properly, it will achieve its goal of growth (assuming, of course, that there are no other
teleofunctional structures of it that are malfunctioning).
A naturally-evolved tree that is goal-oriented toward its own end of growth will also have
the goal of gathering sunlight since gathering sunlight is part of its means toward growth. As
such its leaves, as ineliminable structures of the teleofunctional system that is the tree, will not
just merely perform the function of gathering sunlight. They will likewise have the functional
purpose of gathering sunlight. They are for gathering sunlight because that functional task is
itself one of the goals that the tree itself is aimed at in so far as sunlight is necessary for its
growth. The tree itself is teleologically oriented towards its own well-being which also includes
the goal of gathering sunlight. Leaves that do not perform their function do not make the right
sort of causal contribution to the tree's goal of growth. Conversely, a properly functioning tree
will have functioning leaves because of the connection that exists between a tree being healthy
and its leaves being healthy. A healthy tree has healthy leaves.
Scott Simmons points out the kind of connection that exists between whether something
has a functional purpose to whether it can be harmed. In short he argues that in order for a
biological system to be counted as being harmed by some state of affairs that biological system
must have structures that have functional purpose. He writes, "...it seems clear that, say, an organ
that cannot be said to have anything wrong with it (i.e., be defective) cannot have been harmed."
(Simmons, 2013, p. 255)
178
For instance, should it turn out that a tree's leaves that do not have the functional purpose
of gathering sunlight then those leaves cannot be harmed or damaged by some state of affairs
causing them to malfunction. Similarly, if a non-sentient, teleofunctional system, such as a tree,
does not have the goal of growth then it cannot be harmed by any state of affairs that cause it to
stop growing. It cannot be made to malfunction and so it cannot be harmed in that way.
A tree that has teleofunctional structures that do not have any functional purposes are not
teleofunctional structures that can be harmed in the sense of being caused to malfunction. And an
entire teleofunctional system that is comprised of structures that do not have functional purposes
is one that likewise cannot be harmed in the same sense.
For the reasons given above I propose the following as a necessary condition for having a
goal of one's own.
195
Some non-sentient, teleofunctional system, x, has a goal of its own, only if x has
structures that have teleofunctional purposes.
IV. Can a Systems-based Account be used to Reliably Establish the Existence of Morally
Considerable Teleofunctional Interests for Non-Sentient Beings?
As I illustrated in chapter three, the systems-based account allows someone to make
sense of what is in an organism’s interests without requiring further knowledge of its causal
history. According to this account a living thing has an interest in its structures performing their
teleofunctions because of the actual internal, functional role that those structures play in the self-
regulation of it. Etiological explanations for how some teleofunctional system acquired its
structures are simply not needed to determine whether a living thing has a teleofunctional interest
in its structures performing their teleofunctions. If we needed to identify the teleofunction of an
195
I have argued in the previous section that having a goal of one's own is also a sufficient
condition for having morally considerable teleofunctional interests.
179
organism’s structure and the corresponding interest hat the organism has in that structure
performing it teleofunction, we would not need to wait for some etiological explanation of how
that function arose. As Delancey writes,
“If we were to discover a new kind of mammal, for example, we would not be
stumped to understand it, waiting until the evolutionary biologists placed it in
evolutionary history and then told us why this or that organ or behavior evolved.
We could just watch it in its environment, and working with some basic naturalist
presuppositions
196
…we could develop theories of what it was up to…Some
common-sense understanding of organisms as complex systems with
teleofunctions is the best explanation for our ability to recognize (at least some)
instances of flourishing in other organisms…if we were ever to discover
extraterrestrial life, with a completely different evolutionary history than we have
derived for our own planet, we would not be flummoxed until we uncovered that
planet’s fossil record” (Delancey, 2004, p. 184).
197
I also showed in chapter three that this account is able to resolve problematic cases of
harmful, selected functions such as that of the oncogene. The reason why the oncogene is not in
196
A good question that could be asked is whether our own unspoken etiological
presuppositions might be among the "basic naturalist presuppositions" that Delancey refers to.
"What", it might be urged, "is a new kind of mammal if not what we have already come to
recognize as animals with a particular kind of evolutionary history; one that resulted in their
placement in the mammalian lineage?"
197
Karen Neander (1991), however, takes the contrary position. She, like Varner, thinks that
causal/historical explanations are a crucial aspect of understanding the functional purpose of an
organism’s structure. She writes,
Suppose there are no lions. Then suppose that half a dozen lions pop into existence [sic], we
know not how. Having stared at them in stupefied amazement for some time, we eventually
begin to wonder about their wing-like protuberances on each flank. We ask ourselves whether
these limbs have the proper function of flight…I contend that we could not reliably place them
[the “wings”] until we knew or could infer the lions’ history. And if we were to discover that the
lions had no history, and were the result of an accidental and freak collision of atoms, they would
definitely not belong in any of our familiar functional categories” (Neader, 1991, p. 179-180).
Some might think that Neander’s use of the word “lion” does not represent actual lions because
“real” lions have a particular evolutionary history by natural selection that makes them lions.
Thus, the “lions” that suddenly popped into existence are not really lions. In any event, if
Delancey is correct then we would not need evolutionary, historical knowledge in order to
determine what the wings of these “lions” are for. All we would need to do is simply observe
these creatures in their environment in order to determine what, if any, teleofunctional role that
their wings might play in their self-regulation.
180
an oncomouse's interests is because it is not a teleofunctional structure. It does not contribute to
the self-regulation of the mouse but instead contributes to a degradation of the mouse's overall
self-maintenance. It is not playing the right kind of endogenous causal role in the maintenance of
the life of the mouse. Thus, the mouse has no teleofunctional interest in its oncogene producing
cancerous tumors. The cancerous tumors that the oncogene facilitates disrupt and inhibit the
otherwise, normal teleofunctional structures that exist in the mouse’s organisational system.
Thus, while the oncogene of the mouse is not performing a teleofunction, (in Delancey’s
sense) the other integrated biological structures and systems of the mouse are. These are the
teleofunctional structures that perform functions that the mouse has a teleofunctional interest
in.
198
A harmful, naturally-selected function, such as violently fighting rivals, is likewise not in
the teleofunctional interest of male elephant seals. Naturally-selected fighting behavior causes
systemic harm to individual male elephant seals just as artificially-selected oncogenes cause
systemic harm to them. Systemic harm is not good for mice or elephant seals. Thus, selected
functions that bring about systemic harm are not in the interests of these organisms.
But there is a real problem for the systems-based view, if one wants to use it to establish
the existence of morally considerable teleofunctional interests. The problem lies in the fact that
while such an account is successful in identifying the existence of teleofunctional interests of
non-sentient beings, it cannot rule out instances of teleofunctional organisms that do not have
teleofunctions.
199
It allows for cases of non-sentient organisms that do not meet a necessary
198
It is also true that oncogenic tumors cause pain in oncomice. So having an oncogene is also
not in the mouse's sentient interests either. See Maurizio Salvi's "Transforming Animal Species:
the Case of 'Oncomouse'" in Science and Engineering Ethics (2001).
199
In other words, a teleofunctional organism need not have structures that have teleofunctions.
Instant Arto, for example is a teleofunctional organism, but it does not have structures that have
teleofunctions.
181
condition for having a goal of one's own.
For instance, an instantly produced, non-sentient organism, such as Instant Arto, has
structures that perform various teleofunctional tasks. But none of its structures actually have
teleofunctional purposes. Instant Arto's structures cannot be caused to malfunction; they can only
be caused to function differently. Likewise, Instant Arto itself cannot be caused to malfunction or
to become defective. Since Instant Arto's cell membrane doesn't have the teleofunctional purpose
of selectively filtering matter, it does not have the goal of selectively filtering matter. Hence,
puncturing its cell membrane does not appear to be a moral violation of that goal. Hence, Instant
Arto's teleofunctional interest in its membrane performing the function of selectively filtering
matter is not a morally considerable teleofunctional interest. Its teleofunctional interest does not
provide a reason to value it intrinsically.
Instead let us assume that there exists a tree which has leaves that do have teleofunctional
purposes. Let us say that I prevent these leaves from performing the teleofunction of absorbing
sunlight by blocking their access to sunlight. Should my action of causing the tree's leaves to
malfunction disrupts the tree's goal of absorbing sunlight then that tree's teleofunctional interest
in its leaves absorbing sunlight is a morally considerable teleofunctional interest. Notice that in
order for my act to count as a moral transgression against its interest, it must at least mean that I
caused the leaves of the tree to not function as they should, to function in a way contrary to the
goal of the tree. If its leaves have the teleofunctional purpose of absorbing sunlight and the tree
has the goal of absorbing sunlight, then blocking the tree’s leaves from absorbing sunlight is an
act of causing those leaves to malfunction and of violating the plant's goal. In this case if we
assume that the tree has the goal of absorbing sunlight then my act of blocking sunlight from its
leaves is an act of causing those leaves to malfunction. This means that absorbing sunlight must
182
be what the leaves are for not just what they happen to do.
If biocentrists want to make the case for the moral standing of all living things by
recourse to their possession of interests, then they must argue that the teleofunctional interests of
non-sentient beings are also morally considerable. But in order to do that their account of
interests must also include a provision which requires that all non-sentient beings have structures
that have teleofunctional purposes. Any biocentric account of interests that does not fulfill this
necessary condition cannot succeed in establishing why all living things have morally
considerable teleofunctional interests. It cannot succeed in establishing why all living things
have inherent worth.
200
Holm’s organisational account, a type of systems-based account, implies that Instant Arto
has the goal of selectively filtering matter even if its cell membrane does not have the
teleofunctional purpose of selectively filtering matter. Its membrane does not have the
teleofunctional purpose of selectively filtering matter because that structure was not selected to
perform that function.
In fact, the teleofunctional structures of all instant organisms do not have teleofunctional
purposes at all. Should Instant Arto’s membrane get punctured by someone we would not be in a
position to say that such an act caused that structure to malfunction or to function improperly. Its
membrane never had a teleofunctional purpose to begin with because its etiology did not select
its membrane to perform that teleofunctional job. The systems-based account then would allow
instant, non-sentient organisms to count as having morally considerable teleofunctional interests
when in fact they do not.
200
As a reminder, in chapter one I define inherent worth as, "The value that a thing has in virtue
of, a) having interests and b) where such interests provide a reason why all moral agents ought to
intrinsically value the thing that has such interests."
183
All that a systems-based account of teleofunctional interests can do is show that some
system has teleofunctional interests. Unfortunately, the biocentrist devoted to showing that all
living things, including non-sentient beings, have inherent worth will not get proper guidance
from that account because it is not concerned with whether the structures of non-sentient beings
have teleofunctional purposes.
In order to account for the existence of teleofunctional structures that do have
teleofunctional purposes we must make some sort of appeal to an etiology one that selects those
teleofunctional structures to have the teleofunctions that they perform.
For this reason I will set aside a systems-based account as being inadequate in accounting
for morally considerable teleofunctional interests of non-sentient beings.
V. Can "Instant, Non-Sentient Beings" have Morally Considerable Teleofunctional
Interests?
It is for this same basic reason that an “Instant organism” type of etiology is unable to
provide an account of why instant organisms have teleofunctional interests that are morally
considerable. An instant organism etiology would claim that any teleofunctional system that
arose by an instantaneous, chance event would have teleofunctional interests that arose out of
that etiology. But, that etiology cannot produce non-sentient, teleofunctional systems that have
structures that have teleofunctional purposes. Instantly-produced, non-sentient teleofunctional
interests could not have their interests violated by someone causing their teleofunctional
structures to malfunction. Hence, this type of etiology cannot generate non-sentient beings that
have morally considerable teleofunctional interests.
At this point I will set aside an “Instant organism” type etiology from the list of viable
contenders for identifying morally considerable teleofunctional interests in that it does not meet a
184
necessary condition for the existence of morally considerable teleofunctional interests, namely
that those teleofunctional interests must belong to beings that possess structures that have
teleofunctional purposes.
VI. Can Non-Sentient Beings produced by an Agent-Selection, Non-Design Etiology have
Morally Considerable Teleofunctional Interests?
Let us now consider whether an agent-selection, non-design etiology can be successful in
generating non-sentient beings that have morally considerable teleofunctional interests.
An agent-selection, non-design etiological account is not the same thing as a design
account in that the former, but not the latter, does not involve genuine teleological planning or
deliberate design on the part of an agent who directs various states of affairs to bring about a
teleofunctional system. That is to say, just because an agent’s selective activity is causally
responsible in some way or other for the existence of a teleofunctional system, it does not follow
that such a system was designed.
Also, an agent-selection, non-design etiology can produce both teleofunctional and non-
teleofunctional systems. An example of a non-teleofunctional system produced by this etiology
is "Tom's rainwater collector" which was previously illustrated in chapter two.
201
Tom's
rainwater collector has numerous structures that are integrated in various ways with each other
but those structures are not integrated in such a way that the system itself acquires self-
regulation. The system might regulate the flow of water perhaps but it does not have structures
that all work together for it to regulate itself. The rainwater collector itself doesn’t have any
internal, systemic regulatory processes at all. As such it is not a teleofunctional system and so it
201
See Section IV, "A Survey of Etiological Accounts of Living Organisms", in chapter two.
185
cannot have teleofunctinal interests.
So let us assume for the sake of argument that this etiology actually produced a non-
sentient, teleofunctional being rather than a non-teleofunctional one. Would that system have
morally considerable teleofunctional interests?
Consider the following thought experiment as a case of an agent-selection, non-design
etiology responsible for bringing about a teleofunctional, living cell.
Sara, a lab scientist randomly gathers pipettes each filled with a random
assortment of nucleic acids, carbohydrates and proteins. She throws them all into
a large bin. Their distribution within the bin is entirely random. Next, she blindly
grabs a handful of pipettes from the bin and smashes them onto the lab counter
spilling their contents. As it so happens the chemicals from the pipettes mix
together in such a way that the nucleic acids within the mixture acquire the
capacity to replicate themselves. Our lab scientist, upon noticing this fact,
regards the replication of nucleic acids as something that she particularly likes.
She decides to keep this particular collection. She grabs another random handful
of pipettes from the bin and smashes them against the counter. As it so happens
these chemicals fortuitously mix with the chemicals on the counter top that have
nucleotides capable of self-replication in such a way that the mixture produces a
living cell (let us call it “Nondesign Arto”) capable of respiring on its own,
feeding itself and replicating itself. The lab scientist determines that she likes the
ability of this selected entity to do all of those things that Nondesign Arto has a
teleofunctional interest in. It has an interest in its membrane continuing to
perform the function
202
of selectively filtering matter. If the cell’s membrane
were to rupture the cell would die. To avoid the possibility of such damage the lab
scientist scoops up Nondesign Arto and keeps it safe in her laboratory incubator
where conditions for its continued reproduction and survival are optimal.
In the case of Nondesign Arto
203
we have an organism that was brought about at one or
more stages by an agent, Sara, but in such a way that those stages in its development were not
directed by Sara to obtain that cell as a predetermined object. That is Nondesign Arto had a
history in which some of its parts were selected by Sara but were not designed by Sara for any
202
As I will explain later, even though its membrane performs the function of selective filtering
it does not have the function of selective filtering.
203
This particular example is meant to apply to the emergence of teleofunctional systems, most
notably living, teleofunctional systems.
186
function. Its cell membrane performs the teleofunction of selectively filtering matter but it does
not have the teleofunction of selectively filtering matter. Sara had no intentions or plans to form
any of the cell's teleofunctional structures in light of any functional job that she wanted them to
perform.
This cell appears to have teleofunctional interests. It has numerous structures that are
integrated and multi-functional. Its structures work together to bring about its self-maintenance
and regulation. If this organism were to be placed in conditions that destabilized one of its
teleofunctional structures, such as its cell membrane, its self-regulation would come to an end.
But are its teleofunctional interests morally considerable?
I will argue that they are not for the following reason.
Nondeseign Arto’s cell membrane does not have the teleofunction
204
of selectively
filtering matter even though that is what that structure is doing. For example, although we might
say that the membrane itself contributes to regulating the cell’s pH, which in turn helps regulate
protein synthesis, which in turn help make more membrane proteins, it does not have the
teleofunction of performing any of these contributory functional tasks. It was not selected for the
function that it currently performs. That structure just accidently happened to be capable of
performing those tasks.
205
And since Nondesign Arto’s membrane does not have the teleofunction of performing
204
To say that a structure, S “has the teleofunction” of performing function, F, I mean that that
structure has the teleofunctional purpose of performing F, or that S is for performing the
teleofunction F (non-psychologically).
205
Additionally, Nondesign Arto does not have any structures with Millikanian, proper
functions because it does not have any ancestors. In order for this cell to have a membrane with a
proper function it must have some ancestor that possessed such a membrane as well. And since it
does not have structures with proper functions then those structures do not have the functions
(are not for the functions) that they currently perform.
187
these tasks, or of any task for that matter, it cannot malfunction if it ever were to cease
performing those functions. If its membrane were damaged by someone in such a way that it no
longer filtered matter we would not be in a position to say that its membrane is malfunctioning.
Its membrane cannot malfunction or function improperly because its membrane has no function
to begin with. If, on the other hand, we were to say that Nondesign Arto’s membrane is
"functioning differently" that would simply mean that its membrane is no longer performing a
functional job that it once did. As such Nondesign Arto does not have a goal of its own. Hence, it
cannot have a morally considerable teleofunctional interest.
But this need not mean that Nondesign Arto is without some other value. We might, for
instance, value it for reasons other than its possession of teleofunctional interests. Perhaps it has
a certain rare aesthetic quality about it, such as intricacy or coloring that makes it pleasing to the
human eye. Those features might indeed give us some reason to treat it with some respect but not
its teleofunctional interests per se.
But many biocentrists think that we should not value living things simply because they
happen to appear beautiful to us. Instead we should value all forms of life regardless of whether
they happen to be aesthetically pleasing. Some forms of life in fact aren’t particularly beautiful.
For instance, the blobfish, Psychrolutes marcidus, is actually quite ugly.
206
So if we go by
aesthetic qualities such as beauty it would turn out that some forms of life would not be valuable.
In any event Nondesign Arto was selectively generated on the basis of its possession of
structural features that just so happened to be pleasing to an agent. Nondesign Arto has a
206
The Discovery News website posts an interesting article on ugly animals and why they
should be valued. See “Blobfish Wins Ugliest Animal Mascot Contest” at
http://news.discovery.com/animals/endangered-species/ugly-animals-need-saving-130618.htm
(Viegas, 2013)
188
teleofunctional interest in its membrane continuing to function as a selective barrier. But that
function arose out of the arbitrary, utilitarian concerns of an agent with no real functional
purposes in mind. So the reason why Nondesign Arto has a teleofunctional interest in its cell
membrane continuing to act as a selective barrier is because Sara found that particular feature to
be pleasing to her, not because it would be beneficial or good for the self-maintenance of the
organism.
It is for this reason that all non-sentient, teleofunctional beings produced by an agent-
selection non-teleological process will not have morally considerable teleofunctional interests.
Sentient beings or conscious agents produced by this etiology do have morally considerable
interests. But that does not mean that all teleofunctional beings produced by this same etiology
have morally considerable interests. If non-sentient beings do not have morally considerable
teleofunctional interests then it is also not the case that all living things have inherent worth.
VII. Naturally Selected, Proper Functions and Goals of One's Own`
At this point the only etiological options available for producing non-sentient,
teleofunctional beings that could have teleofunctional structures with teleofunctional purposes
are a natural selection etiology and a design etiology.
The suggestion made by many biocentrists is that the existence of proper functions are
what can ground the existence of inherent goals and hence morally considerable teleofunctional
interests for non-sentient, teleofunctional beings. They want to show that all living organisms
with a natural selection etiology have their own goals because they have structures with
teleofunctional purposes. The goal-oriented behaviors and functions of living things, they claim,
are “original” to them in large part because they have structures with teleofunctional purposes
189
assigned to them by natural selection, purposes which are not given to them from something
outside of themselves such as a designing agent.
It has been argued that natural selection is capable of selecting structures to have
functions understood as functional purposes. Specifically it has been argued that naturally
selected proper functions count as functional purposes.
207
Ruth Millikan has claimed that
proper functions are those functions that it would make sense for us to claim are the functional
"purposes" of a structure. Structures with proper functions have, according to Millikan,
functional "purposes". She writes, “...the things that have “proper functions” do seem to coincide
with things (omitting God) that have, in ordinary parlance, “purposes.” (Millikan, 1984, p. 18).
So on this view if the roots of a tree have the proper function of absorbing water they have the
functional purpose of absorbing water.
208
Millikan's account of the normativity of naturally-selected functions is part of a larger
philosophical project of arriving at norms of performance from nonnormative, natural properties.
As Millikan writes in her paper "Speaking up for Darwin" she writes,
"Meaning and truth cannot be naturalized without a theory that naturalizes norms
generally. Sellars followed Wittgenstein, grounding his theory of norms in
community. An alternative, some of us have argued, is to ground the needed
norms in evolutionary biology [my emphasis] - to let Darwinian natural purposes
set the standards against which failures, untruths, incorrectness, etc. are
measured." (Millikan, 1991, p. 151)
She has also written that,
"The definition of "proper function" is intended as a theoretical definition of
function or purpose. It is an attempt to describe a unitary phenomenon that lies
behind all the various sorts of cases in which we ascribe purposes or functions to
things...My claim is that actual body organs and systems, actual actions and
207
As I argued previously in order for a non-sentient teleofunctional being to have a goal of its
own it must have structures that have teleofunctional purposes.
208
In a later section I challenge the claim that naturally selected proper functions count as
functional purposes.
190
purposive behaviors, artifacts, words and grammatical forms, and many customs,
etc., all have proper functions, and that these proper functions correspond to their
functions or purposes [my emphasis]. (Millikan, 1989, p. 293).
So Millikan's definition of proper functions is meant to be an account of functional norms
of performance, or as we might also call them, functional purposes. Although she uses the words
"supposed to" and "purpose" in quotation marks her notion of proper functions is one of
functional normativity. A cell membrane that has the Millikinian proper function of selectively
filtering matter is, presumably, for selectively filtering matter. Selectively filtering matter is its
functional purpose. That is what it is "supposed to" (normatively) do.
Naturalistically-minded biocentrists then pick up on this normativity of function to imply
that all naturally-selected living things have their own goals. In particular, complex, naturally-
selected, teleofunctional living things have structures that have teleofunctional purposes because
their structures have Millikanian proper functions. The general line of thinking goes that since
naturally selected structures have teleofunctional purposes then the whole organism itself will
have a goal of its own, a goal oriented towards its own well-being.
209
And since all naturally
selected, living things are goal-oriented toward their own well-being, they all seem to have goals
of their own. Hence, all naturally selected living things have morally considerable
teleofunctional interests. Hence, they all have inherent worth.
This argument might look something like the following.
1) All NSNSLTs
210
have teleofunctional structures with naturally selected proper
functions.
2) If an NSNSLT has teleofunctional structures with naturally selected proper
209
This is presumably because the fulfillment of the functional purposes of the teleofunctional
structures of living things also results in the fulfillment of the self-maintenance of the organism
itself. Because of the causal connections that exist between all of the teleofunctional structures of
the organism the self-maintenance of the organism is the sum total of the fulfillment of all
teleofunctional purposes of all of the individual structures of that organism.
210
From here on I will use the abbreviation NSNSLT to stand for "naturally-selected, non-
sentient living thing".
191
functions then it has structures with functional purposes.
3) If something has structures with functional purposes then that thing has a goal
of its own.
211
4) Thus, all NSNSLTs have goals of their own.
5) If all NSNSLTs have goal of their own then all NSNSLTs have morally
considerable teleofunctional interests.
6) Thus, all NSNSLTs have morally considerable teleofunctional interests.
Ruth Millikan stresses the importance of how being "selected for" is important for a thing
to have a proper function, which for Millikan is a functional purpose. She writes,
"To have a proper function an item must also come from a lineage that has
survived due to a correlation between traits that distinguish it and the effects that
are "functions" of these traits, keeping in mind that a correlation is defined by
contrasting positive with negative instances. Intuitively, these traits have been
selected for [my emphasis] reproduction over actual competitors. Because the
correlation must be a result of a causal effect of the trait, the trait will not merely
have been "selected" but will have been "selected for" (Sober 1984). Thus a
thing's proper functions are akin, intuitively, to what it does by design, or on
purpose, rather than accidentally." (Millikan, 2002, p. 8).
Likewise, Millikan draws the connection between a structure being "selected for" and it
having a purpose when she writes,
"In sum, if we look at the whole human person in the light of our history of
evolution by natural selection,…it appears that all levels of purpose have their
origin in adaptation by some form of selection [my emphasis]. In this sense, all
purposes are ‘‘natural purposes.’’ Even though there are, of course, many
important differences among these kinds of purposes, there is a univocal sense of
‘purpose’ in which they are all exactly the same." (Millikan, 2004, p. 13)
In other words, in order for a structure to have a functional purpose it is necessary that it
be selected for performing a certain functional task.
Jay Rosenberg has also made the following comments regarding Millikan's connection
between functional purpose and being selected for. He writes,
211
Some might disagree with this proposition and regard the possession of functional purposes
for teleofunctional structures to not be a sufficient condition for the organism bearing those
structures to have a goal of its own. For the purposes of this dissertation I, however, will not
challenge this premise.
192
"The likenesses to which Millikan wants to direct our attention, in other words,
come into view only from a narrow, limited, and specialized theoretical
perspective, the perspective of biological functionalism. From this perspective,
what counts is the availability of a certain pattern of explanation. Something has a
purpose [my emphasis] just in case the best explanation why it exists or obtains
appeals at some point to ‘‘adaptation by some form of selection.’’
212
Its purpose
is [his emphasis] ‘‘in one way or another, whatever it has been selected for
doing’’ [Millikan, 2004, p. 13] or, more precisely, (Rosenberg, 2007, p. 693).
'the functions of things are effects that these things have, namely, effects
that they have been selected for [my emphasis] causing, or that their
producers have been selected for producing things that will cause, and so
forth. [Millikan, 2004, p. 67]'"
213
But why, exactly, should being "selected for" be necessary for a thing to have a
functional purpose?
I provide the following reason.
We must be clear about what it means for a thing to have a functional purpose. If some
object, x, has a functional purpose, p, then x is for p. For instance, if we say that the functional
purpose of a screwdriver is driving screws into wood, then it means that the screwdriver is for
driving screws into wood.
But how can any object, including screwdrivers, come to be for anything? How can an
object come to possess a functional purpose? The screwdriver did not accidentally get the
functional purpose of driving screws into wood. It was brought about in such a way so that the
screwdriver might fulfil the task of driving screws in wood. So in order for the screwdriver to be
for driving screws into wood it had to have had an etiology that fashioned it with that functional
purpose in mind. Over the causal history of the screwdriver it was selected for driving screws
212
For reference see the above quote from Millikan on this page.
213
Rosenberg inserts a footnote here. He writes, "As far as I can tell, Millikan uses ‘purpose’
and ‘function’ pretty much interchangeably, as I have just done, although she plainly favors the
former..." (Rosenberg, 2007, p. 693)
193
into wood.
214
In this case the screwdriver was selected by the engineer for the functional
purpose of driving screws into wood. In this way the screwdriver was "selected for" driving
screws into wood.
All other things that we normally think have functional purposes must have been selected
for their functional tasks too. The heart, presumably, has the functional purpose of pumping
blood because it was selected for pumping blood. The butterfly's wing is for flight, has the
functional purpose of flight, because it was selected for flight. And the disc brake is for stopping
vehicles because it was selected to stop vehicles.
This way of thinking about functional purposes and being selected for has, of course,
spilled over into the domain of biological structures. Natural selection, it is claimed by Millikan,
selects all manner biological structures for functional purposes. For instance, natural selection
selected the heart for pumping blood and that is why it has the functional purpose of pumping
blood. Likewise, natural selection selected the cell membranes of single-celled organisms for
selectively filtering matter. These naturally selected cell membranes have the functional purpose
of selectively filtering matter.
However, the view that natural selection can select structures for functional tasks is
untenable. One might grant, for purposes of expediency, that the biological structures of
naturally-selected living things have Millikinian proper functions. But they were not actually
selected for any functional purposes. A naturally-selected heart, for example, might be said to
have the Millikanian proper function of pumping blood because past performances of pumping
blood were adaptive for ancestral heart-bearers. But that does not mean that the heart has the
214
The "selected for" here is referring to the screwdriver being designed. It was designed for
driving screws into wood.
194
functional purpose of pumping blood. A naturally-selected heart does not have the functional
purpose of pumping blood because pumping blood is not what that heart was selected for.
The reason why we should say that the heart was not selected for pumping blood is
because the naturally-selected heart was not selected in order to pump blood. For a structure to
have a functional purpose it must at least have been brought about in such a way that is was
selected for some functional task or selected in order to or so that that task would be brought
about. For example, screwdrivers were brought about in order to drive screws into wood. They
were selected for driving screws into wood. But it is not true that the roots of naturally-selected
trees were selected for absorbing water or brought about in order to absorb water. For a structure
to have a functional purpose means for it to be brought about by a process in which there was
some selection for it.
But this is just what natural selection cannot do. A structure could only have a
Millikanian proper function but it could not have a functional purpose understood as a functional
task that it was selected for. This means that if we are going to talk about structures that have
naturally-selected, proper functions we must work with the understanding that those structures
were not selected for a functional task and that functional purposes belonging to structures that
were selected for a functional task.
My argument against the existence of structures that have naturally-selected functional
purposes is the following:
1) If the naturally-selected heart has the functional purpose of pumping blood,
then it was selected for pumping blood.
2) But, the naturally-selected heart was not selected for pumping blood.
3) Thus, the naturally-selected heart does not have the functional purpose of
pumping blood.
Jerry Fodor has commented on the basic nature of this problem as well. The problem, in
essence, is that natural selection cannot truly select any trait or structure for some functional end.
195
He writes,
"Here's the problem: you can read adaptationism as saying that environments
select creatures for their fitness; or you can read it as saying that environments
select traits for their fitness. It looks like the theory must be read both ways if it's
to do the work that it's intended to: on the one hand, forces of selection must act
on individual creatures since it is individual creatures that live, struggle,
reproduce and die. On the other hand, forces of selection must act on traits since it
is phenotypes - bundles of heritable traits - whose evolution selection theory
purports to explain. It isn't obvious, however, that the theory of selection can
sustain both readings at once. Perhaps the consensus view among Darwinists is
that phenotypes evolve because fit individuals are selected for the traits that make
them fit. This way of putting it avoids the ambiguity, but whether it's viable
depends on whether adaptationism is able to provide the required notion of
'selected for' [my emphasis]; and it seems, on reflection, that maybe it can't.
Hence the current perplexity...The present worry is that the explication of natural
selection by appeal to selective breeding is seriously misleading, and that it
thoroughly misled Darwin. Because breeders have minds, there's a fact of the
matter about what traits they breed for; if you want to know just ask them. Natural
selection, by contrast, is mindless; it acts without malice aforethought. That
strains the analogy between natural selection and selective breeding, perhaps to
the breaking point. What, then, is the intended interpretation when one speaks of
natural selection? The question is wide open as of this writing." (Fodor, 2007, p.
19-20).
Although the question of what the intended interpretation of "selected for" should be
when one speaks of natural selection is open for Fodor, it is not open when the intended
interpretation of "selected for" should be when one speaks of intentional selection or conscious
design. Perhaps this is the only way that being "selected for" can be faithfully interpreted.
215
Paul Davies thinks that even the term "proper function", construed as a normative
function, should be done away with because naturally selected proper functions are not truly
normative. He thinks that naturally selected structures simply do not, properly speaking, have
proper, as opposed to improper, functions. As Davies writes, “…our understanding of functions
[my emphasis] must be reformed to better fit a progressive orientation toward inquiry, and that
215
In the next chapter, I provide a defense for this interpretation of what being "selected for"
means.
196
requires giving up our traditionally normative understanding of functions” (Davies, 2009, p. 55).
The "normative understanding" that Davies is referring to here is the Millikanian view that
naturally-selected structures have functional purposes. He thinks that we should cease referring
to the functions of naturally-selected structures as proper functions where proper functions
denote functional purposes.
Davies argues that proper functions, insofar as they are claimed to represent organismic
or structural purposes in biology, cannot survive the insights that Darwin has provided us. He
thinks that virtually all attempts to ground functional norms, understood as what structures are
‘supposed’ to do, or 'meant' to do, on the basis of past reproductive success via natural selection,
are bound to fail. In particular, he argues that mere past reproductive success tells us nothing
about the current functional utility that a structure has in an individual organism. And so it
cannot give us an account of what that structure should be doing at the present. For Davies,
evolutionary adaptations (which are defined in causal, historical terms) do not entail functional
normativity, in the sense of functional purposes, at all. In addressing the connection between
proper functions and normativity he writes,
"The naturalistic credentials of the theory of proper functions are fraudulent; it
takes only a bit of historical insight to reveal the deceit…This is clear in detail
and in general, in light of what we already know about our history and
constitution...In evolutionary theory, "adaptation" is defined in purely historical
terms. Present-day tokens of a trait qualify as adaptations for some effect if and
only if they descend from a lineage of ancestral tokens that were selectively
successful [my emphasis] by virtue of producing that very effect. And that means
that, by definition, having the property "being an adaptation" tells us nothing
about the other properties of present-day tokens. Or, more modestly, the most it
tells us is that similarly structured organisms in similar ecologies will likely
evolve in ways that converge on a similar functional property....Knowing that
present-day tokens are adaptations in light of their history tells us nothing about,
say, their present utility; they may be adaptations in light of their history but
maladaptive in light of their present situation [my emphasis]. Similarly, being an
adaptation tells us nothing about the normative properties of present-day tokens,
since "being descended from selectively successful ancestors" is distinct from [my
197
emphasis] "being supposed to produce such and such an effect". Success in the
past is not equivalent to possessing a standard of self-evaluation today. What
one's ancestors did in the past tells us nothing about what one is supposed to do
now or in the future." (Davies, 2009, p. 82-83)
According to Davies, advocates of proper functions
216
work on the assumption that there
exist ‘norms of performance’ even though such an assumption is not in keeping with the
"naturalistic orientation of inquiry" that is required by natural selection and by modern science in
general. He writes,
“The assumption is that some effects of some natural objects are genuinely
functional in the sense that such functions entail norms of performance intrinsic
to the relevant traits that underwrite the possibility of malfunctions while other
effects are not genuinely functional, but at best merely useful. I reject this
assumption because I reject the claim that some natural objects possess intrinsic
norms of performance. To accept the postulation of such norms is, I argue,
contrary to a naturalistic orientation in inquiry and certainly contrary to the
methods and postulations of the theory of evolution by natural selection” (Davies,
2000, p. 103-104).
Both Elliot Sober and Jay Odenbaugh have recognized the overall difficulty of arriving at
functional norms or proper functions by way of a naturalistic evolutionary story. For Sober
references to past fitness are not enough to secure current functional norms. He writes,
“What we should conclude is that these functional notions of normality are not to
be characterized in terms of a historical notion of fitness. Perhaps they can be
understood in some other way; that remains to be seen” (Sober, 1980, p. 378).
For Odenbaugh the move from a naturalistic ontology to a normative function for
naturally-selected structures appears rather daunting. He writes, “…the difficulty is making sense
of normativity in a wholly natural world” (Odenbaugh, 2015, p. 2).
217
Natural selection etiological accounts of functions are unable to give a truly teleological
216
What Davies also calls “selected functions”.
217
I am not here arguing that normativity itself is impossible under an assumption of
naturalism, only that normativity is, as Odenbaugh argues, is a "difficulty" on a naturalist
assumption.
198
explanation of function, an explanation of what some structure was selected for (in other words
its functional purpose) in the context of why it was brought about for that purpose. According to
Cummins and Davies, natural selection etiological functional explanations cannot tell us why
some structure has the functional purpose that it does. This problem can be put in the following
way. “If we are to construe proper functions as descriptions of what various structures “should”
do, or as Millikan says what they are “supposed to” do, how are we to understand what it is that
they “should” do in light of the fact that they weren’t even selected for bringing about the very
functional end that they presumably did bring about?”
So if the biocentrist wants to make the argument that naturally-selected, non-sentient
beings have goals of their own, then they will be not able to justify that view on the claim that
they have structures with functional purposes. And if the implications of the Darwinian view of
life are really correct then the environmentalist’s project of showing that naturally-selected,
proper functions denote functional purposes is a non-starter.
VIII. Natural Selection and Aristotelianism
The notion of having a goal of one's own is closely tied to the concept of interests defined
as "a good of one's own". The connection between them can be illustrated in the following way.
Those things that have goals of their own have them because they embark on activities "aimed
at" their own self-preservation, sustenance, etc. and that goal belongs to the organism itself. Self-
regulatory activities are good for the thing that pursues them and these activities do not exist for
some other extrinsic purpose. Biocentrists think that interference with these kinds of goals is
prima facie wrong.
For many biocentrists, the claim that all naturally-selected living things have their own
199
goals is based on the view that the process of natural selection can generate structures that have
functional purposes. It is then claimed that since proper functions denote functional purposes
then it also generates organisms that have goals of their own.
218
But as I have previously
argued, natural selection cannot generate structures that have teleofunctional purposes. Hence,
the claim they have teleofunctional purposes cannot serve as an antecedent condition for
naturally-selected living things to have their own goals.
Still, others insist that naturally selected living organisms do have goals of their own.
Daniel Nicholson, for example, argues that living organisms are intrinsically purposive
while artificially selected machines are only extrinsically purposive. He contrasts living
organisms with machines by arguing that the parts or structures of naturally-selected beings
exercise functional purposes for the good of the whole organism and that exist only for its good.
Artifactual machines, on the other hand, have parts or structures that do not exist only for its
good. Their structures exist also for the goals or purposes of the designer of the machine. As he
writes,
"...the parts of both machines and organisms have functions, given that in each
case the immediate beneficiary of their operation is the whole system to which
they belong, be it a machine or an organism. The key difference here is that in the
case of the machine, the function of the whole is in turn good for an external
agent, namely the maker or user of the machine. In contrast, in the case of the
organism, the concatenation of functional beneficiaries is avoided because the
system is intrinsically purposive and consequently does not serve the interests of
218
Gary Varner, for example, argues that an organism "A has an interest in X if an only if...X
would fulfill some biological function of some organ or subsystem of A, where X is a biological
function of S in A if and only if
(a) X is a consequence of A's having S and
(b) A has S because achieving X was adaptive for A's ancestors." (Varner, 1998, p. 68)
For further discussion of Varner see sections II and III of chapter two. For Varner, a biological
function is basically a Millikanian proper function and an interest is, by definition, morally
considerable. Also an interest, for Varner, represents having a goal or aim that can be identified
without reference to something outside of the thing that has that interest. That is things that have
interests have their own goals.
200
an external agent." (Nicholson, 2013, p. 671)
Basically Nicholson is arguing that living organisms have their own purposes because
their structures and parts are for their self-maintenance and preservation. Naturally selected, non-
sentient beings have structures that are for their preservation and self-maintenance because their
structures have organismic preservation and self-maintenance as their functional purpose.
But what could motivate the view that non-sentient, naturally-selected beings are
intrinsically purposive or have goals of their own?
An answer to that question lies in an Aristotelian conception of natural selection and of
non-sentient, living things and their processes. Many biocentrists arguing for the existence of the
inherent worth of all living things work on the assumption that living things, including all non-
sentient, living things, have their own Aristotelian "telos" or purposiveness. These biocentrists,
according to Hans-Jürgen Link,
“rel[y] on the observation that living beings appear to aspire to an inherent end;
after all, even biologists seem to give a functional description of life. Plants, for
example, grow, seek nutrition and reproduce. In an Aristotelian diction, organisms
give the impression of being directed towards a telos…Even if less complex life
forms do not have experiences, it is argued, to compromise a living organism is
contrary to its ‘interests’ and therefore morally wrong since it is not appropriate to
its natural telos” (Link, 2013, p. 439).
A basic, biocentric argument for the existence of the inherent worth of naturally-selected,
non-sentient beings by recourse to Aristotelian purposes might look something like the
following.
1) All NSNSLTs have intrinsic, Aristotelian purposes.
2) If all NSNSLTs have intrinsic, Aristotelian purposes, then all NSNSLTs have
goals of their own.
3) Thus, all NSNSLTs have goals of their own.
4) If all NSNSLTs have goals of their own, then all NSNSLTs have morally
considerable teleofunctional interests.
4) Thus, all NSNSLTs have morally considerable teleofunctional interests.
5) If all NSNSLTs have morally considerable teleofunctional interests, then all
NSNSLTs have inherent worth.
201
6) Thus all NSNSLTs have inherent worth.
In order for the conclusion of the argument to be established by the premises given it
must be the case that premise one is true.
What I want to consider at this point are the arguments in support of premise one, the
claim that all naturally selected, non-sentient living things have intrinsic, Aristotelian purposes.
There appear to exist two separate arguments for this claim.
One argument relies on the premise that natural selection is itself some kind of purposive
or directed process that can generate the intrinsic, Aristotelian purposes of all living things.
Natural selection is in some way guided by some kind of overarching directionality or
teleology
219
in which various forms of living things are in some sense "aimed at" by the process
of natural selection itself.
An argument in support of premise one that employs such a premise is the following. I
call this argument the "Aristotelian Natural Selection Argument".
1) If natural selection is a purposive, directed process, then all NSNSLTs have
intrinsic, Aristotelian purposes.
2) Natural selection is a purposive, directed process.
3) Thus, all NSNSLTs have intrinsic, Aristotelian purposes.
The view that the evolution of life is directed in some way stems from the basic
Aristotelian view that there is a "top-down" structure to reality including the existence and form
of all living things. As Mariusz Tabaczek writes,
"While the predecessors of his philosophical reflection on nature found it
necessary to specify the most basic and enduring entities, and define the
principles of the compositional explanation of everything else, Aristotle opted for
a “top-down” approach in life-sciences. As the first anti-reductionist, he argued
that natural objects owe their characteristic modes of being and acting to their
formal natures. Aristotle’s way of doing biology reflected the basic principles of
219
Henri Bergson is an example of a philosophers that embraces a form of evolutionary change
for the existence of living things that is guided or directed. See his book Creative Evolution.
202
his substance metaphysics founded on the concepts of hylomorphism (material
and formal composition of entities), teleology, essence, chance and necessity, and
thus remained in opposition to materialistic and reductionist explanations found
among Pre-Socratics." (Tabaczek, 2014, p.57)
Some biocentrists might want to argue that the evolutionary process of natural selection
is goal-directed and purposive, a process capable of directing itself in certain ways so that the
things produced by it are in some sense "meant" to occur. The changes that take place in nature,
according to this view, are ultimately not undirected or blind.
Aristotle himself espoused support for the view that there was some kind of teleology in
nature and that living things and their structures were constructed in such a way that they would
fulfill some functional ends.
As Fran O'Rourke writes,
"Teleology is equally obvious for Aristotle both within the internal behavior and
the outward activity of the living organism: here too there is manifest order. From
his observations of animals, Aristotle concluded that the structure of the body is
so constructed by nature as best to fulfill a definite function [my emphasis]; so
too, more minutely, are its parts. The bird's wings are shaped so that it can fly; the
fins of the fish are so designed since its nature is to swim in water. 'Nature,'
Aristotle declares, 'makes nothing without a purpose but always with a view to the
best possible for each individual, preserving the particular substance and essence
of each'.
220
(O'Rourke, 2004, p. 19)
On this view nature constructs living things in order to "fulfill a definite function."
But, natural selection, properly understood, is an undirected, purposeless process. It does
not "aim" for anything. So the claim that all naturally selected living things get their intrinsic,
Aristotelian purposes because they were naturally-selected is a non-starter. This, of course, does
not show that Aristotelianism is false only that natural selection as a process is itself non-
Aristotelian.
220
Here O'Rourke footnotes Aristotle's On the Progression of Animals 8.708a9-12.
203
According to John Dewey, the Aristotelian way of thinking about purposes must
ultimately be done away with if we are to maintain a basic Darwinian perspective on the
development of life. He addresses the consequences of the Darwinian picture of the world as it
relates to the question of purpose and the moral concerns of human beings. Purposefulness had
previously provided an explanation for why things had some moral value. But this is no longer
the case. He writes,
"Purposefulness accounted for the intelligibility of nature and the possibility of
science, while the absolute or cosmic character of this purposefulness gave
sanction and worth to the moral and religious endeavors of man....The Darwinian
principle of natural selection cut straight under this philosophy. If all organic
adaptations are due simply to constant variation and the elimination of those
variations which are harmful in the struggle for existence that is brought about by
excessive reproduction, there is no call for a prior intelligent causal force to plan
and preordain them." (Dewey, 2009, pp. 58-59)
Although Aristotelian forms are not themselves intelligent causal forces they are
instances of preordination. If Dewey is right it looks like the advocate of an Aristotelian
conception of living things cannot appeal to a specifically Darwinian, natural selection process as
a means of explaining the existence of the functional purposes or inherent goals of all living
things.
In any event, if it is true that natural selection is an undirected, rather than a directed,
process, then premise two of the "Aristotelian Natural Selection Argument" is false. This in turn
means that the argument is unsound. The fact that natural selection is an undirected process does
not prove that naturally selected, non-sentient organisms do not have intrinsic, Aristotelian
purposes. Nonetheless, it does show that if naturally selected, non-sentient living things do turn
out to have intrinsic, Aristotelian purposes it would not be because those living things were
naturally selected.
This leaves a second argument that a biocentrist might use for the claim that all naturally
204
selected, non-sentient living things have intrinsic, Aristotelian purposes.
This argument begins with the premise that all naturally-selected, non-sentient living
things, are members of a species. In turn, all naturally-selected, non-sentient living things have
structures that have functional purposes as defined by the norm of the species. Living organisms
themselves have their own Aristotelian purposes because their structures have inherent
functional purposes that "aim at" fulfilling their proper functional role as dictated by the species
or kind to which the organism belongs.
This argument, which I call the "Aristotelian Natural Goodness Argument" might look
like the following:
1) All NSNSLTs are members of a species.
2) If all NSNSLTs are members of species then all NSNSLTs have structures that
have Aristotelian functional purposes.
3) If all NSNSLTs have structures that have Aristotelian functional purposes, then
all NSNSLTs have goals of their own.
4) If all NSNSLTs have goals of their own, then all NSNSLTs have morally
considerable interests.
5) Thus, all NSNSLTs have morally considerable interests.
What I want to examine here is an argument for premise two that comes by way of
Philippa Foot and her account of functional purpose via Aristotelian categoricals.
Philippa Foot and Rosalind Hursthouse argue that different species have characteristic
"natural goods" or inherent purposes that are appropriate for their kinds
221
. According to Foot
all species have their own particular way of life or life cycle that includes such things as their
species’ development, reproduction, self-sustenance, feeding, etc.
Teleological statements, statements about what the functional goal of an organism’s
221
Foot’s and Hursthouse’s views on natural goodness are very similar. I will, thus, focus mainly
on Foot’s discussion of natural goodness of living organisms. For more info on Hursthouse’s view
see her 1999 book On Virtue Ethics.
205
structure is, are statements about those structures, traits or processes that exist the context of the
organism’s species. An example of this way of thinking about the purposes of a living thing’s
structures is described by Foot in the following way. She writes, “There is an Aristotelian
categorical about the species peacock to the effect that the male peacock displays its brilliant tail
in order to [her emphasis] attract a female during the mating season” (Foot, 2001, p.31).
One initial objection to Foot's notion of Aristotelian categoricals comes from the
recognition that species themselves don't seem to represent precise, ordering categories in nature
at all. The species that exist in nature are remarkably diverse and have gone through all sorts of
gradual changes over time. Many species share much in the way of genetic and morphological
overlap.
Natural selection, and the findings from modern evolutionary biology, tell us that
individual organisms don't appear to trace their historical development according to some
preexisting, Aristotelian forms but are genetically malleable in innumerable ways and subject to
all manner of further random genetic changes. These biological findings suggest that the
"categories" are of life are artificial constructs. Although this does not definitively prove that
Aristotelian forms do not exist it nonetheless suggests that there are no formal ordering
characteristics as targets that define what functional purposes are appropriate for an organism. In
fact the myriad possibilities for genetic mutations in living organisms is one of the things that
actually makes gradual evolutionary change by natural selection possible. This means that
species are not stable, prototypical units that have natural purposes as defined by their species or
type. Rather species are dynamic, fluid entities. As Elliot Sober writes,
“The fact that species evolve gradually entails that the boundaries of species are
vague. The essentialist holds that there are characteristics which all and only the
members of species possess. But this is no longer a tenable view; it is just as
implausible as demanding that there should be a precise number of dollars which
206
marks the boundary between rich and poor” (Sober, 1980, p. 356).
Likewise, Sober thinks that the tenuous existence of various biological forms in nature
refutes the Aristotelian claim to a formal telos or purpose regarding individuals of biological
species. He writes,
“…evolutionary theory makes it more plausible to view species as spatio-
temporally extended individuals than as natural kinds. A genuine natural kind like
gold may “go extinct” and then reappear; it is quite possible for there to be gold
things at one time, for there to be no gold at some later time, and then, finally, for
gold to exist at some still later time. But the conception of species given by
evolutionary theory does not allow this sort of flip-flopping in and out of
existence: once a biological taxon goes extinct, it must remain so” (Sober, 1980,
p. 359).
222
For Sober, biological species do not represent natural kinds because biological species,
unlike natural kinds, are not stable but are subject to far too many chance, environmental, genetic
and historical forces that constantly change. On the other hand, gold, a chemical element that is
produced by repeatable, stable and known natural forces, does represent a natural kind. David
Hull, like Sober, emphasizes the view of biological nonessentialism this way:
“…if all gold atoms were to cease existing, the class of gold atoms would
temporarily have no members. Later when atoms arose with the appropriate
atomic number, gold would come into existence again. However, once a species
becomes extinct, it cannot rise again. If a species of flying reptile were to evolve
which was identical in every respect to a species of extinct pterodactyl save
origin, it would have to be classed as a new species” (Hull, 1976, p. 184).
John Nolt argues that we should abandon the Aristotelian orientation of thinking about
the evolutionary development of living organisms as teleologically striving to reach some ideal
222
Like Sober, Stephen J. Gould believes that living organisms will not reemerge once lost to
extinction. The natural selection processes that brings about living organisms and the
circumstances that govern their emergence are so contingent and unrepeatable that it is not
reasonable to think that there is some inherent tendency in nature to produce one species or another.
The haphazard forces and contingencies of natural history would almost never produce the same
type of organism twice. They would, however, produce gold more than once.
207
state. He writes,
“From Plato onward, much of the Western tradition held that for each biological
species there was a single immutable form that defined the ideal of perfection for
its members. But that notion has two fatal flaws: (1) it is incompatible with
Darwinian biology, and (2) even if it were not, it is no longer clear why perfection
in that sense should be good at all…Plato and Aristotle explained the goodness of
perfection by positing a natural tendency of things to strive for, imitate, or
approximate their ideal forms. Perfection was good for an organism, then, because
to realize its ideal form was its natural end, its telos. In medieval theology,
standards of perfection were regarded as divinely ordained. Since Darwin,
however, there has been no reason to believe in ideals that function either as goals
toward which organisms naturally strive or as standards set for them by divine
decree. This is not to say that organisms lack purpose, but only that they lack the
specific purpose of realizing ideals. In what sense, then, could realization of an
ideal (even supposing such things existed) be good for them or, indeed, good at
all?” (Nolt, 2009, p. 139-140).
Foot, however, has a ready answer to these kinds of objections. Her view of functional
purpose is not really an etiological explanation of functional purpose but rather an Aristotelian
categorical one. An Aristotelian categorical explanation of functional purpose does not make
reference to the historical, causal forces that brought about living things. Rather it makes
reference to the species or kind that the organism belongs to at a given point in time. Foot
explains how individual living organisms and their structures can come to possess functional
purposes by recourse to their membership within a species even if species are not themselves
fixed. The normative evaluation of living things and their structures is made independently of the
species etiology. She writes,
"It will no doubt be objected here that reproduction is in fact not fixed, since
species themselves are subject to change [my emphasis]. This is of course
important, and it means that Aristotelian categoricals must take account of sub-
species adapted to local conditions. The history of a species is not, however, the
subject with which Aristotelian categoricals deal [my emphasis]. Their truth is
truth about a species at a given historical time, and it is only the relative stability
of at least the most general features of the different species of living things that
makes these propositions possible at all. They tell how a kind of plant or animal,
considered at a particular time and in its natural habitat, develops, sustains itself,
defends itself, and reproduces." (Foot, 2001, p. 29).
208
Aristotelians also refer to the functional purposes or goals of living things in light of what
it is that they need as dictated by their species. Micah Lott describes Foot’s notion of needs as
connected with the Aristotelian categorical features of a species in the following way:
“Because “the tiger has four legs” is a true Aristotelian categorical, we can also
say that tigers “need” four legs. In this way, Aristotelian categoricals correspond
to what Foot, following Elizabeth Anscombe, refers to as “Aristotelian
necessities.” Here, what is “needed” or “necessary” is that on which good hangs.
In this sense an oak tree “needs” deep roots – to be a good, excellent oak tree, a
particular oak tree must have deep roots, and this is so because deep roots play an
important part in the life of “the oak.” What counts as “necessary” in the case of
living things is determined by the life form. Thus, earthworms do not “need” four
legs as tigers do and “earthworms have four legs” is not a true Aristotelian
categorical because having legs is not part of how the earthworm achieves the
ends that define its life cycle.” (Lott, 2012, p. 357)
On the Aristotelian categorical view, "butterflies have a proboscis" is a true Aristotelian
categorical and since having a proboscis is important in the life of butterflies, individual
butterflies need a proboscis.
223
But this doesn't mean that butterflies need any sort of proboscis.
They need a proboscis that performs its function well or as it is supposed to in keeping with the
part that it plays in the life of "the butterfly" just as deep roots play an in important part in the
life of "the oak".
This implies that the structures of all naturally-selected living things have functional
purposes, functional jobs that those structures are "supposed to" perform as dictated by the
species. An excellent proboscis is one that fulfills its functional purpose in the life of individual
butterflies in the natural kind "butterfly". Sipping nectar is the purpose of the proboscis and so an
excellent proboscis is one that is adept at sipping nectar. However, as I pointed out earlier, the
223
Notice how this differs from a typical categorical statement. The statement "Dogs have four
legs" does not entail the categorical proposition that "All dogs have four legs." The former
statement is an Aristotelian categorical statement while the second is a categorical statement
simpliciter.
209
structures of naturally-selected living things, on an Aristotelian categorical view, will have
functional purposes regardless of whether those organisms were naturally selected or not.
A malformed proboscis does not follow the norm as specified by the type, not as specified
by the causal process that brought about the butterfly. A butterfly with a malformed proboscis
cannot fulfill its purpose as specified by the norm of the type "butterfly". A functioning
proboscis, on the other hand, is one that fits the norm of the type "butterfly" and so does fulfill its
functional purpose as specified by the norm of the type "butterfly".
Foot warns her readers that the term “function” can be interpreted in either an
evolutionary/historical sense or in a sense of what is 'good' for the organism that bears a structure
with that function. She stresses the use of the term function in the latter sense as occupying a
special place in the actual lives of living things. Those functions that an individual living thing’s
structures have are those functional purposes that are conducive to its self-maintenance,
nourishment and reproduction as appropriate to its species. In a footnote to chapter two of her
book “Natural Goodness” she writes,
“It is imperative that the word ‘function’ as used here is not confused with its use
in evolutionary biology, where, as Simon Blackburn has put it in the Oxford
Dictionary of Philosophy, ‘the function of a feature of an organism is frequently
defined as that role it plays which has been responsible for its genetic success and
evolution’(149-50). Features that are functional in this sense are what Dawkins,
for instance, calls ‘adaptations’, when he defines an adaptation both historically
and as ‘approximately an attribute of an organism that is “good for something”’
(The Extended Phenotype, 290). In such contexts it is supposed to make sense to
speak of the good of a species, as if a species were itself a gradually developing,
one-off organism, whose life might stretch for millions of years. Perhaps the
extinction of a species is imagined as a kind of death, and therefore as if it were
an evil with that which makes for its continuance thought of as ‘for its good’! It is
easy to confuse these technical uses of words such as ‘function’ and ‘good’ with
their everyday uses, but the meanings are distinct. To say that some feature of a
living thing is an adaptation is to place it in the history of a species. To say that it
has a function is to say that it has a certain place in the life of the individuals that
belong to that species at a certain time.” (my emphasis, Foot, 2001, p. 32).
Foot is using the term ‘function’ not to refer to some evolutionary adaptation, what Ruth
210
Millikan might call a "proper function" or what Gary Varner would call a "biological function",
but, as she puts it, to “a certain place in the life of the individuals that belong to that species at a
certain time”
224
. These functions, accordingly are functional purposes not because those
functions arose out of a process of the natural selection of previously adapted ancestors but
because they are the natural functional features of the organism’s species.
Foot then extends the notion of purposiveness beyond just the structures of all living
things to include individual living things themselves. Individual organisms have their own goals
or purposes, things that they in some sense "intend" to do, or are "supposed" to do, as specified
by their species or type.
But Foot warns her readers that the existence of these kinds of purposes does not always
mean that all living things have those purposes in an intentional or psychological sense. Instead
all living things have purposes of their own in a derivative sense in that they acquired their
purposes through their membership within a species. She writes,
"There is an Aristotelian categorical about the species peacock to the effect that
the male peacock displays its brilliant tail in order to [her emphasis] attract a
female during the mating season. The display serves this purpose. Let us call such
language, purposive language. But be careful here! Where something that S's do
is, in this sense, purposive we should beware of slipping over into saying of an
individual S that it has [her emphasis] this purpose when it does this thing. Plants
grow upwards in order to get to the light, but it is fanciful to say that that is what
my honeysuckle is trying to do or that that is 'its end' [my emphasis]". (Foot,
2001, p. 31)
224
Foot writes that the question of functional normativity is not a mere question that can be
answered by an evolutionary account such as Millikan’s. She writes, “We are not interpreting it
[the question of functional normativity] as a historical question, as ‘proper function’ is interpreted,
for instance, by Ruth Millikan in Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories, chapter 1,
and as function’ would generally be interpreted in evolutionary biology. As Wiggins says in
Postscript 4 in Needs, Values, Truth, 353, ‘we really need to describe what morality has become
[his emphasis], a question on which evolutionary theory casts no particular light’” (Foot, 2001,
p.40)
211
Foot then makes a distinction between plants and animals in that although plants engage
in certain activities that they are supposed to perform as specified by their type, other living
things such as some animals do seem to have their own intentional purposes in the sense that
they actually intend to engage in various self-maintaining activities. She writes,
“If we ask either with regard to a plant or to an animal why it does a certain thing
or has a certain characteristic, we are satisfied with an answer that places this
operation in the life of that species [my emphasis]. Moreover, if we consider the
concepts involved we should be surprised to be told that there is no common
meaning or shared logical structure between evaluations of botanical and
zoological subjects. The common structure of evaluation seems unaffected by the
radical difference between the two. Animals operate very differently from plants,
because perception plays a large part in the way that they gain nourishment,
defend themselves, and reproduce. Yet there is no reason offhand to suppose that
the word 'function' has a different meaning in a sentence about the function of the
spreading of a peacock's tail and in one that speaks of the opening of a flower in
sunlight. There seems to be identity in the general structure of such explanations
throughout the sub-rational world, in spite of the differences appearing in a range
of subsidiary concepts. It is true, for example, that an answer to a ‘Why?’
question about an animal may be in terms of appetite and therefore not just about
what it needs but also about what it wants: even about what it 'tries to do'. Since
plants do not have desires or appetites, no feature or operation in a plant can be
explained by what it wants, and although we sometimes say that a plant is 'trying
to get to the light', this must be recognized as a fanciful use of words. Yet we find,
as already suggested, the same structural terminology as of goodness or defect
relating to parts, characteristics, and operations, and also terms such as 'function'
and 'purpose' and expressions such as 'in order to' or 'in order that' in things as
different from each other as plants and animals.” (Foot, 2001, p. 40-41).
While it is true that a peacock can intentionally extend its tail feathers 'in order to' attract
a mate it is not true that a honeysuckle plant can likewise intentionally extend its leaves 'in order
to' acquire sunlight. The phrase 'in order to' can be interpreted in two different senses. In one
sense the phrase 'in order to' can refer to intentionally guided behaviors and actions. The male
peacock probably has enough intentional states to actually desire to, want to or intend to extend
its tail feathers. Likewise, my dog is capable of intending to drink water in order to quench his
thirst. On this sense of 'in order to' animals can have goals or purposes of their own in that their
intentional states, preferences, desires, etc. are in some sense original to them.
212
But plants, on Foot's view, also seem to have purposes that are original to them as well,
purposes of their own. So how are we to interpret what a plant does when Foot says that it
extends its leaves 'in order to' acquire sunlight? Foot's answer is that the 'in order to' in this
different, second sense is one of the Aristotelian categoricals about what plants do. The
honeysuckle plant extends its leaves in order to get sunlight, not because it is capable of desiring
to gather sunlight, but because that is what individual honeysuckle plants are supposed to do as
defined by their group or species. Likewise the male peacock has its own purpose of displaying
its tail during mating season, not simply because it actually intends to display its tail feathers
during mating season, but because tail display itself is a functional purpose of the peacock's tail
as defined by its species.
The proponent of Aristotelian natural goodness argues that membership within a species,
not its natural selection etiology, is all that is needed for an individual living thing within that
group to have functional purposes and goals of its own. The defender of Aristotelian natural
goodness could say, "Foot is right to say that individual honeysuckle plants extend their leaves in
order to acquire sunlight in virtue of their being members of the species 'honeysuckle'. In fact,
all living things, sentient and non-sentient alike, have purposes of their own where such purposes
are defined by their membership within a species."
But then we can inquire as whether it is true that non-sentient living things can indeed
have purposes of their own in virtue of being a member of a species. We can inquire into
whether premise two of the "Aristotelian Natural Goodness Argument" is correct.
Consider the following thought experiment. Imagine that a million Instant Artos all
suddenly popping into existence at the same time and in the same habitat due to a single
lightning bolt striking a shallow pond. All of these individual cells have the exact same
213
biological constitution, have the same basic way of life and engage freely in reproduction with
one another.
If we consider this group of organisms to be a "species", in the sense that they are all
similar in the above ways, then according to the proponent of Aristotelian natural goodness we
would have to say that the individual cells within the group conform to a true Aristotelian
categorical statement about the species 'Instant Arto'. One such statement is "All Instant Artos
are selective matter filterers". In turn this would mean that each individual Instant Arto would
have a purpose of its own of selectively filtering matter simply by the fact that the individual
belongs to a group or species. Given that that is a true Aristotelian categorical statement about
the species 'Instant Arto' then each individual Instant Arto in the entire group would have a
purpose of its own of selectively filtering matter.
But does that seem correct?
These single-celled organisms would be regarded as having purposes of their own even if
their teleofunctional structures were not selected for any teleofunctional purposes. This claim is
at odds with the view that in order for an object or structure to have a functional purpose it must
have been produced by a causal history that "selected it for" a functional purpose. The
Aristotelian categorical position would claim that there is no need for references to what some
structure was "selected for". A structure's being "selected for" a functional purpose is not needed
for that thing to have a functional purpose.
So, is being a member of a group enough to make it the case that a living thing has
structures that are for any functional purposes? This seems a rather odd position to hold.
The structures of Instant Arto were not selected for any teleofunctional purposes yet on
an Aristotelian categorical view it would turn out that its structures have teleofunctional purposes
214
anyway just by recourse to membership of the organism within a species. As I have previously
argued, having structures that were selected for teleofunctional purposes is a necessary condition
for a non-sentient living thing to have a purpose of its own. But the defender of Aristotelian
categoricals would deny this. They would argue that the structures of instant, non-sentient
organisms have teleofunctional purposes. Their cell membranes not only perform the
teleofunction of selectively filtering matter, but they have the teleofunction of selectively
filtering matter even if their membranes were not "selected for" selectively filtering matter.
At this point the defender of Aristotelian natural goodness could respond by saying, "Yes
Instant Arto is a genuine species. Even though it seems like they do not have structures with
teleofunctional purposes they really do simply because of their membership within the species
'Instant Arto'". Should the defender of Aristotelian natural goodness go in for this view then it
wouldn't matter at all what a species etiology is for it to have structures with functional purposes.
The defender of Aristotalian natural goodness, however, could go the other way and
respond by simply denying that Instant Arto is a true species. They might not like the implication
that an instantly-produced group of organisms could really have structures that have functional
purposes. As such they might try to find some way of denying that a group of instant organisms
could count as a species. They might respond by saying "Instant Arto is not really species. Even
if a million instant organisms were all brought about by the same causal process and were all the
same biologically, that does not qualify them to be members of a species because in order for a
group of organisms to belong to a species it must be a group that was brought about in the right
sort of way, a causal process that adapted it to
225
the conditions of its environment. In order for
a group of organisms to belong to a species that group must itself have been adapted to its
225
Being "adapted to" here should be interpreted in non-psychological, non-intentionalist terms.
215
environment. 'Instant Arto' was not brought about by a process that adapted it to its environment.
Hence, it is not adapted to its environment. Hence, it is not a true species."
Notice that this kind of response does make reference to the etiology of a group of
organisms as being a necessary requirement for that group to be counted as a species and thus for
the individuals in that group to have structures with teleofunctional purpose and thus have
purposes of their own. In particular a species is one that was brought about by an etiology that
adapted it to its environment.
However, Foot claims that how a species came about is irrelevant to whether the
organisms within it conform to an Aristotelian categorical. To quote from Foot again,
"The history of a species is not [my emphasis], however, the subject with which
Aristotelian categoricals deal. Their truth is truth about a species at a given
historical time, and it is only the relative stability of a least the most general
features of the different species of living things that makes these propositions
possible at all." (Foot, 2001, p. 29).
The defender of Aristotelian natural goodness might say in response, "Foot is simply
wrong to suggest that the truth of Aristotelian categoricals does not depend in any way on the
etiology of the group. The truth of Aristotelian categoricals does depend on the etiology of the
group under consideration. The truth of a group's Aristotelian categoricals depends on whether
that group was adapted to its environment. Only things that are adapted to their environment get
to count as a species and get to count as having Aristotelian categoricals."
But there is a problem for this move.
If the defender of Aristotelian categoricals makes this argument and they claim that
natural selection itself is the only etiology responsible for adapting a species to its environment,
then it also looks like an instant organism type etiology can likewise adapt a group of organisms
to its environment. The instant organisms referred to in the above thought experiment were all
adapted to their environment in the sense that they were able to survive and thrive perfectly well
216
under the conditions in which they were found. Likewise, a naturally-selected group of single-
celled organisms can be regarded as adapted to their environment for the same reason. If it turns
out that they are capable of surviving and thriving in their habitat, then they are adapted to that
habitat. Claims about what adapts an organism to its environment are in this way susceptible to
being mere "post-hoc" claims.
In a footnote to his paper "Against Darwinism" Jerry Fodor argues that the claim that
natural selection adapts organisms to their environment is "post-hoc". He writes,
"As usual, not attending to the intensionality of one’s explanatory constructs
eventuates in all sorts of silliness [my emphasis]. Thus Jarrel Diamond (in his
Introduction to Ernst Mayr’s What Evolution Is Basic Books, 2001) wonders
(rhetorically) ‘How can one explain the remarkable adaptation of every species to
its chosen niche?‘ (p. x). Likewise Sober (1993) p.186: “The exquisite fit of
organisms to their environments is one of the central phenomena that the theory
of evolution by natural selection attempts to explain.” (See also passages from
Dobzhansky quoted on p 49 of Sterelny and Griffiths.)
226
But, so long as `degree
of fitness’ and `the organism’s environment’ are specified post-hoc, there’s
nothing here to wonder at except a tautology. If a certain creature fails to occupy a
certain niche exactly, then it just follows that that isn’t exactly the niche that the
creature occupies. Imagine a research program directed to explaining why each
creature fits so precisely into the corresponding hole in space. Would the NSF be
well-advised to fund it? "Or imagine Scrooge before his tragic capitulation: `The
chap who is living in the gutter on scraps from the tables of the rich has nothing to
complain of, for he is perfectly adapted to living in exactly the way that he does;
viz in the gutter on scraps from the tables of the rich.’ This would be a joke if it
were funny." (Fodor, 2008b, p. 21)
In other words, it makes just as much sense to claim that a group of instant organisms is
"adapted to" its environment, should it turn out to survive and thrive in its environment, as it is to
say that a naturally selected group of organisms is "adapted to" its environment, should it happen
226
Fodor does not provide a complete references for Sober's quote nor from his mention of
Sterelney and Griffiths in the references cited section of his paper. The quote from Sober can be
found on page 172 of Sober's book The Nature of Selection: Evolutionary Theory in
Philosophical Focus (Sober, 1984). The reference to Dobzhansky by Sterelny and Griffiths is
found in the book Sex and Death: An Introduction Philosophy of Biology (Sterelny and Griffiths,
1999).
217
to survive in its environment. In this way the 'adaptation' or being 'adapted to' is, as Fodor
suggests, "post-hoc". Both an instant organism etiology and a natural selection are capable of
producing organisms that are adapted to their environment.
So clearly having an etiology that results in a group of organisms being "adapted to" their
environment is not enough for that group of organisms to be counted as a species. Instant
organisms are adapted to their environment even though the defender of Aristotelian natural
goodness would claim they are not a species.
It might also be urged that the claim that natural selection really adapts a group of
organism to their environment is not true. It might be reasonable to think that natural selection
does not really adapt organisms to their environment. In order for a causal process to adapt
something to some environment there must be some kind of intentionality or directionality to that
process so that the thing being adapted to the environment is guided in some way. But natural
selection is an undirected, unguided process. As such, it cannot, properly speaking, adapt a
group of organisms to an environment.
So the defender of Aristotelian natural goodness is still left with the question, "Just
exactly what is needed for a group of organisms to be counted as a species?" Well, one place to
start is by looking at what most biologists think a species is. According to Peter Bowler, modern
biology, as informed by Darwinian evolutionary theory, regards species as "a breeding
population" (Bowler, 2003, p. 5).
But this definition of a species will not help the defender of Aristotelian natural goodness
who wants to deny that a group of instantly-produced organisms could be a species. The problem
is that while naturally-selected organisms can result in a breeding population, a million instantly-
produced organisms can also result in a breeding population. If natural selection itself is claimed
218
to be the etiology responsible for generating a species, then it looks as if that claim is false. An
instant organism type etiology is logically consistent with it being able to generate a species.
227
The defender of Aristotelian natural goodness cannot on the one hand claim that
membership within a species is what defines the inherent purposes of organisms and on the other
hand claim that a group of instantly-produced organisms cannot be a species. In order to do that
they must make some kind of appeal to the group's etiology. But, Aristotelian natural goodness is
an etiology independent notion. Whatever gets counted as a species has organisms within it that
have structures with functional purposes as defined by their species. If a group of instant
organisms counts as a species, and under an Aristotelian natural goodness perspective there is no
reason to think that they would not, then instantly-produced organisms have structures with
functional purposes too.
But the problem is that instantly-produced organisms do not have structures that were
selected for any teleofunctional purposes. Aristotelian natural goodness would claim that these
organisms get to have functional purposes even if by all appearances they do not.
Apart from these difficulties in spelling out just what should be regarded as a species and
why an instant organism type etiology should not be regarded as species-producing, I would like
to move to a discussion of a more substantial problem for the Aristotelian natural goodness
argument.
For the purposes of the remainder of this section I will assume that Aristotelian
categoricals can result in organisms that have structures with Aristotelian functional purposes.
What I want to argue against is the claim that naturally-selected Aristotelian functional purposes
represent the interests of individual organisms. The Aristotelian Natural Goodness argument
227
A breeding population of organisms can also be brought about by a design etiology as well.
219
claims that there is a rather straightforward relationship between Aristotelian categoricals and
organismic flourishing. Specifically premise four of that argument claims that "If all NSNSLTs
have goals of their own, then all NSNSLTs have morally considerable interests." I want to argue
that this premise of Aristotelian Natural Goodness argument is false.
Morally considerable interests are interests of individual organisms were the fulfillment
of those interests is good for the well-being of the individual organism in question. But there
appear to be cases of "Aristotelian categoricals" that do not represent what is good for the well-
being of individual organisms of a species.
It has been claimed by Foot that living things engage in behaviors that are naturally good
for them. They engage in behaviors that promote their own self-maintenance, reproduction, etc.
These behaviors, behaviors that promote their own good, are specified by the true Aristotelian
categoricals of the species to which the organism belongs. Foot wants to naturalize the
normativity of teleological statements such as "the honeysuckle plant extends its leaves in order
to acquire sunlight" by pointing to some "natural facts" that express what is naturally good for
individual organisms of the species. For her, some of these natural facts, facts concerning what
members of a species or type do, exhibit “patterns of natural normativity” (Foot, 2001, p. 38). So
these natural facts are taken in turn to be teleological facts about the functional purposes of a
living thing's structures that are good for the individual organism itself.
Foot writes,
“…’natural’ goodness, as I define it, which is attributable only to living things
themselves and to their parts, characteristics, and operations, is intrinsic or
‘autonomous’ goodness in that it depends directly on the relation of an individual
to the ‘life form’ of its species.” (Foot, 2001, pp. 26-27).
So, for example, it could be argued that nectar is important for the life of all butterflies.
Butterflies need nectar because it is good for them. The characteristic way that butterflies go
220
about getting nectar is by using the proboscis. That structure aids in the sipping of nectar which
then fulfills the Aristotelian categorical statement that “Butterflies are nectar sippers.” And since
butterflies are nectar sippers the purpose of its proboscis is to aid in the sipping of nectar. A
butterfly must have a functioning proboscis if it is to be successful at sipping nectar. A butterfly
then needs a functioning proboscis because it needs nectar and it needs nectar because nectar is a
characteristic good for all butterflies.
These characteristic “goods” exists for all forms of life.
There are characteristic goods for bacteria, fungi, plants, birds and human beings along
with every other form of life that specifies what the purposes of their structures are. Bacteria, for
instance, have certain purposes that belong specifically to them and not to some other group of
organisms. They have interests in their structures fulfilling their purposes. Fungi, on the other
hand, have a very different way of life and hence have their own purposes.
However, the findings of evolutionary biology suggest that many individual organisms
belong to species that engage in apparently harmful and destructive behaviors, behaviors that do
not seem to be good for or benefit the individual organisms of the species at all. A biocentric
individualist devoted to an Aristotelian categorical view would have to say that these destructive
behaviors represent "natural goodness" too and must also be for the good of the individual
organism just as much as helpful behaviors are naturally good. There is nothing within
Aristotelian natural goodness that can separate harmful and destructive functions from functions
that promote the good of the organism. All that Aristotelian categoricals can give us are
statements about what members of a species do, not whether those features of the species are
actually good for the individual members of that species.
For example, a biocentric individualist devoted to an Aristotelian categorical view of
221
living organisms would have to say that the violent fighting behavior of individual male elephant
seals is good for their well-being and is a purpose of their own even though it doesn't really look
like such behavior is actually good for their well-being at all. Take the following as presented by
Micah Lott:
“A related example involves the dominance hierarchies among male elephant
seals. These seals fight one another to gain exclusive control of the harem,
sometimes to the point of significant injury, and the females of the species
typically refuse to mate with any other than the dominant male. Such behavior,
Fitzpatrick says, makes “perfectly good evolutionary sense,” because the genes
tending to produce such behavior would have out-replicated their rival alleles in
the gene pool. But once again there is no plausible benefit realized by such
behavior: “Can we really suppose that animals fighting desperately with their
peers simply in order to out-reproduce them are thereby acting ‘for their good’, or
for any organism’s good for that matter, making themselves or others better off?
On the contrary, it seems elephants seals could at least in principle get on just as
well without these traits perhaps even better, expending less energy fighting,
avoiding the inevitable injuries, and so on”” (Lott, 2012, p. 364)
The statement "Male elephant seals are violent fighters." is a true Aristotelian categorical
about the species 'elephant seals'. The violent fighting behavior of male elephant seals is a
“natural fact” about all males of that species just as much as it is a “natural fact” that organisms
of that species need and consume food. Hence, engaging in fighting behavior is also one of their
goals.
The problem is that it does not appear as if it is, or would be, one of their interests. It is
one of the things that male elephant seals do and it is expressed in the form of an Aristotelian
categorical, but it does not contribute to well-being of the individual male elephant seal.
Hence, there is no reason to think that this goal represents an interest let alone a morally
considerable interest. Having this goal does not provide a reason to value the individual male
elephant in and of itself. There might be other reasons to value the male elephant seal in and of
itself, but not because it has the goal or purpose of engaging in this kind of violent behavior.
If anything the violent fighting behavior of male elephant seals makes these animals
222
extrinsically valuable for genetic reproduction. But it does not provide a reason to value these
living things in and of themselves.
As William FitzPatrick writes, “These traits are needed if they [male elephant seals] are
to function fully as the sorts of gene replicating systems they are, but they don’t improve the
lives of elephant seals or contribute to their flourishing” (FitzPatrick, 2000, p. 117).
228
Thus
Aristotelian categoricals are not able to identify and separate harmful activities from activities
that are unharmful or beneficial. If there turns out to be some form of violent behavior in the
animal world that appears contrary to a flourishing kind of individual life, then the defendant of
an Aristotelian categorical view of living organisms needs to provide some way of dealing with
these problems.
I call this problem the "problem of harmful Aristotelian categoricals".
In fact, disconcerting natural facts are not uncommon in the natural world at all. For
example, some female warblers kill off the young offspring of rival females in their vicinity.
Presumably this gives females that engage in such behavior a reproductive advantage.
229
On
this view we would have to say that female great reed warblers commit infanticide in order to
spread their genes because that is just what female great reed warblers do and this is beneficial to
the species. This is a natural fact about them. But many of us would find it difficult to further
228
Another example is found in the lifestyle of a microsporidian parasite called Nosema. Nosema
infects larvae of the flour beetle and by its own genetic endowments secretes a chemical analogue
to the larvae’s own juvenile hormone. Nosema produces so much of this hormone that it effectively
causes the larvae to grow larger than normal. This in turn provides are larger shelter for the Nosema
parasite to live in. This facilitates Nosema’s reproduction. Natural selection in this case has
produced one organism, Nosema, with a lifestyle utterly detrimental to another species, the flour
beetle. But natural selection cares neither for the Nosema nor the flour beetle. Also, see p. 87-88
in FitzPatrick, 2000 or Fisher and Sanborn’s paper “Production of Insect Juvenile Hormone by the
Microsporidian Parasite Nosema. (Fisher and Sanborn, 1962).
229
See the article by Hansson et al. “Infanticide in Great Reed Warblers: Secondary Females
Destroy Eggs of Primary Females.” (Hansson et al., 1997).
223
claim that such an activity is a kind of “natural goodness” directed at fulfilling organismic well-
being.
230
This problem can also be illustrated in the opposite way. Some Aristotelian categoricals
would regard some helpful behaviors as being defects of the organism engaging in them.
Consider the following from Timothy J. Clewell's Master's Thesis "The Promise and Limits of
Natural Normativity in a Neo-Aristotelian Virtue Ethics". He writes,
"To give an example, tree squirrels live a predominately solitary life, they breed
about twice a year and the female looks after the young. According to Foot, in
order for a tree squirrel to be described as flourishing [my emphasis] it must be
living a life where these characteristics are realized. This is not simply a claim
about what is required for tree squirrel flourishing, it is also a claim about what
we even mean when we say something is a tree squirrel. For this reason, if a male
squirrel stayed with the female squirrel and they raised the young in tandem, we
can make sense of saying the male squirrel is in some way defective and not
flourishing qua tree squirrel (even if the male’s behavior promotes the survival of
the baby squirrels). We can do so by referring to the characteristics that play a
role in the fulfillment of the teleology of members of the tree squirrel species. But
the only way that such evaluations work is if there is some concept, external to all
particular instantiations (of tree squirrels) by which the particulars are to be
judged. A male tree squirrel, behaving in a way that it actually promotes the well-
being of its offspring, would seem (at least on an account that takes into
consideration its own particular goal) to be flourishing. If one wants to say
otherwise, the criteria by which one judges flourishing must be external to the
apparent goal of the particular life [my emphasis] about which a judgment is
being made." (Clewell, 2011, p. 11-12)
The problem of Aristotelian categoricals could also apply to a group of organisms that
was deliberately designed in the lab primarily for extrinsic ends that have nothing to do with
individual organismic flourishing. A maliciously-designed group of organisms would have true
Aristotelian categoricals about their functional purposes just as much as a naturally-selected
230
Insights such as these led Alfred North Tennyson to depict nature as being “red, in tooth and
claw”. This famous phrase is from Cantro LVI of Tennyson’s poem “In Memoriam A.H.H.”. A
line in the previous cantro (Cantro LV) of that same poem expresses a similar sentiment. Nature
is wasteful, without foresight and “So careless of the single life”. (Tennyson, 1900).
224
group of organisms would have true Aristotelian categoricals about them. A maliciously-
designed group of organisms could have purposes according to their Aristotelian categoricals
that do not promote the well-being the individuals of the groups. William Fitzpatrick discusses
this kind of possibility for those who, like Foot, advocate a conceptual connection between
organismic well-being and what functions that an organism has as ascribed by Aristotelian
categoricals. He writes,
"Perhaps many will still insist - as I believe Foot would - that it is just intuitively
obvious that biological teleology must be understood ultimately in terms of
welfare promotion, claiming that there is simply a conceptual connection between
function in biology and the promotion of welfare of the satisfaction of welfare-
based needs...I'd like to consider a thought experiment that may help to remove
the temptation to suppose that welfare promotion must come into the functional
teleology of living things, weakening the opponent's confidence in such a
conceptual connection...suppose there is an extremely clever inventor who has
discovered in the laboratory how to design and create organic machines that look
and act much like natural organisms, maintaining and reproducing themselves
through very similar methods, including many of the same bio-chemical reactions
and so on. Let us imagine that the similarity is close enough that these machines
are conceded to be alive, and to be such that we can genuinely speak of their
welfare (unlike any machines that have actually been created so far). This
inventor, however, is rather perverse: He is single-mindedly obsessed with the
propagation of the replicating molecules in these machines which correspond to
genes in natural organisms - call them "shmenes" - and cannot be persuaded by
his more conscientious colleagues to place first priority on their welfare as he
designs them. Instead he simply designs his machines simply to work ultimately
toward the most efficient replication of their shmenes, however this affects their
welfare...Now it seems clear to me that what he has created are primarily and
ultimately shmene replicating machines. The functions pertaining to these things
are generally and ultimately related to the end of shmene replication, not to the
promotion of the machines' welfare. The fact that they have welfare at all is
incidental....But now if this is right, then clearly there can be living things whose
functionality does not have generally or ultimately to do with the promotion of
their welfare, but has to do with (in this case) shmene replication. There is not,
therefore, any conceptual connection between function in living things and
welfare promotion. (Fitzpatrick, 2000, p. 189-190)
If we conceive of this group of artificially-produced living machines (let us call them
"Arto Machines") a species, and there's no reason to suppose that are not, then they too must
225
have true Aristotelian categoricals about them based on their membership within the group "Arto
Machines". One of those categoricals might be, "Arto Machines sacrifice their own well-being
for the replication of 'shmenes'". But there is no reason to think that their sacrificial behavior
represents an interest of theirs. In fact such behavior is not really in their interest at all. If
anything the replication of shmenes is in the interest of the designer of Arto Machines. To be
more precise, the teleofunctional purposes of an Arto Machine's structures enable it to maintain
itself but only so that such self-maintaining capacities enhances its ability to replicate shmenes.
It might be objected by Foot, and other defendants of the "natural goodness" view, that
although these instances of violent animal behavior and "shmene replication" might appear to be
destructive or harmful to us they are actually good for the individual organisms of these species
to engage in. It might be claimed that the violent fighting behavior of rival elephant seals, harsh
though it appears to us, is actually very successful in adapting them to the conditions in which
they are found and in which competition for mates is very high.
Likewise, they might also say that instances of male tree squirrels that help rear their
young are actually instances of defective tree squirrels. Although instances of such behavior
might appear to be beneficial to us, they are actually behaviors that are defective and thus bad
for the organisms of the species. "These kinds of objections to natural goodness" they might say,
"are simply an artifact of our tendency to project onto nature our own feelings and expectations
about what is good or bad for living things. We should not anthropomorphize the natural world
and view its normativity through the lens of our own prejudice. Instead we should rely on the
Aristotelian categoricals to speak for themselves and make those judgements for us."
But this objection will not work. The point of the objection to Aristotelian categoricals is
not that we have somehow projected our own prejudices onto nature. Rather the objection is that
226
some Aristotelian categoricals do not always express what is truly good for the life of the
individual organism of the species. In other words, not everything that is an Aristotelian
categorical represents an activity that is truly in the interest of the individual organism of the
species. Individual male elephant seals might desire to engage in violent fighting behavior and
this behavior might be a "natural fact" about them, but this behavior is objectively not good for
the life of the individual male elephant seals of the species regardless of whether we might think
that such behavior is bad or not. Such behavior might be good for the species' own integrity but it
does not actually benefit the individuals of that species. Males of the Autumn Spider, Metellina
segmentata, will fight each other to the death for the advantage to reproduce with a female. As
Prenter et al. write, "In male-male fights for ‘ownership’ of the web in the genus Metellina, the
larger males have an advantage (Hack et al. 1997; Bridge et al. 2000), smaller males are
occasionally injured or killed (personal observation)." (Prenter et al., 2003, p. 1054). This
fighting behavior is a "natural fact" about them as a species. But it is not good for the life of the
individual males.
Still the defender of an Aristotelian categorical view might respond by claiming that
while these behaviors are not necessarily good for the health of individual organisms of a species
they are still good for those organisms because these behaviors are what allow the individual
organism to reproduce which is good for the organism.
But even a cursory examination of this notion reveals that reproduction itself has nothing
to do with what is good for the individual organism. Reproduction is the passing along of one's
own genetic material to subsequent generations. It does not, however, bring about what is good
for the life of the individual organism itself. Reproduction itself does not further the good of the
227
individual organism.
231
If anything we might be able to say that it is good for the genes of the
organism in that they are what enjoy some form of continued survival through the act of
reproduction by the individual organism.
232
Aristotelian categoricals don't always coincide with individual organismic flourishing.
Those that attempt to wed natural selection with an Aristotelian categorical view will inevitably
end up cashing out "natural goodness" not in terms of individual flourishing, but rather in terms
of what is good for the species, or what is good for the genetic survival of the species, or even
what is in the interests of the species. Evolutionary biology suggests that much of what takes
place in natural selection is not aimed at bringing about the good of individual living beings and
their self-maintenance. Rather organismic flourishing takes a back seat to the genetic
reproduction of the species.
With this in mind I want to return to the "Aristotelian Natural Goodness" argument.
1) All NSNSLTs
233
are members of a species.
2) If all NSNSLTs are members of species then all NSNSLTs have structures that
have Aristotelian functional purposes.
3) If all NSNSLTs have structures that have Aristotelian functional purposes, then
all NSNSLTs have goals of their own.
4) If all NSNSLTs have goals of their own, then all NSNSLTs have morally
considerable interests.
5) Thus, all NSNSLTs have morally considerable interests.
Given the information presented earlier regarding harmful behaviors that are Aristotelian
categoricals and helpful behaviors that are not Aristotelian categoricals I want to argue that
231
It might, however, be claimed that reproduction can be "good for" individual organisms in
the sense that those organisms have preferences or desires to reproduce. In this way it can be
"good for" a mother to have a baby if that is what the mother desires. But, non-sentient being do
not have such desires and so reproduction cannot be "good for" them in that way.
232
In the next section I examine the question of whether genes have their own purposes.
233
As a reminder, the NSNSLT is an abbreviation for "naturally-selected, non-sentient living
things".
228
premise four of the "Aristotelian Natural Goodness" argument is false. If a male elephant seal
engages in the "goal of its own" of violent fighting behavior as a means of spreading his own
genes, that might be a form of Aristotelian "natural goodness", but it would not be an interest of
the male elephant seal. Having that kind of goal is not for its good and so engaging in that kind
of destructive behavior cannot be a morally considerable interest. Such behavior does not
provide a reason to care about the individual male elephant seal non-instrumentally. It does not
give it inherent worth.
At this point it might be suggested that naturally selected, non-sentient beings can still
have goals of their own because a certain part of them has a goal of its own. It might be argued
that while entire living organisms themselves are not the loci of inherent, Aristotelian purpose or
goals of their own that a part of them is the loci of such intrinsic purposes or goals of their own.
Hence, naturally selected living things can in some sense have a goal of their own because they
have a part that has a goal of its own. That part or portion of living things that some have
suggested might have a goal of its own are genes.
IX. Can Genes have Goals of Their Own?
Richard Dawkins, a prominent figure in evolutionary biology, holds the view that living
organisms are gene “survival machines” that ultimately exist "for"
234
the benefit of genetic
reproduction.
As Dawkins writes,
“Four thousand million years on, what was to be the fate of the ancient replicators
234
I put the word "for" in quotes here to point out that natural selection itself does not do
anything for something else because it has no foresight.
229
[genes]? They did not die out
235
, for they are past masters of the survival arts.
But do not look for them floating loose in the sea; they gave up that cavalier
freedom long ago. Now they swarm in huge colonies, safe inside gigantic
lumbering robots,
236
sealed off from the outside world, communicating with it by
tortuous indirect routes, manipulating it by remote control. They are in you and in
me; they created us, body and mind; and their preservation is the ultimate
rationale for our existence. They have come a long way, those replicators. Now
they go by the name of genes, and we are their survival machines.” (Dawkins,
1999, pp. 19-20).
Or, consider these comments from Lawrence Rifkin’s article “Is the Meaning of Your
Life to Make Babies?” in a Scientific American blog post.
"Genetic evolution is the meaning of biologic life, in that it is the why and how of
it, as well as the stock of future biological existence. The genes that survive -- and
in turn the organisms they make -- are the winners in the existence game. Can we
just dismiss this when considering the meaning of our own individual human
lives? Sure, evolution itself does not have a specific direction or teleology, and
genes themselves are not conscious, so there is not meaning in that sense. But
evolution cannot just be shrugged off as something apart from us, take it or leave
it. It is the biological explanation of who we are, how we got here, and the
diversity of life. Over billions of years, life left the oceans, stretched limbs to
cover the earth, raised wings to fly. Underlying it all are the replicating molecules
that continue to copy themselves even now." (Rifkin, 2013).
So, on this view all living things are gene “survival machines” with the extrinsic purpose
of replicating their genes. In his book The Selfish Gene Dawkins claims that genes are really the
final unit of selection, not organisms themselves. That is to say genes are the things that get
selected and passed on to the next generation by natural selection, not individual organisms.
Organisms and their structures were not brought about in order to serve the organism's own
235
This reference to “dying” is of course metaphorical. Ancient replicating genes are not alive
in and of themselves. So to speak of them “dying” doesn’t mean to speak of them as no longer
being alive. Rather it is to speak of them as no longer existing.
236
The asterisk here was given by Dawkins to indicate his own endnote which contains the
following commentary on his use of the term “robots” to describe living things: “If, like most of
the critics of my ‘lumbering robot’ passage, you are not religious, then face up to the following
question. What on earth do you think you are, if not a robot, albeit a very complicated one? I
have discussed all this in The Extended Phenotype, pp. 15-17.” (Dawkins, 1999, pp. 270-271).
230
good. Instead they were brought about in order to help make more DNA.
237
This is what I call the “genetic selectionist” view. Nature "selects" genes not individual
living things. On a genetic selectionist view whatever is “good for” the survival and selection of
genes is whether those genes are carried by organisms that are adept at reproducing themselves.
Paul Sheldon Davies explains the genetic selectionist view this way:
“We could, for example, postulate a drive or, if not a drive, an inherent tendency
within genes to manifest and perpetuate the species form. Something like this
appears to be the view of Richard Dawkins’s 1976 gene-centered theory,
according to which individual organisms are properly conceptualized as nothing
more than the genes’ (or the genotypes’) way of making more copies of
themselves. Genes serve as the theoretical center of command and control [my
emphasis] by orchestrating the development of the organism’s body and
behavioral repertoire in order to help ensure its own perpetuation. Individual
organisms come and go much like the seasons, but genes, thanks to the relatively
reliable copying processes through which they replicate, enjoy a relative form of
immortality” (Davies, 2009, p. 97)
The genetic selectionist might try to argue that even if all naturally-selected, individual
living things are not the direct bearers of goals of their own but rather are purposeful pawns in
the reproduction of genes, that their genes still have their own goals. Perhaps genes exist “in
order to” perform some inherent life function or have some essential “natural tendencies” about
them to perform some function or bring about biological goals. These would be purposes or
goals that are intrinsic to the genes. And if the genes have intrinsic purposes then the organisms
bearing those genes have their own intrinsic purposes.
The argument for the claim that naturally-selected, non-sentient beings have their own
purposes based on their possession of genes, what I call the "Genetic Purposes Argument", might
look like the following:
237
In The Selfish Gene Dawkins also writes, “A monkey is a machine that preserves genes up
trees, a fish is a machine that preserves genes in the water; there is even a small worm that
preserves genes in German beer mats.” (Dawkins, 1999, p. 21).
231
1) If the genes of all NSNSLTs have their own inherent purposes, then all
NSNSLTs have their own inherent purposes.
2) The genes of all NSNSLTs have their own inherent purposes.
3) Therefore, all NSNSLTs have their own inherent purposes.
But, according to Paul Sheldon Davies, the claim that genes have their own goals as the
‘command and control’ center of species propagation and development is quite contested, and for
some biologists, highly suspect and controversial. Davies argues that genes really do not have
their own goals or inherent tendencies. This is so for two reasons.
First, genes are not the only causal factor dictating organismal development and form. If
they were then perhaps we could say that genes have their own natural ends or purposes in
bringing about certain biological forms or species. But, modern science has uncovered other
causal factors besides genes that can significantly influence organismal developmental patterns.
Davies writes,
“The crucial general claim is that there appears to be no non-question-begging
grounds for conceptualizing genes as centers of command and control. Genes are
of undoubted importance in ontogenesis
238
they provide information causally
necessary for organismic development but the same is true of causal factors in
[the] other three resources. Development requires a host of epigenetic interactions
[1], behaviors [2], and culturally transmitted symbols [3]” (Davies, 2009, p.
97).
239
238
This is the developmental patterning and unfolding that takes place in an individual
organism from its earliest stage (i.e., the fertilized egg) all the way up to the full-grown adult
form.
239
For a further explanation of other factors besides genes that are responsible for organismic
development and form see Jablonka and Lamb, 2005. They write,
“The idea that DNA alone is responsible for all the hereditary differences between
individuals is now so firmly fixed in people’s minds that it is difficult to get rid of it…The
genetic [DNA] system is the basis of all biological organization, including the organization
of the supragenetic heredity systems we are going to consider, but these additional systems
allow variations in a different type of information to be transmitted. The variations occur at
higher levels of organization [my emphasis] at the cell [epigenetic], organism [behaviors],
or group level [culturally transmitted symbols]. They may be quite independent of variations
at the genetic level, in just the same way that variations in recorded performances may be
independent of variations in the score” (Jablonka and Lamb, 2005, p. 109-110).
232
Second, genes do not seem to have their own internal drives or goods that they are
striving to obtain. Genes merely dictate differences between species as they dictate organismal
form, but they have no inherent, natural tendencies within them to realize any particular,
biological development or form. As Davies observes,
“…there is no sense in which genes contain an internal drive that is genuinely
intrinsic to its operations. The behavior of genes, as is well-known, is affected by
an array of extrinsic factors cellular, organismic, and environmental. We can
change developmental outcomes by manipulating mechanisms internal to the
gene, without doubt, but we can also alter development by manipulating
mechanisms in the cell, elsewhere in the organisms, even in the
environment…genes would never exhibit anything we might reasonably describe
as a natural striving toward [my emphasis] self-perpetuation” (Davies, 2009, p.
98).
Davies goes one step further to claim that this Darwinian understanding of biological
functioning is simply not consistent with the claim that non-sentient beings have their own
intrinsic purposes. He writes,
“If contemporary theories of development are on track, then the forms of life that
gardeners and breeders cultivate are not at all as Kant and his contemporaries
thought of them. The coherence, stability, and persistence of living forms are, for
Kant, an expression of something intrinsic [my emphasis] to the individual
organism. For us, by contrast, no one and no thing ensures the coherence or
stability of living forms. No one is in charge; nothing comprises a center of
command; no sentry protects against change or destruction. To the contrary, the
human form and all the other forms we encounter are fleeting effects of recurring
ensembles of scattered causal factors, and only the most obstinate failure of
historical imagination could make us think otherwise…a radical implication of
evolutionary theory is that the perpetuation of living forms is not under the
control of a command center of any sort [my emphasis]. Not even a metaphorical
one” (Davies, 2009, p. 99-101).
240
240
In reference to Kant see section 65 of his book Critique of Judgment where he writes,
“An organi[s]ed being is then not a mere machine, for that has merely moving power, but it
possesses in itself formative power of a self-propagating kind which it communicates to its
materials though they have it not of themselves; it organi[s]es them, in fact, and this cannot
be explained by the mere mechanical faculty of motion…internal natural perfection, as it
belongs to those things which are only possible as natural purposes, and are therefore called
233
In other words naturally-selected, non-sentient living things do not really have intrinsic
purposes or goals of their own because they have no inherent tendencies to direct themselves
towards their functions and processes.
In any event even if it did turn out that genes had their own intrinsic purposes the living
organisms that contain those genes do not directly have goals of their own. And if naturally
selected living organisms are not the direct bearers of goals of their own, but rather their genes,
then we would have to say that it is the genes of living things that have morally considerable
interests not the individual organisms to which they belong.
The counter-argument to the "Genetic Purposes Argument" looks like the following:
1) If all NSNSLTs have their own inherent purposes, then the genes of all
NSNSLTs have their own inherent purposes.
2) But, the genes of all NSNSLTs do not have their own inherent purposes.
3) Therefore, all NSNSLTs do not have their own inherent purposes.
So if this argument is correct it looks like there is little to recommend for the view that
naturally selected, non-sentient beings have intrinsic purposes or goods of their own.
X. Is This the End for a Biocentrism Based on Natural Selection?
The process of natural selection has been argued to be capable of bringing about non-
sentient, teleofunctional beings that have a good of their own. Yet this same view of life has
actually made it untenable to think that non-sentient, teleofunctional beings and their structures,
really have teleofunctional purposes or that their teleofunctional structures exist for the purpose
of their self-maintenance and good. As such naturally-selected non-sentient living things do not
organised beings, is not analogous to any physical, i.e. natural, faculty known to us…” (Kant,
1790, sec. 65).
This ‘formative power’ for Kant represents some kind of direction or “aim” (non-psychological)
to life and biological forms. These “aims” are what Davies denies exists.
234
have goals of their own that could confer upon them direct moral standing.
If we examine what happens to a naturally-selected single cell after its cell membrane is
punctured we will find no instances of sentient harm done to it. It feels no pain and makes no
plans to escape it. It also has no desires so it cannot be harmed by having any preference interests
violated. It can, however, be systemically harmed by having its teleofunctional interests violated.
But why, it may be asked, should that kind of harm matter from a moral point of view
especially given that its teleofunctional structures do not have purposes, specifically functional
purposes for its own good? The naturally-selected, single cell has an interest in its membrane
continuing to perform the teleofunction of selectively filtering matter
241
. But if we puncture its
membrane all that happens to it is a cessation of its self-regulatory abilities. It ceases its
biochemical processes because it can no longer maintain its internal homeostasis. But no goals as
such have been thwarted. So on the face of it, it doesn't look like any moral wrong has been done
directly to these beings.
But the biocentrist wants to maintain that a moral wrong had been done.
The biocentrist faces a problem in trying to identify just what could be morally salient
about the teleofunctional interests of all naturally-selected, non-sentient beings that give them
direct moral standing. As I have argued above it cannot be because naturally-selected, non-
sentieint living things have goals or have structures that exist for their self-maintenance. Hence,
it cannot be because these beings have a good of their own.
XI. Why All Non-sentient Living Things Do Not Have a Good of Their Own
241
The same would be true of an instantly-produced cell, a designed cell or any cell that is
appropriately teleofunctional. Its etiology is irrelevant to what its teleofunctional interests are.
235
But what if it should turn out that all non-sentient teleofunctional beings regardless of
their etiology simply do not have a good of their own anyway?
There are actually a few good reasons to think that all non-sentient teleofunctional beings
do not have goods of their own because they do not have goals of their own.
First, these beings do not have mental states capable of holding some goal as a future
target. They do not aim for some future state of affairs at all. These beings are capable of
responding to changes in their environment in various ways, but that does not mean that they
have their own intrinsic purposiveness or goals. Furthermore, the problem with using teleological
language to describe the teleofunctional life processes of non-sentient beings is that these beings
themselves do not strive or aim to do anything insofar as being capable of making plans and
endeavoring to bring about some future state of affairs for themselves. Our claim that these
beings have their own goals might be less about the fact that they actually have their own goals
and more about our own propensity to project intrinsic purposiveness onto these beings in much
the same way that we are prone the anthropomorphize the undirected process of natural selection
(Fodor, 2007).
A second argument for why all non-sentient beings do not have goals of their own comes
from comparing some designed, non-sentient beings with other non-sentient living things. For
example, designed objects, such as heat-seeking missiles, can rightly be said to have the goal of
seeking out sources of heat, but they do not have their own goal of seeking out sources of heat.
One reason why we might think that non-sentient beings do not have their own goals is because
they are incapable of assigning goals to themselves in such a way that they are able to dictate
their own behavior. Intentional beings, as opposed to non-sentient beings, do have this ability.
Lilian O'Brien has some similar thoughts on this matter. She writes,
236
"Even if we grant that the heat-seeking missile has such states [that]...are
sufficient for mentality, I don't think that it's the kind of agent that can perform an
intentional action...although the missile behaviour is goal-oriented, it does not
itself assign a goal or goals to its behaviour..." (O'Brien, 2015, p. 137)
Oftentimes, we use certain metaphorical language to talk about the teleofunctional
processes of non-sentient beings. Sometimes we say that a tree, or some other plant, "aims" to
grow toward sunlight or that it "struggles" to find a source of water. Individual cells, it is
sometimes claimed, “try” to regulate their own internal pH levels. But these terms are
misleading. Trees, bacteria and other non-sentient forms of life do not themselves "aim" or "try"
to do anything in the sense of having intentional states or purposive behaviors directed toward
some future goal.
It makes some sense for us to think that conscious agents, beings that have preference
interests, have their own goals. These are beings that can make plans and form intentions to
embark on various activities that they themselves aim at. It also makes some sense to think that
sentient beings, beings that are capable of feeling pain and responding to it, have their own goals
too because they embark on purposive behaviors in response to external stimuli.
Most, if not all, sentient beings if physically harmed will experience a phenomenal state
of pain and will engage in some sort of purposive behavior, although not necessarily conscious,
to avoid it or get away from it. These beings at least seem to have intentions in avoiding pain as
evidenced by their reactions to pain. For instance, many sentient beings can sense and escape
sources of pain that are external to them. Invertebrates, many of which are sentient beings, but
not conscious agents, can exhibit behavioral responses to pain. As Dr. Jane Smith writes,
"Most, if not all, invertebrates have the capacity to detect and respond to noxious
or aversive stimuli. That is, like vertebrates, they are capable of ‘nociception.’
Examples of aversive stimuli include changes in temperature beyond the animal's
normal range, contact with noxious chemicals, mechanical interference, or electric
shock. Under certain conditions, all of these might be expected to cause pain in
humans. In general, invertebrates, like vertebrates, respond to such stimuli by
237
withdrawing or escaping so as to reduce the likelihood that they will be damaged
by the noxious conditions." (Smith, 1991, p. 26)
So it seems reasonable to think that both conscious agents and sentient beings have their
own goals and can embark on purposive behaviors.
242
And so it is reasonable to think that they
have interests that are morally considerable.
Some, however, might regard the phenomenon of heliotropism
243
in plants to be a
purposive behavior, a goal of their own. It might be argued that plants move their leaves in order
to get sunlight. On this view plants seem to have the goal of their own of acquiring sunlight.
Lowell Nissen, however, disagrees with the view that plants have goals. He thinks that in order
for something to have a goal it must be able to have mental representations of that goal. He
writes,
...since our language admits such sentences as "Hannibal's goal was to conquer
Rome," or even, elliptically, "Hannibal's goal was Rome," it is easy to slip into
the incorrect view that a goal is identical to a state of affairs or an event such as
conquering Rome, or even a physical entity, such as Rome. Nagel does this when
he talks about plants being goal-directed systems. A goal-directed system must be
a system whose behavior is directed to a goal, and that requires a goal. Since he is
operating under the nonmentalistic assumption, he must mean by "goal"
something not mind-dependent that is an objective state of affairs, a certain
arrangement of the nonmental world, such as photosynthesis actually occurring,
roots actually reaching moisture, or leaves actually facing the sun. This makes it
necessary to refer the mind-dependent interpretation as an "end in view" or
"deliberate goal." Nonetheless...an objective state of affairs in the world is not a
goal. The mere fact that plants regularly extend roots to moisture does not make
their behavior goal-directed any more than the fact that rocks regularly roll
downhill makes their behavior goal-directed." (Nissen, 1997, pp. 196-197).
242
Also Tyler Burge has commented on the existence of apparently goal-directed behavior of
spiders in the genus Portia. These spiders have the ability to make plans and change routes when
tracking down prey. Regarding these spiders Burge writes, "There is substantial evidence that
Portia can set and hold in memory a detailed route [to capturing prey]. Following the route often
involves extensive detour behavior. Portia commonly forages in a jungle tangle of branches and
vines. In such an environment, detours are often necessary." (Burge, 2010, p. 515)
243
Heliotropism is the ability of plants to turn their leaves toward and track sources of light.
238
On Nissen's view plants do not have the goal of moving their leaves toward sunlight
because the state of affairs "leaves actually reaching the sun" is not, properly speaking, a goal for
it. He thinks that in order for something to have a goal it must be able to hold that goal in
representation as some future target. Beings that have mental states as representations of some
future target are able to hold goals as future targets. But non-sentient beings, mindless beings, are
not capable of having mental states as representations of some future target.
Nonetheless, the behaviors of non-sentient living beings are conducive to their own self-
maintenance. These beings are able to control their own physiological processes in such a way
that their own biological integrity is maintained. In fact all living things have an amazing ability
to regulate their own internal processes in response to varying and harmful external conditions
by the employment of their teleofunctional structures. But having this ability should not be
confused with having goals of their own.
XII. Some Clarification on Morally Considerable Interests and Moral Standing
Given that it seems quite difficult to make the case that non-sentient, teleofunctional
beings have their own goals, it looks like the biocentrist project of showing that all living things
have inherent worth might be in danger.
The problem for the biocentrist is not in establishing that non-sentient living beings have
teleofunctional interests. The problem is that their teleofunctional interests do not denote
teleofunctional interests that are morally considerable to the extent that such interests give them
direct moral standing.
Should a biocentrist accept the view that all non-sentient living things do not have goals
or goods of their own she has a decision to make.
239
First, she could choose to take up the view that while conscious agents and sentient living
beings have interests that provide them direct moral standing (because they have their own goals)
non-sentient beings do not have interests that provide them direct moral standing because they do
not have goals of their own.
Or she might choose to hold the view that all non-sentient living beings do not have
interests because they do not have a good of their own. Hence, they cannot have inherent worth.
If she chooses this option she might argue the following:
1) If something has interests that give it direct moral standing then it has a goal of its
own.
2) But all NSLTs
244
do not have goals of their own.
3) Thus, all NSLTs do not have interests that give them direct moral standing.
4) If all NSLTs do not have interests that give them direct moral standing, then they do
not have inherent worth.
5) Thus, all NSLTs do not have inherent worth.
If an environmentalist were to accept this line of reasoning then it looks like she really
would have to give up on the biocentrist project of showing that all living things have inherent
worth.
But she could reject the claim that they have inherent worth by a different route. She
could simply deny that non-sentient living things have interests and that since they do not have
interests they cannot have inherent worth. She then might instead try to show that all living
things are still morally considerable even if they do not have interests.
Lars Samuelson points out this kind of move in the following passage. He writes,
"Many non-sentientist environmental ethicists think that there are reasons to care
for things that do not have interests, and towards which we cannot have such
duties. These non-sentientists hold that we can have moral reasons that are not
connected to duties towards someone. It is not an argument against such views to
simply state that we cannot have such reasons. Dale Jamieson (1998: 47) applies a
similar question-begging line of reasoning when he simply postulates that '[n]on-
244
Here NSLT stands for "non-sentient, living things".
240
sentient entities are not of primary value because they do not have a perspective
from which their lives go better or worse. Ultimately the value of nonsentient
entities rests on how they fit into the lives of sentient beings'. The claim of non-
sentientist environmental ethicists is precisely that non-sentient entities can have a
value independently of how they fit into the lives of sentient beings (cf. Crisp's
response to Jamieson (Crisp, 1998: 477))" (Samuelson, 2010, p. 529)
Here we have the prospect of a biocentrist arguing that there could still be reasons to
think that non-sentient beings have moral standing even if they should turn out not to have
interests and thus not to have inherent worth.
What I want to argue here is that the biocentrist considering this option should not allow
sentientism to dictate the terms of what having an interest means. I have argued in the previous
chapter that non-sentient beings can have interests even if they do not "have a perspective from
which their lives go better or worse". It is perfectly reasonable to talk about what is, or would be,
in a living thing's interests even if that thing has no conscious awareness of its own interests, has
no concept of what is 'better' or 'worse' for it or can have no experiences of pleasure or pain.
Even if it is true that there is some other way of arguing that we have a reason to care for
non-sentient beings besides the fact that they have interests, it would be a misstep to simply
capitulate to a sentientist criterion of interest possession if in fact non-sentient beings really do
have interests.
The main question that we should ask at this point is not whether non-sentient living
beings have teleofunctional interests (they do) or whether they have a goals of their own (they do
not) but whether they have teleofunctional interests that provide a reason to care about them non-
instrumentally.
It is quite reasonable to think that beings that have goals of their own, such as rational
agents and sentient beings, are entitled to some direct moral standing. These beings have
interests that make them directly morally considerable. But how can someone have a direct
241
moral obligation to non-sentient, teleofunctional beings especially given that those being do not
have goals of their own?
It does not appear as if they can.
A being that has direct moral standing is a being that other moral agents have obligations
directly to. For example, human beings have direct moral standing because we have certain
moral obligations to them not to harm or kill them.
245
Likewise, we have direct moral
obligations to other sentient beings not to cause them to feel unnecessary pain. So conscious
agents and sentient beings have direct moral standing. And furthermore they have this standing
because they have goals of their own regardless of their etiology.
But we should not conclude from this that non-sentient living things cannot have
teleofunctional interests that also provide a reason to care about them non-instrumentally. Their
teleofunctional interests could still be morally considerable in an indirect way even if those
interests do not confer direct moral standing to them.
The biocentrist willing to accept the conclusion that all non-sentient living things do not
have goals of their own might instead try to find some way of showing that their interests are still
morally considerable even if they do not confer direct moral standing to their bearers.
First it is possible for there to exist some things that we do not have direct moral
obligations to, but rather indirect moral obligations to. These things can have moral standing in
an indirect sort of way. They can have indirect moral standing.
For the purposes of this dissertation I will define indirect moral standing in the following
245
We could also say that we have direct moral obligations to human being because they have
direct moral standing. I do not here wish to defend the claim that having direct moral standing is
a necessary and sufficient conditions for us to have obligations to them only that such a view
could be argued for.
242
way.
X has indirect moral standing if and only if there is a reason not to harm X that is not
based on any intrinsic properties of X.
For example, I own a car that has the purpose of providing me with transportation. One of
its intrinsic properties is that it "has an engine". But this intrinsic property provides no reason not
to harm it. But the car could have an extrinsic property such as "loved by David" of "is David's
only form of transportation". These extrinsic properties do provide a reason not to harm it. Thus
the car has indirect moral standing by recourse to these extrinsic properties. I have a fairly strong
preference interest in having my car kept in working order. Should someone steal my car’s
alternator they would not be violating the car's interests. After all my car is something that has
no interests at all because it is neither sentient nor teleofunctional. On this point moral agents do
not have direct obligations to the car not to remove its alternator. However, the car's indirect
moral standing means that there is a reason not to harm it. This does not mean that it would
always be wrong to harm my car. It only means that there exists a reason not to harm it.
It is not the case that my car has no moral standing whatsoever. My car acquires a degree
of indirect moral standing through my preference interests in it. To be sure, my car doesn't have
interests. But that shouldn't mean that there cannot be a reason not to harm it that is not based on
any of its intrinsic properties. Other moral agents have a direct obligation to me to treat my car
with respect even if they do not have a direct obligation to the car to treat it with respect. My car
has this indirect moral standing because I, as a being with goals of my own, have a preference
interest in it being treated with care by others. My car has indirect moral standing because there
is a reason not to harm it but that reason does not rely on any intrinsic properties of it. My car has
indirect moral standing because there is a reason not to harm it based on my preference interest
243
in it which is not an intrinsic property of the car.
Non-sentient living things can have teleofunctional interests that can be indirectly
morally considerable. This is possible if their teleofunctional interests are the subject of a
rational agent's preference interests.
246
They would have indirect moral standing because there
exists a reason not to harm them that is not based on any of their intrinsic properties.
My car does not have interests
247
, but the oak tree that grows in my front lawn does. The
oak tree in my front lawn has the extrinsic purpose of providing shade to my house during hot
summer months. But that is not the only extrinsic purpose that it has. It also is beautiful and adds
some value to my property so it is extrinsically purposeful in those ways as well. These extrinsic
purposes are among the reasons why it should not be harmed by others. Damage to that tree's
teleofunctional structures would constitute a violation of its interests. But since there is a reason
not to violate its interests that is not based on any of its intrinsic properties, then the tree has
indirect moral standing.
With these considerations in mind I would like to add the following as a sufficient
condition for a non-sentient living being to have teleofunctional interests that give it indirect
moral standing.
If some rational agent has a non-trivial,
248
preference interest in the
246
There also might be other ways that non-sentient living things could get indirect moral
standing.
247
This is because my car is not a complex, teleofunctional being. It has no long-term self-
maintaining capacities. As I mentioned in chapter 3 beings that are not complex or have
teleofunctional complexity (such as fires) do not have interests.
248
I include the word "non-trivial" here to exclude cases of what we might call "weak"
preference interests, preference interests that are not strong enough to provide much, if any,
reason to not harm the thing that one has the weak preference interest in. For instance, someone
might have a very weak or trivial preference interest in their car bumper not being very, slightly
scratched yet also not think that any moral wrong would have been committed if someone should
very slightly scratch their bumper. This kind of trivial preference interest might be claimed by
244
teleofunctional interests of a non-sentient being x, then x has teleofunctional
interests that give it indirect moral standing.
My oak tree has teleofunctional interests that give it indirect moral standing because I
have a non-trivial preference interest in it. But the tree's teleofunctional interests in and of
themselves do not provide a reason for why it should not be harmed.
249
Nonetheless, the tree's
teleofunctional interests indirectly provide it with some moral standing.
The preference, sentient and teleofunctional interests of conscious agents and sentient
beings provide them with direct moral standing because these interests belong to beings that have
goals of their own. For instance, my preference interests in a tree's teleofunctional interests are
directly morally considerable because those interests are among my intrinsic purposes. Hence, I
have direct moral standing while the tree has indirect moral standing in relation to my
preference interests in it. The teleofunctional interests of non-sentient beings, however, do not
provide them direct moral standing. This is because these beings do not have goals of their own.
The specific problem for the biocentrist hoping to argue for the claim that all living
things have inherent worth is that it needs to be shown that the teleofunctional interests of all
non-sentient living things provide a reason for why all valuers should value or care about them
in and of themselves, not specifically whether they have a good of their own or whether their
some to provide some reason not to scratch the car's bumper (since the person preferred that it
not be slightly scratched), but it might also be argued that such a trivial preference interest
actually does not provide a reason not to scratch the bumper at all (since the person also did not
regard that preference interest as being one that it would be wrong for others to violate). It might
be argued that such a trivial preference does not really provide a reason not to very slightly
scratch the car bumper because it would never be morally wrong to violate that particular
preference interest. On the other hand, non-trivial preference interests are ones in which it would
be prima facie morally wrong to violate. Whereas prima facie it is not wrong to violate a trivial
preference interest.
249
Here I am assuming that the tree that I am talking about is a naturally-selected tree. But it
could just as well be an instantly-produced tree or a tree produced by some designer. The
etiology of the tree would not matter to whether the tree could have indirect moral standing.
245
interests are directly morally considerable. Recall that in chapter one I defined morally
considerable interests as interests that provide a reason for why all valuers should care about the
possessor of those interests in and of itself.
250
The biocentrist who believes that all living things have inherent worth, as defined in this
dissertation, thinks that all living thing have interests that are morally considerable and that we
should value all living things in and of themselves because of the interests that they have. The
fact that we should value them in such a way has implications for how we end up treating them.
As Lars Samuelson writes,
"...reasons are what EE should primarily be concerned with...EE is first and
foremost a practical discipline. It is largely motivated by the insight that action is
urgent if we want to reverse the current, alarming situation of the natural world.
The point of establishing that nature has intrinsic value is that such values would
lay claims on us that they would supply us with reasons for action with respect
to their bearers. If it were not for this connection to reasons, environmental
ethicists and environmentalists would not have taken interest in the intrinsic value
of nature in the first place. It is the practical questions about what we have reason
to do that motivate the further questions that we may want to ask about value and
moral standing. If these latter notions were not closely connected to reasons, they
would simply not be interesting from an ethical point of view. What good would
the value of nature be if it did not lay claim on us?" (Samuelsson, 2010, p.
530).
251
Thus, the biocentrist who does not want to give up on the project of showing that all
living things have inherent worth needs to show that all non-sentient beings can still have
250
For a discussion of the definition of morally considerable interests see section VIII of
chapter one.
251
Samuelsson should not be read as endorsing biocentric individualism here. Rather he is
emphasizing the need to appeal to the existence of reasons for taking up a nature-preserving
attitude. His use of the term "nature" does not refer precisely to individual living organisms but
rather to "non-human, non-sentient natural entities". He writes,
"...the notion of intrinsic value has occupied a prominent position within the field [of EE], and
one of its most frequently debated questions has been that of whether some non-human, non-
sentient natural entities have intrinsic value. (From now on I will simply write ‘nature’ to refer to
any such natural entity that one may think has intrinsic value.)" (Samuelsson, 2010, p. 518)
246
interests that provide a reason for valuers to care about them in and of themselves.
However, for the purposes of this dissertation I want to focus on the question of whether
non-sentient living things can be guaranteed to have indirect moral standing. The question of
whether the teleofunctional interests of non-sentient living things provide reasons for why they
should be cared about or valued non-instrumentally, unfortunately is not a question that space
here permits.
The question of whether there exists reasons for why a non-sentient living thing should
not be harmed that are not based on any of its intrinsic properties is a separate question from
whether there exists reasons for why a non-sentient living thing should be cared about non-
instrumentally. For example, if I take a preference interest in a plant growing in my backyard
then there would exist a reason not to harm it that is not based on any intrinsic properties of the
plant. But the fact that I happen to have a preference interest in the plant does not necessarily
mean that there is a reason for others to care about it non-instrumentally. Those other valuer
have a reason not to harm it, but they might not necessarily have a reason to care about it per se.
At this stage it is important for the biocentrist to point to reasons for how the
teleofunctional interests of non-sentient living things could give them indirect moral standing.
Since all non-sentient living things do not have interests that provide them direct moral standing,
the biocentrist should still inquire into whether the teleofunctional interests of naturally-selected,
non-sentient living things could guarantee that those beings have indirect moral standing.
XIII. Can All Naturally-Selected Non-Sentient Living Things be guaranteed to Have
Indirect Moral Standing?
At this point we should inquire as to whether the teleofunctional interests of all naturally-
247
selected non-sentient beings gives them indirect moral standing.
Natural selection is incapable of selecting a teleofunctional structure for a functional task.
Hence, naturally selected, non-sentient beings do not have teleofunctional purposes. Hence, they
do not have goals. Since I have shown that naturally selected, non-sentient beings do not have
goals, a biocentrist could still argue that natural selection is capable of generating teleofunctional
interests that give their bearer's indirect moral standing.
For instance, consider the following world in which there exists only naturally-selected
forms of life including some rational, moral agents. Billy, a five-year-old in that world, uproots a
mulberry bush in his grandmother's back yard. Upon uprooting the plant Billy causes it to sustain
fatal, systemic harm. The plant dies. The plant itself, however, is not the subject of direct moral
standing. It sustains no sentient or psychological harm and has no goals of its own. Billy's
grandmother happens to witness the plant's uprooting. Observing this event causes her to
experience sadness and anger. She particularly liked the plant because of its beautiful leaves. She
projected an extrinsic purpose onto the plant, that purpose being the purpose of appearing
beautiful to her and her guests. Billy's grandmother thus experiences some psychological harm
because this particular plant was one that she took a preference interest in. Billy's grandmother
had an interest in maintaining the plant's teleofunctional interests. Billy, by violating the plant's
teleofunctional interests, directly violated his grandmother's preference interests in the plant.
Billy's act of uprooting the plant is thus wrong because his violation of the plant's teleofunctional
interests resulted in the violation of another person's preference interests.
So what should we say about the moral standing of the plant? In this case it seems
reasonable to think that the plant has indirect moral standing. The plant has teleofunctional
interests. But those interests considered in isolation do not make the plant itself morally
248
considerable or worthy of some respect in its own right. Rather its teleofunctional interests are
the subject of another person's fairly strong, preference interests. It thus has an extrinsic purpose
related to its teleofunctional interests. If this particular plant could not regulate itself because of
some damage done to one of its teleofunctional structures it would not be as beautiful or as
useful to Billy’s grandmother.
The plant, in this case, has indirect moral standing which means there exists a reason for
why Billy, and other agents, should not harm it, a reason that is not based on any intrinsic
properties of the plant. It has an extrinsic purpose associated with some agent, Billy’s
grandmother, who has her own intrinsic purposes.
But would naturally-selected non-sentient teleofunctional beings be guaranteed to have
such indirect moral standing?
Let us imagine a world without any creator in which there only existed naturally selected,
non-sentient, teleofunctional beings. Should we think that the teleofunctional interests of all of
these non-sentient beings are morally considerable? Would their teleofunctional interests
represent some kind of moral value in that world?
I do not think so. The naturally-selected, teleofunctional interests of non-sentient beings
in this world do not have moral value in themselves. These non-sentient beings do not
themselves have goals, either intrinsic or extrinsic. These non-sentient beings engage in the
processes of replicating their DNA, reproducing themselves, converting ADP into ATP,
harnessing sunlight, making carbohydrates, and competing in the Darwinian “struggle for
existence” etc. But these biological processes are completely amoral.
So in this type of world the naturally-selected, non-sentient living things in it cannot be
guaranteed to have indirect moral standing.
249
But let us imagine a slightly differently world, one in which there exists many naturally-
selected, non-sentient living things and just one rational agent, Ken.
Ken himself does not have a preference interest in any of the teleofunctional interests in
the non-sentient beings that he encounters in that world. One day he uproots a small tree. Since
Ken has no preference interests in the plants and there are no other rational beings around that
could take an interest in the tree's teleofunctional interests, then there is not reason for why the
tree should not be harmed. As such the tree's teleofunctional interests do not give it indirect
moral standing.
Should Ken cause systemic harm to the non-sentient beings in this kind of world such an
act does not appear to be morally wrong. Even Harley Cahan acknowledges that this kind of
evaluation might be reasonable. He writes. "Should we find moral significance in an organism's
goals? Perhaps not. We may coherently admit that plants have goals
252
, yet deny that we have
duties to them." (Cahen, 1988, p. 208).
Naturally selected plants have teleofunctional interests in replicating their DNA,
converting ADP into ATP and in harnessing sunlight to make sugar. But those teleofunctional
interests are not purposeful in themselves and do not themselves provide a reason for why any
moral agent should value them in and of themselves. Thus, a natural selection etiology cannot
guarantee that all living things produced by that etiology will have indirect moral standing.
Still it could be argued that even if all naturally selected living things do not have goals
of their own there is a high probability that they would all acquire extrinsic purposefulness by
being appreciated or valued by human beings. It might be argued that human beings routinely
252
Here Cahen is writing about the "goals" of a tree's "growth, survival and reproduction".
Although, as I have argued previously naturally selected trees do not have goals. Unlike Cahen, I
do not believe that we can "coherently admit that plants have goals."
250
project purposefulness onto the non-sentient beings produced by natural selection and so human
beings routinely have preference interests in all naturally-selected, non-sentient living things. In
other words it might be claimed that we, as observers of the natural world, always “see”
purposefulness, goal-directedness and value in the world and that such human sentiments always
makes it the case that the non-sentient living things that exist will acquire indirect moral standing
from our dispositions to appreciate their teleofunctional activities. Since the teleofunctional
interests of all non-sentient living things are valued by our fellow human beings, then there is a
reason not to harm them that is not based on any of their intrinsic properties.
Note that this claim is consistent with human beings projecting purposefulness onto all
non-sentient living things without regard for their etiology. In other words, humans could project
purposefulness onto an instantly-produced tree just as much as they could project purposefulness
onto a naturally-selected tree.
In any event even if human beings were to acquire some basic, natural affinity for
projecting value onto non-sentient beings that is a far cry from the claim that we would value the
teleofunctional interests of all naturally selected, non-sentient beings.
In fact there are some reasons to think that humans would not find purposes or care about
all non-sentient living things. There are a great many non-sentient forms of life that Homo
sapiens simply hasn't even encountered yet much less valued. There are still numerous, unnamed
species of plants on the planet that are yet to be discovered by us.
253
For example, ten to twenty
253
On a related note, Robert May and Ray Beverton have commented on biologist's efforts to
discover and describe new species. Biologists have routinely opted for discovering and
describing larger, more prominent forms of life than smaller, more obscure forms. Bigger things
just seem to be more important to us than smaller or microscopic things. They write,
"As one moves down the size-spectrum of organisms, from the romantic large mammals and
birds, through nondescript small arthropods [sic], on down to protozoan, bacterial and viral
species, not only does concern for diversity and conservation fall away, but it even changes sign.
251
percent of known species of flowering plant are "missing" (Joppa et al., 2011a; Joppa, et al.,
2011b).
Still the biocentrist could make a slightly different argument. They might say, "All that
biocentrism needs is a case where one rational agent cares about the teleofunctional interests of
all living beings in order for them to all have indirect moral standing. As long as one person has
a preference interest in the teleofunctional interests of all non-sentient teleofunctional beings,
then all valuers should care about those beings. And I care about the interests of all living things.
So all living things have indirect moral standing." I will call this argument the "biocentric
preferred interests" argument.
This argument might look like the following:
1) For all x, if x is a NSNSLT, then if the teleofunctional interests of all x are the
subject of at least one human being's preference interest, then all x have
indirect moral standing.
2) The teleofunctional interests of all x are the subject of at least one human
being's preference interests.
3) Thus, all x have indirect moral standing.
It might, at first glance, appear that the "biocentric preferred interests" argument could
make the biocentrist happy. All that is needed is for one human being to care about, or have a
preference interest in, the teleofunctional interests of all non-sentient living beings.
There are, however, some problems for the "biocentric preferred interests" argument.
First, when the biocentrist says that she "cares about all living things" she means that she
cares about the whole collection of living things, not all individual organisms. For example, a
concert pianist can declare love to her adoring audience by saying "I love you all." This does not
mean that she loves each individual person there. What she means is that she loves the group or
In the Smithsonian Institution in Washington, a touching label attached to Martha, the last
passenger pigeon, laments her death in 1914, but no-one mourned the passing of the last
smallpox virus." (May and Beverton, 1990, p. 301).
252
the audience itself. The claim that a human being can care about all individual non-sentient
living things is false. Human beings are simply not capable of taking up that kind of attitude
toward all individual non-sentient living things.
It seems a bit unrealistic to expect that human beings actually would find some value or
have some extrinsic purpose for the teleofunctional interests of all non-sentient living things.
What goes on inside of a lone plant in a remote area of the world is actually of very little interest
to most if not all human beings. As Holmes Rolston comments, "I too claim that no species
among the five or ten million on Earth is worthless; each has a good of its kind; each is a good
kind. But it is going to be quite a stretch to show that each and every one of them is some good to
us." (my emphasis, Rolston, 2009, p. 101).
This is what I call the "the limited capacity of human caring" problem.
Second, many biocentrists think that all living things should not be harmed regardless of
what our
254
preference interests turn out to be towards them. They believe that not only is it the
case that prima facie all living things should not be harmed, but that the justification for why
they should not be harmed shouldn't be based on the preferences of human beings at all. In other
words, these biocentrists might agree that even if some person has a preference interest in all
individual non-sentient teleofunctional beings (a doubtful proposition for human beings) that that
would provide some reason for why those beings should not be harmed. But they would caution
that such a reason is not necessary to guarantee the moral standing of all living things.
Biocentrists think that all living things have value independently of their effects on human
beings.
For instance, Holmes Rolston holds the view that living organisms have value
254
By "our" I mean human beings.
253
independently of whether human beings subjectively confer value onto them. He writes,
"The bee's defending its own life for what it is in itself is just as much fact of the
matter as is its using its stinger or making honey to do so...these are observations
of value in nature [my emphasis] with just as much certainty as they are biological
facts. We are misled to think that all the value of the tree, instrumental or
intrinsic, must be subjectively conferred, like the greenness, a secondary quality,
or even a tertiary one. A simpler, less anthropically based, more biocentric theory
holds that some values, instrumental and intrinsic, are objectively there,
discovered not generated by the valuer." (Rolston, 2003, p. 146).
255
Biocentrists such as Rolston would probably say, "Prima facie, all living things should
not be harmed even if no one else cares about any of them at all. We have a prima facie duty not
to harm all living things despite whether any being takes up a preference interest in them or not.
Our prima facie duties to not harm living things shouldn't be dependent in that way on the
evaluative attitudes of others."
Consequently, biocentrists would say that if the antecedent condition of premise one of
the "biocentric preferred interests" argument does not hold all living things still shouldn't be
harmed anyway. Reliance on such a premise, they think, undermines the overall biocentrist
project of showing that all living things have value independently of whether any valuers happen
to value them.
255
On a related matter, Paul Taylor claims that since human beings' moral intuitions about what
has value and what does not are socially conditioned and subjective, that such intuitions cannot
be reliable in getting at an objective environmental ethic. He writes,
"Our moral intuitions regarding how the living things of the natural world should be treated are
psychologically dependent on certain basic attitudes toward nature that we were imbued with in
childhood. What attitudes were given to us early in life reflect the particular outlook on animals
and plants accepted by our social group....Since our intuitive judgments in matters of ethics are
this way strongly affected by our early moral conditioning and since different societies will
imbue children with different attitudes and feelings about the treatment of animals and plants, we
cannot use either our own or anyone else's moral intuitions as grounds for accepting or rejecting
a theory of environmental ethics...We must strive for objectivity, and this requires a certain
detachment from our immediate intuitions in the area so that we consider without prejudice the
merits of the case for a life-centered ethic." (Taylor, 1986, p. 23-24).
254
This is what I call the "independence from human valuers" problem.
Thus, in a world in which natural selection is the sole cause for the existence of all non-
sentient living things it is not true that all of those beings are guaranteed to have indirect moral
standing.
But non-sentient beings produced by the other etiologies considered thus far will also not
be guaranteed to have indirect moral standing either. These considerations would no doubt also
apply to non-sentient living things produced by the other etiologies we have considered thus far.
Some of these beings might be extrinsically valued by other rational agents while others might
not. There is no guarantee that they would all be extrinsically valued or appreciated by other
rational agents.
The biocentrist concerned about these problems might then wish for an alternative to the
"biocentric preferred interests" argument, one that steers clear of these complications.
But can this wish really be fulfilled?
As I have argued in this chapter, there is very little to recommend for the view that non-
sentient teleofunctional beings have direct moral standing, a moral standing that exists
independently of all valuers whatsoever. The only remaining option for non-sentient beings to
acquire moral standing is if they acquire indirect moral standing. But as I have argued here the
biocentrist's hope of guaranteeing indirect moral standing for all naturally-selected, non-sentient
living things independently of the valuing attitudes human valuers cannot hope to succeed.
XIV. Conclusion
In this chapter I have attempted to demonstrate that a systems-based approach is not
successful in showing how the teleofunctional interests of non-sentient beings could make them
255
have direct moral standing or have a goal of their own. I have also argued that all of the
etiological options considered in this chapter are unsuccessful in showing how the
teleofunctional interests of all non-sentient living beings could make it the case that they have a
good or a goal of their own. Neither the systems-based approach, nor the etiological approaches
considered thus far appear to be very good candidates for showing that non-sentient living things
can have such goals.
Biocentrists argue that all living things have interests that are morally considerable,
interests that provide a reason for why the possessors of those interests should be valued in and
of themselves. But if the biocentrist wants to argue that all living things have interests that give
them direct moral standing, then as I have argued here, there seems to be little to recommend
that view. If, on the other, hand morally considerable interests could include teleofunctional
interests that give their possessors indirect moral standing, then all non-sentient living beings
could have that kind of moral standing. That is if the biocentrist insists that interests that provide
direct moral standing are the only kinds of interests that can provide moral standing, then non-
sentient living beings cannot have moral standing. If, on the other hand, she is willing to
countenance the view that interests that provide direct moral standing are not the only kinds of
interests that can provide moral standing, then non-sentient teleofunctional beings could get
indirect moral standing.
Daniel Dennett has described Darwinism as a "universal acid" which "eats through just
about every traditional concept" (Dennett, 1995, p.63), including prescriptive norms in
ethics. This acid, unfortunately, has now attacked the biocentrist project of showing that all
living things have inherent worth. Darwin's theory has indeed reduced (and some may claim
rightly) the status of human beings as the proverbial “pinnacle of creation”. Humans are now
256
merely one among many species that inhabit the planet Earth.
256
Unfortunately, it has also
made the biocentrist's project of showing that all living things have inherent worth more, rather
than less, difficult. Naturally selected, non-sentient living things have no goals of their own. And
if they happen to acquire some indirect moral standing it will depend entirely on other valuers
contingently finding some value in them. Given the tenuous nature of those values perhaps the
biocentrist should look elsewhere.
One problem that does need to be addressed, but that is beyond the scope of this
dissertation, is whether teleofunctional interests that give non-sentient living things indirect
moral standing should be regarded as interests that give them inherent worth. The problem is
roughly this: If teleofunctional interests are the only kinds of interests that non-sentient
teleofunctional beings can have, and those interests can only give those beings indirect moral
standing and not moral standing in their own right, then it looks like non-sentient living beings
cannot, properly speaking, have inherent worth. Non-sentient teleofunctional beings are not
inherently worthy of moral standing in their own right because their teleofunctional interests do
not represent a "good of their own". Non-sentient living things can only be worthy of moral
standing by recourse to reasons for why they should not be harmed that is not based on any of
their intrinsic properties. In this way non-sentient teleofunctional beings, it might by urged,
cannot have worth that is inherent or intrinsic to them. If this understanding of inherent worth is
what the biocentrist is hoping for, then as I have argued here, that project cannot succeed. If so
256
This is the claim that human beings are not inherently superior to other species but is instead
a late-forming twig on the evolutionary “tree of life”. As Christopher Uhl writes, "In truth, we
are not superior, nor inferior, to the rest of the family of life. The process of evolution has
produced Earth's tree of life. This tree has myriad branches, each its own evolutionary line. The
buds along each of these branches are species. Our species, Homo sapiens, represents on bud on
one branch - no better, no worse than the millions of other buds strung along the tree's other
branches." (Uhl, 2013, p. 79).
257
then such a biocentrist might be urged to give up on the claim that all living things have
specifically inherent worth. It might be recommended that non-sentient teleofunctional beings
could have some other kind of worth, just not inherent worth.
If, on the other hand, the biocentrist is willing to allow that non-sentient living things can
have inherent worth because they possess, or can possess, interests that provide a reason not to
harm them, then she will not have to give up on the claim that all living things have inherent
worth.
Because of this difficulty I will then set aside the discussion of whether non-sentient
living things can have inherent worth and instead focus on the question of whether non-sentient
living things can have indirect moral standing.
The only other etiological possibility that we have not considered is a design etiology.
As I mentioned in chapter three, the systems-based account of interests suggests that
there could exist artificial forms of life that would have interests. This approach leaves open the
prospect that intelligently-designed teleofunctional systems, whether living or non-living, can be
candidates for interest possession. Mossio et al. recognize this possibility when they write, “we
leave open the possibility that, at least in principle, functional attributions may concern ‘non-
living’ systems. In practice, however, all known cases of closed and differentiated self-
maintaining systems are living systems” (Mossio et al., 2009, p. 828). If so then the
environmentalist that accepts this aspect of the systems-based account cannot exclude items with
a design etiology from having teleofunctional interests.
In the next chapter I will argue that if the teleofunctional interests of non-sentient living
beings were brought about by a designer then those beings would be guaranteed to have indirect
moral standing. All persons in that world would have a reason not to harm those beings
258
independently of whether any of those persons happens to take up a preference interest in them.
259
CHAPTER FIVE
A Design Etiology and Indirect Morally Considerable, Teleofunctional Interests
In the preceding chapters I have attempted to demonstrate that there is a significant
difference between having teleofunctional interests and having morally considerable
teleofunctional interests. Morally considerable teleofunctional interests are ones that provide a
reason to care about the possessor of those interests in and of itself or non-instrumentally.
I have also attempted to show that a non-etiological, systems-based approach is not
capable of identifying teleofunctional interests that could make non-sentient beings have direct
moral standing. This approach is very adept at identifying the presence of teleofunctional
interests by recourse to whether a system has a teleofunctional type of organization. Should there
exist some organism that contains a variety of structures and substructures that all work in
conjunction with one another to contribute to its self-maintenance, then the future well-being of
that thing would depend on the continued successful operation of its constituent, teleofunctional
parts. That organism, as a teleofunctional system, would have teleofunctional interests in its parts
continuing to perform the functions that they do.
But as I mentioned in the previous chapter, the teleofunctional structures of instant
organisms do not have functions. Instant Arto's membrane, for example, does not have the
function of filtering matter. And so no one can cause its membrane to malfunction. Its membrane
is not for filtering matter.
Instant organisms are a problem for a non-etiological, systems-based views of interests
because those accounts don't make any kind of moral distinction between the interests of "instant
organisms" and other organisms produced in a different way.
Even though Instant Arto has a teleofunctional interest in its membrane filtering matter,
260
should its membrane cease to function as a selective barrier (due to, for example, it being
punctured by someone) we would be unable to say that that structure malfunctions or functions
improperly as a result of its being punctured. Since Instant Arto’s membrane does not have
filtering matter as a function it also cannot malfunction or improperly filter matter. In this case
Instant Arto has a teleofunctional interest in its membrane functioning as a selective barrier. But
there is nothing about that interest that would warrant the conclusion that is should be valued in
and of itself.
In fact, as I have argued, there is no good reason to think that non-sentient living things
can have a good of their own even though they can have interests.
This leaves indirect moral standing
257
as the only available kind of moral standing that
non-sentient living things can have.
We might admire the precision and efficiency with which Instant Arto's teleofunctional
structures perform their functions and so it could have interests that give it indirect moral
standing on that basis. We could also value it as a subject of future biomedical research or we
might value it for some of its aesthetic properties (perhaps its membrane structure is particularly,
intricate or beautiful).
But it would make very little sense for the biocentrist to claim that their teleofunctional
interests would be universally preferred such that all teleofunctional, non-sentient beings would
have indirect moral standing.
In the first section will explain what a design etiology is and I provide a definition of
what the term "design" means.
257
In section XII of chapter four I defined indirect moral standing in the following way: X has
indirect moral standing if and only if there is a reason not to harm X that is not based on any
intrinsic properties of X.
261
In the second section I will raise the possibility that a design etiology could guarantee
that non-sentient living things produced by it would have indirect moral standing. In it I make
the argument that if all non-sentient living thing were designed then they would have indirect
moral standing because they were brought about by an intrinsically good activity, creativity.
Since creativity is an intrinsically good activity then there would be a reason why non-sentient
living things that were brought about by that good activity should not harmed.
In the third section I provide a second argument for why designed, non-sentient living
things have indirect moral standing. Here I will argue that designed, non-sentient living things
are guaranteed to have indirect moral standing because they have teleofunctional structures that
have teleofunctional purposes. The existence of these functional purposes guarantees that
designed, non-sentient living things have indirect moral standing because these purposes were
intended by a designer.
In the fourth section I introduce a "theistic design etiology" as possible way in which all
non-sentient living things could have been brought about. This etiology, as the name implies, is
one in which God brought about all non-sentient living things.
In the fifth section I provide some justification for the project of arguing that God's
existence and action in the world does provide reasons not to harm the non-sentient living things
that he designed. Various environmentalists have argued that some religious beliefs have been
antithetical to an environmental ethic. They have made arguments which suggest that theism in
environmental ethics is something that should either be avoided or is simply not relevant to
environmental ethics.
In the sixth section I embark on a discussion of what it would take for a designer to
design the non-sentient living things that exist in the actual world. Here I argue that such a
262
designer would have to able to generate genetic information in order to bring about those beings.
I also argue that given the highly complex nature of those living things and the amount of
biological information that they contain that their designer would have, relative to beings like us,
great creativity. Here I will attempt to show that such a designer would have, relative to beings
like us, a level creativity that far exceeds our own. To us such creativity would be rather
astonishing.
In the seventh section I will address the question of whether it would be proper to claim
that natural selection is creative or has great creativity. Here I argue that since natural selection is
a blind and without intention it cannot, properly speaking, be regarded as creative. It might
create living things, but it cannot be creative nor exercise creativity. Rational agents, on the
other hand, can exercise creativity.
In section eight I argue that if the theistic design etiology were true then the non-sentient
living things that were brought about by that etiology would be guaranteed to have indirect moral
standing for still further reasons. Here I argue that if all non-sentient living things were designed
by God for the purpose of inspiring beings like us with a sense of awe and wonder then those
non-sentient living things would have indirect moral standing of our obligation to be thankful to
God for designing such beings. Having the obligation to be thankful to God provides a reason
why we should not harm the non-sentient living things that were designed by God. Non-designed
non-sentient living things, on the other hand, are not ones that we have an obligation to be
thankful to God, or any other being, for bringing about.
In section nine I argue that if the theistic design etiology were true then the non-sentient
living things that were brought about by that etiology are guaranteed to have indirect moral
standing for still even further reasons, reasons not available for why a non-designed, non-sentient
263
living being should not be harmed. I argue that if the theistic design etiology were true, then
there would be an entire collection of preference interests that would provide a reason for the
non-sentient living things produced by that etiology should not be harmed. This collection of
preference interests is what I call a "project". Projects involve numerous preference interests and
desires. Non-sentient living things that are not designed are not a designer's project and so a
designer's preference interests cannot be among the reasons available for why non-designed non-
sentient living things should not be harmed. Non-designed, non-sentient living things cannot
acquire indirect moral standing for these reasons.
In the tenth, and final, section I provide a recap of this chapter and conclude with some
final remarks about how a design etiological view of the teleofunctional interests of all living
things is the best route that a biocentrist can take in support of their arguments for the claim that
all living things have moral standing.
I. What Does it Mean to Have a Design Etiology?
At this point the biocentrist might simply accept the verdict that all non-sentient
teleofunctional beings cannot by guaranteed to have indirect moral standing and try to find some
other way of arguing on behalf of their protection.
There is, however, one remaining etiological option for how non-sentient living things
could have come about. That etiological option is a design etiology.
But what does the term "design" mean?
Whenever I use the term ‘design’ I will not use it in the same way that some evolutionary
biologists do when they refer to the process of natural selection as being one of ‘design’.
Scientists often use the term ‘design’ when talking about how the process of natural
264
selection can 'design' living organisms and their structures. Natural selection, they claim,
‘designs’ living things. For instance, anthropologist Edward Hagen describes the process of
natural selection as of ‘designing’ the human immune and sensory systems. He writes,
"Natural selection designed [my emphasis] the immune system to detect and
eliminate foreign proteins, but, in operation, the immune system must learn to
detect and eliminate measles and strep. Similarly, natural selection designed our
sensory systems to identify carbohydrate sources using reliable cues like color
and taste, but these systems, in operation, must learn to identify particular
carbohydrate sources, like apples and oranges." (Hagen, 2005, pp. 160-161)
Francisco Ayala, another evolutionary biologist, claims that natural selection can produce
‘design but without a designer’ (Ayala, 2007) while Daniel Dennett, in speaking about Charles
Darwin’s own understanding of ‘design’, writes,
“Hume’s Cleanthes...lumps the adapted marvels of the living world with the
regularities of the heavens it’s all like a wonderful clockwork to him. But
Darwin suggests a division: Give me Order, he says and time, and I will give you
Design. Let me start with regularity the mere purposeless, mindless, pointless
regularity of physics and I will show you a process that eventually will yield
products that exhibit not just regularity but purposive design.” (Dennett, 1995, p.
65).
On my use of the term ‘design’, however, there is no actual ‘design’ unless there is an
actual designer or conscious agent that had some purposeful intention to bring about some object
or state of affairs. For this reason I will treat the term ‘design’ to be equivalent to ‘design by an
agent’.
258
If this is so then anything that is designed is one that is designed by an agent.
The following, then, is a necessary and sufficient condition for a thing to be designed.
X is designed if and only if x is designed by an agent.
258
I will use the term ‘design’ to refer to 'design by an agent' all the while recognizing that this
is not the only sense in which that term has been used by others, particularly by evolutionary
biologists. Although, as Plantinga argues in Warrant and Proper Function, these evolutionary
biologists, if they are naturalists, should abandon the very idea of proper function or functional
purpose. For a naturalist to adopt the intentionalist stance is to embrace an illusion that "...as
Freud and Marx tell us, has its uses; but helping to achieve straightforward understanding is not
among them" (Plantinga, 1993, p. 214)
265
According to my use of the term 'design' natural selection cannot ‘design’ anything
because it is not an agent. It, unlike agents, cannot make conscious plans or intend for anything
to come about. It does not involve the conscious planning of a mind. Should a non-sentient,
teleofunctional being be produced by natural selection then that being would not be a designed
being. Natural selection, like all blind, unguided processes has no mind and makes no purposeful
plans to produce anything.
In his critique of Philip Kitcher’s attempt to “unify” the concepts of purposeless 'design'
with purposeful design, Paul Davies amply describes this point in the following way. He writes,
“Kitcher asserts that ‘one of Darwin’s important discoveries is that we can think
of design without a designer’ (1993, 380). But this is ambiguous. It may assert
merely that (a) Darwin showed us how to explain the apparent marks of design
without postulating a designer. Alternatively, it may assert that (b) Darwin
showed us that there really is design in the natural world despite the absence of a
designer. Now I take it that (a) is true. But as we have seen, the truth of (a) cannot
support Kitcher’s proposed unification, since the concept ‘design’ applies to the
production of artifacts while the quite different concept ‘bears-apparent-marks-of-
design’ applies to the evolution via selection of natural objects. I also take it that
(b) is false. For no one, not even Darwin, can show that there is design in the
absence of a designer, since no one can refute the rather plausible conceptual
claim that design requires a designer...it is just not true that Darwin thought there
could be design with no designers. On the contrary. Darwin’s view is that we can
explain away that apparent marks of design without appeal to a designer. And to
explain away the appearance of design without appeal to a designer is not to show
that we can think of design without a designer; it is rather to show that we ought
to cease thinking of the natural world as designed.” (Davies, 2001, p. 59).
Since natural selection is a mindless process it cannot literally be true that it intentionally
selects structures for functional purposes. The use of such metaphorical language on our part
might be instrumental in some way but it does not describe what is actually going on with natural
selection. As Jerry Fodor writes,
"It couldn't, for example, be literally true [my emphasis] that the traits selected for
are the ones Mother Nature has in mind when she does the selecting; nor can it be
literally true that they are the traits one's selfish genes have in mind when they
undertake to reproduce themselves. There is, after all, no Mother Nature, and
genes don't have, or lack, personality defects. Metaphors are fine things; science
266
probably couldn't be done without them. But they are supposed to be the sort of
things that can, in a pinch, be cashed. Lacking a serious and literal construal of
'selection for', adaptationism founders on the methodological truism" (Fodor,
2007, p. 20).
259
A doorknob is for, has the purpose of, opening and closing doors because that is what it
was brought about in order to do. A watch, likewise, is for, has the purpose of, telling time. But
the functions of naturally-selected structures are not like that because natural selection cannot
select any structure in order to fulfill some functional goal. Designers, on the other hand,
routinely select the structures of artifacts in order to fulfill some functional goal.
A teleological explanation, a design explanation, is an explanation of functional purpose
that explains what the function of some structure is by recourse to what it was “selected to” do or
what it was "designed to" do.
At this point I would like to provide some further explication of what being "designed"
means. In order for something to be designed it must have been designed by an agent who
employed her creativity in bringing it about. If something is designed, then it is something that a
designer herself brought into existence by employing her creativity. Let's consider the proposal
as a definition of what being designed means.
X is designed if and only if some agent, y, employed her creativity to bring about
x.
But this definition has some difficulties.
Being the product of someone's creativity is not enough to show that that thing was
designed by that agent. For example, suppose that some agent uses her creativity to design a
fireworks show which unintentionally results in a patch of woods catching on fire. In this case
259
Fodor has also made similar remarks in his paper "Against Darwinism", Mind & Language,
2008. (Fodor, 2008a).
267
the designer did not design the patch of woods catching on fire because it was not her intention
for the patch of woods to catch fire when she designed the fireworks show. The patch of woods
catching on fire, however, was the product of her creativity. She designed the fireworks show,
but she did not design the patch of woods catching on fire.
So how might the definition of design be improved to take this kind of problematic
example into account?
To that end I propose the following revised version of what it means for some object to
be designed.
X is designed if and only if some agent, y, employed her creativity to intentionally
bring about x.
On this definition a painting would qualify as a "designed" object if that painter used her
creativity to bring it about and that designer used her creativity to intentionally bring it about.
The designer of the fireworks show designed the fireworks show. But she did not design the
patch of woods catching on fire because she did not employ her creativity to intentionally bring it
about.
But what exactly is creativity?
I will use the term “creativity” as it is defined by the Merriam-Webster Dictionary. It
defines creativity as “the ability to make new things or think of new ideas”. So when an agent is
creative, or engages in creativity, that agent uses her ability to bring about some new idea or
concept. Arthur Cropley also emphasizes the newness, or what we might also call novelty,
associated with creativity in the following way. He writes.
“Almost 50 years ago, Morgan (1953) reviewed a large number of definitions of
creativity and showed that the single common element was novelty. Cognitive
definitions of creativity usually follow this tradition and emphasize production of
novelty as the crucial aspect [my emphasis]...Novelty can be produced in the
form of mere self-expression (daubing paint on paper, writing text in any way that
pleases the writer, or picking out notes at random on the piano) or of simple
268
production of variability (doing things differently from the usual regardless of
accuracy, meaning, sense, significance, or interestingness)." (Cropley, 1999, p.
253).
It should be recognized that the novelty that is of concern here is the novelty of an idea.
For example, a random bolt of lightning might be regarded as novel in that it might be an
unexpected or surprising thing, but it is not a novel idea or an innovative concept. So the novelty
that I am speaking about here is a novelty of an idea or concept.
A novel idea, however, might be "new" in two different senses. For instance, if an
individual comes up with an idea for an invention that already happens to exist (even though this
individual does not know that such an invention already exists), that person would have come up
with a novel idea. The activity of coming up with that new idea would be an instance of
creativity. But this new idea would be "new to her". It would not, however, be "new to the
world".
But even if an idea is not "new to the world" that should not entail that the person's
activity in coming up with the idea is not creative. An historical incident in which two separate
people had independently come up with the same idea was the invention of calculus by both
Newton and Leibniz. Although both of their ideas were not, in a strict sense, "new to the world"
(because the other had already invented it) it would be false to say that neither of them had been
creative in coming up with the idea of calculus. In other words an idea need not be "new to the
world" in order for it to be an instance of a person's creativity.
Should some agent produce an idea that is both "new to the agent" and "new to the
world" that too would be an instance of that agent's creativity. For simplicity's sake I will a
confine illustrative cases of a person's creativity to cases in which that agent's idea is both "new
to the agent" and "new to the world".
There can be instances in which a team of designers can work collaboratively to bring
269
about an designed thing. For example, automobiles are designed by a team of designers
collaboratively working together. One engineer designs the steering wheel of the automobile
while another designs its drivetrain. If there should exist an automobile that was designed by a
team of designers, then that would mean that that team designed it. The team, then, would be the
agent that designed the automobile.
260
There can also be instances where one or more features of an object were designed by
separate designers but in which other features of that object were not designed by them either
individually or as a group collaboratively. For example, one of the features of a television set is
that its screen melts at 1400˚C. This is a feature of the television set. But it was not designed by
any of the designers of the television. Also, a collection of toys under a Christmas tree might
each be designed by different designers yet the feature of the collection itself appearing
underneath the tree was not brought about by any of the individual designers of the toys. In this
case one of the toys was made by one designer while some other toy was made by yet another
designer. But the collection of toys itself was not collaboratively made by them.
The above considerations suggest that a person can design a feature of an object without
having to design all of the features of that object, that a person can design a feature of an object,
but not in collaboration with other designers of other features of that same object or that a single
designer could design all of the features of an object without any causal input from other agents.
To take into account the fact that features of an objects can be designed we can stipulate
that some features of an object are designed if they are ones that some agent employed her
creativity to intentionally bring about. With this in mind I propose the following definition of
what it means for a feature of some object to be designed.
260
Of course, not all teams are agents.
270
Feature, f, of object, o, is a designed feature of o if and only if some agent, y, employed
her creativity to intentionally bring about f in o.
We can of course imagine some cases in which a teleofunctional object was brought
about by an agent
261
that designed all of its teleofunctional features that are essential to its self-
maintenance. For example, a tree is a teleofunctional object. In order for it to be teleofunctional
it must maintain its own biological integrity. And in order for it to do that it must have
teleofunctional features that are essential to its self-maintenance. These features are what I call
"essential teleofunctional features". An essential teleofunctional feature is a feature that a
teleofunctional object has that if absent would result in the cessation of that system's self-
maintenance.
262
A tree, is a teleofunctional object and so has certain essential teleofunctional
features. One of those essential teleofunctional features is its possession of phloem, a transporter
of sugars. Without this essential teleofunctional feature the tree would cease to maintain itself. It
would die. So we could imagine a case were a designer brought about this teleofunctional object
261
An "agent" can be either a single rational agent or a team of agents.
262
There can also exist non-essential teleofunctional features that fulfill non-essential
teleofunctional roles. These features, while not essential to a teleofunctional object's self-
maintenance, can nonetheless be conducive to it. For example, having a left hand is a non-
essential teleofunctional feature that my body has. I can continue to live and maintain my own
biological integrity without having a left hand. Nonetheless, having a left hand is conducive to
my self-maintenance. I can use it to feed myself, to grasp a glass of water or to fight off a
predator. These states of affairs are conducive to my self-maintenance in that they make some
sort of contribution (however slight) to my long-term biological integrity. Having a left hand
fulfills those non-essential teleofunctional roles. But having a left hand is not necessary to my
self-maintenance. Having a left hand is not essential to my self-maintenance. And so having that
property fulfills some non-essential teleofunctional role. I can live without having a left hand.
Having a heart, on the other hand, is an essential teleofunctional feature because having a heart
fulfills an essential teleofunctional role within my body. If I did not have a heart my blood would
no longer pump blood which would result in oxygen not being delivered throughout my body
which would result in the cessation of my self-maintenance. I could, however, have a
replacement heart or an artificial heart. And if I had one of those features they would fulfill the
same essential teleofunctional role as my having of a heart presently does.
271
and all of its essential teleofunctional features, which would include its phloem.
There can, however, exist some cases in which all of the teleofunctional features of a
non-sentient being were brought about by a designer even if some other agent was also partially,
causally responsible for bringing it about.
Consider the following case.
Nancy intends to bring about an adapted, self-regulating cell. She consults the
owner’s manual of a new invention, The Adapted Cell Machine. This machine can
produce any kind of appropriately adapted cell if an operator tell the machine
what environment that she wants the cell is to exist in. Nancy enters in the
appropriate environmental data into the machine so that it produces a cell that
can exist in the forest soils of the Amazonian rainforest. The machine spits out a
teleofunctional cell capable of regulating itself in those environmental conditions.
Here we have a case where an agent, Nancy, brought about a teleofunctional living being
that was adapted to its environment.
But Nancy did not design any of the teleofunctional features of this cell. We might say
that Nancy was in part responsible for bringing about the cell and that the inventor of the
machine was also in part responsible for bringing it about. But Nancy did not use her creativity
to intentionally bring about any of the teleofunctional features of it. Rather she used a machine
that was designed by some other agent for the purpose of generating teleofunctional cells.
The designer of the machine, however, can be said to be the designer of some of the
teleofunctional features of the cell. Let us suppose that the designer of the machine programmed
it to produce a particular kind of teleofunctional structure in response to a particular request by
some other agent. The designer of the machine would have intentionally brought that
teleofunctional structure about by employing his creativity. That teleofunctional feature would
have been designed by the designer of the machine.
263
263
An analogous case of design involving a machine that produces an object that has a feature
272
But let us imagine another case where Nancy does not enter the environmental data into
the machine to produce the cell but rather programs the machine to produce the cell by providing
it with explicit, procedural instructions for how it is to make it.
264
If her programming of the
machine specified numerous procedural operations aimed at producing a specific kind of
functional organism that she had in mind then this looks more like a case of actual design by
Nancy. Nancy would be the designer for some of the teleofunctional features of the cell produced
by the machine in that her programming of the machine required instructional input on her part
to direct the system to produce an intended output. Such a case would be more analogous to a
computer programmer entering instructional information into a computer so that it would engage
in a particular computational process that would generate a specific kind of output.
Taking the above considerations in mind I propose the following definition of what a
designed teleofunctional feature is.
Teleofunctional feature, f, of a teleofunctional object, o, is a designed
teleofunctional feature of o if and only if some agent, y, employed her creativity to
intentionally bring about f in o.
For the remainder of the dissertation I will confine my discussion of cases in which all of
the essential teleofunctional features of some teleofunctional object were brought about by a
single designer rather than by a team of designers all the while recognizing that that object could
that was designed by the designer of the machine is that of a computer that was designed to
produce a specific kind of font for a document that has other features that were designed by some
other agent. The font can be designed by the designer of the computer while other features of the
document, such as the particular words typed on it, were produced by some agent other than the
designer of the computer.
264
If Nancy's act of "programming" the machine to produce this cell was similar to a person
ordering an item from a long list of items in a catalog, then it does not appear as if she did any
real designing at all. None of its features would have been designed by her. Some might even
suggest that this is not an instance of her actually programming the machine but rather of her
choosing one of the many options that the machine can run.
273
have been designed by such a team.
At the end of the previous chapter I suggested that non-sentient teleofunctional beings
produced by a non-design etiology cannot be guaranteed to have indirect moral standing. But in
this chapter I will argue that non-sentient living things produced by design are guaranteed to
have indirect moral standing.
I have attempted to show in the previous chapter that all of the etiological accounts of
interests considered up until this point are incapable of accounting for how non-sentient
teleofunctional beings could have interests that are directly morally considerable. These other
etiological accounts are incapable of doing this because the antecedent conditions of those
accounts are not able to make it the case that the teleofunctional interests of all non-sentient
beings provide a reason for why they should have direct moral standing.
However, as also I mentioned in the previous chapter, all non-sentient living beings can
have indirect moral standing.
There is one way that all non-sentient living beings could get indirect moral standing in
such a way that is not contingent on another person's preference interests. Non-sentient living
beings would be guaranteed to have indirect moral standing if they were designed.
II. Can all Designed, Non-Sentient, Living Things be guaranteed to have Indirect Moral
Standing?; (i) The Argument from Creativity
In this section I will argue that if all non-sentient living thing were designed then their
indirect moral standing can be guaranteed.
At this point I want to argue that since creativity is a virtue that has intrinsic value, and
since the exercise of a virtue is an intrinsically good thing, then all valuers have a reason to have
274
a reason not to harm the object that was brought about by creativity independently of whether
they realize the existence of such a reason. Moreover all valuers have this reason independently
of whether they have a preference interest in the thing that was designed. In other words, if
designed, then all non-sentient living things will be guaranteed to have indirect moral standing. It
is guaranteed in the sense that their design etiology guarantees that there is a reason not to harm
them. It is indirect, however, in the sense that they have their moral standing by recourse to their
etiology not by recourse to any intrinsic properties or inherent goals of their own.
My argument is roughly the following:
1) For all x, if x is a DNSLT
265
, then x's teleofunctional interests were brought
about by creativity.
2) Creativity is an intrinsically good activity.
3) Thus, if x's teleofunctional interests were brought about by creativity, then x
was brought about by an intrinsically good activity.
4) If x was brought about by an intrinsically good activity, then there is a reason
why all valuers should have positive regard for the activity of bringing about
x.
5) If there is a reason why all valuers should have positive regard for the activity
of bringing about x then there is reason why all valuers should not harm x that
is not based on any of x intrinsic properties.
6) If there is reason why all valuers should not harm x that is not based on any of
x intrinsic properties then x has indirect moral standing.
7) Thus, for all x, if x is a DNSLT, then x has indirect moral standing.
At this point I want to defend the argument's premises.
Premise one simply falls out of the definition of design that I presented earlier in this
chapter.
Premise two, however, needs to be defended. This premise claims that creativity is an
intrinsically good thing. But why think that? G.E. Moore has made the observation that if
someone asks the question of what make something that is good good then trying to provide an
265
Here DNSLT means "designed, non-sentient living thing"
275
answer as to makes it good would be a futile endeavor. He writes,
“What, then, is good? How is good to be defined?...What I want to discover is the
nature of that object or idea, and about this I am extremely anxious to arrive at an
agreement… But if we understand the question in this sense, my answer to it may
seem a very disappointing one. If I am asked, ‘What is good?’ my answer is that
good is good, and that is the end of the matter. Or if I am asked ‘How is good to
be defined?’ my answer is that it cannot be defined and that is all I have to say
about it…My point is that ‘good’ is a simple notion, just as ‘yellow’ is a simple
notion; that just as you cannot, by any manner of means, explain to anyone who
does not already know it, what yellow is, so you cannot explain what good is.”
(Moore, 1948, pp. 6-7).
Well, some hold the view that creativity itself has intrinsic, value. On this view there
simply would be no answer to the question of why creativity is good. It simply is good, in and of
itself. But perhaps we can do a little bit better than that. Another way of looking at it is that
creativity is regarded by some to be an admirable or virtuous quality which means to say that it is
a good quality for a person to have.
As Berys Gaut writes,
“...to establish that creativity is an excellence, we merely have to establish that it
is a valuable psychological quality [my emphasis]. That is widely acknowledged:
we praise and admire people for their creativity, we seek to foster it in various
ways through educational and cultural projects, and so on. We also do not value
creativity merely as a means, i.e. for its effects, but also value it as an end: that is,
we think that it has final or intrinsic value [my emphasis].” (Gaut, 2014, p.188)
266
If this defense is sufficient, then creativity simply is a good thing and whenever someone
is creative or is engaged in some creative activity then that person is at some level "doing a good
thing". For the purposes of this dissertation I will assume that creativity, if it is a virtuous
activity, would be a virtuous activity for any rational agent to engage in not just human beings.
266
In other words, creativity is one excellence. It is one intellectual virtue. For an interesting
discussion of creativity as an intellectual virtue see Linda Zagzebski’s 1996 book, Virtues of the
Mind: An Inquiry into the Nature of Virtue and the Ethical Foundations of Knowledge, pp.123-
125. See also Gaut, 2014.
276
There is, however, one rather simple argument that one could construct to show that
creativity is a good thing. That is the following.
1) All virtues are good things.
2) Creativity is a virtue.
3) Thus, creativity is a good thing.
Some at this point, however, might object to premise 2 of the above argument. They
might say that if some rational agent is engaged in a creative activity then that agent is not
necessarily doing a good thing. This might not be an unreasonable thing to suppose. In fact there
might exist many activities that involve a designer's creativity that are not in the final analysis
good activities at all. There can be things that could have taken a designer's creativity to make
yet not be something that we, in the final analysis, should care about. For instance, suppose that
an extremely powerful, diabolical agent used his great creativity to design a bacterium capable of
causing much suffering and death in the human population. This being is highly skilled at
manipulating biological materials to make new forms of life. His creative abilities were put to
use in the service of making something that was intended to bring about great harm to others.
There was a malicious intent behind his creative genius. On the whole it seems reasonable to
think that this bacterium is not something that would be appropriate for valuers to protect or
promote.
But there is a response to the claim that a designer's creative activity is not a good thing.
Although our diabolical agent had the virtue of creativity, he did not exercise that
particular virtue in a way consistent with the other virtues. He did not possess other virtues such
as benevolence, caring or charity when he was constructing his deadly bacterium. The lack of
these other virtues made his activity of designing this deadly bacterium an activity that was not
on the whole not good. A very powerful, diabolical agent who designs a deadly pestilence is not
on the whole acting virtuously even if his creative activity does involve that virtue. Creativity is
277
but one virtue that a designer could have. But simply having this virtue is not enough to justify
the claim that anything that was created by it must be, in the final analysis, worthy of being cared
about non-instrumentally.
Even our diabolical, agent had at least one virtuous character trait, that of having
creativity. It was a virtue that he had. As such, the exercise of that virtue does provide a reason
for why his designed object should not be harmed. But this reason is, of course, swamped by
many other reasons available for why it should be harmed, reasons pertaining to the designer's
malicious intents. In the final analysis, we should destroy this designed pestilence, not because it
was not made with a virtue, but because there is much more of a reason to destroy it than there is
not to.
Or consider another example. Suppose that a team of engineers designed a highly
sophisticated missile capable of exploding just two inches above ground. Such a missile would
be a marvel of creative engineering. It takes a lot of technical proficiency and skill to design
something with that level of precision. This level of technical proficiency and creativity is a
virtue. But should that missile have been designed for the malevolent purpose of killing an entire
village of innocent people, we should not think that the missile, in the final analysis, deserves to
be protected from harm rather than destroyed.
If premises one and two are true then the conclusion at line three necessarily follows.
The following is a defense of premise four.
When someone does a good thing then there is a reason for us to recognize the value of
the good thing that that person had done. In other words when someone does a good thing then
all valuers have a reason to take up positive attitude toward the good activity in question.
For example, let us consider Michelangelo's Pieta.
278
Given that the Pieta was brought about by creativity, which is intrinsically valuable, we
should have a positive attitude of value toward the goodness of Michelangelo's creative activity
of bringing it about. This does not mean that we should value the Pieta directly or that we have
direct obligations to it. Rather we should have an attitude toward the creativity that went into
making it.
The following is a defense of premises five and six.
Let us consider the Pieta again.
All valuers have a reason not to harm the Pieta since it was brought about by an
intrinsically good or virtuous activity. This does not mean that there is a reason to have a positive
attitude toward it, or that all valuers would never have a reason to destroy it.
267
It just means
that all valuers have a reason to treat it in a way consistent with the fact that it was brought about
by a virtuous activity. So if non-sentient living things were designed by an agent, then that agent
did a good thing which means that all valuers have a reason not to harm that designed object.
In this way the Pieta has indirect moral standing because there exists a reason not to harm
it, a reason not based on any of its intrinsic properties.
268
Or consider another example.
Let us suppose that a father receives a stick figure drawing that was lovingly made for
him by his two-year-old daughter, that object would be something that the father has a reason not
267
For instance, valuers could have a reason to destroy a designed work if that work was meant
to be destroyed or if this work is something that in the final analysis is something that should be
destroyed. They would not, however, have a reason to wantonly destroy it that is to destroy it for
no reason whatsoever or for very poor reasons.
268
I am not here arguing that all valuers should have the highest positive regard toward a
designer's work, only that all valuers have a reason for why they should not destroy it even if that
reason is not in the final analysis enough for why all valuers should have an on balance positive
regard toward a designer's work or even not to harm it.
279
to harm. He has a reason not to harm it because it was "made with love". Even if other valuers
have no relation to the designer of this picture, the picture was still made with love even if the
picture itself doesn't make the father happy. Although there is no empirical indication that it was
made with love, the etiology of the object involved this girl's love. Her love, we might say, "went
into" the making of it. This drawing, like the Pieta, has indirect moral standing because there
exists a reason not to harm it that is not based on any intrinsic properties of it.
In like manner, if some non-sentient, teleofunctional being was brought about by
creativity there would be reason for why all valuers should not harm it. Non-designed, non-
sentient beings, on the other hand, things that were not brought about creativity, are not ones in
which it is guaranteed that there is a reason not to harm them. They were not produced by an
intrinsically good, virtuous activity and so being the products of creativity cannot be among one
of the reasons available for why those beings should not be harmed.
At this point the biocentrist might have a complaint to make against this argument. Many
biocentrists want to avoid any anthropocentric orientation towards value judgments about the
natural world. In light of their concerns to avoid anthropocentrism they might say, "Living
organisms should have value regardless of what we human beings believe about the world. What
you are implying is that non-sentient living organisms should not be harmed so long as we
believe that creativity went into the making of them. But the beliefs of human beings are not
what justifies the claim that all non-sentient living organisms should not be harmed. They should
not be harmed for reasons independent of what human beings think."
But this worry can be addressed.
While it is true that human beings might believe that creativity went into the making of
some non-sentient living things, it is not true that our thinking that some non-sentient living thing
280
was brought about by creativity is what makes it the case that they were brought about by
creativity. Creativity, as I have defined it, is an attribute that agents can either possess or not
possess. If they possess it then they possess an intellectual virtue that is good in and of itself. If
they do not possess it then they do not possess that intellectual virtue and cannot engage in
creative activity. If some agent exercises creativity in the making of some designed object, then
the making of that object is a good thing independently of whether we think that it is a good
thing. As such the reason why that designed thing should not be harmed exists independently or
whether we believe that a virtuous activity went into the making of it or not.
If this argument is sound, then designed, non-sentient living things would be guaranteed
to have indirect moral standing in that there would exist a reason for why those beings should not
be harmed that is not based on any of their intrinsic properties. This reason would exist
independently of whether human beings have a preference interest in their teleofunctional
interests.
III. Can all Designed, Non-Sentient, Living Things be guaranteed to have Indirect Moral
Standing?; (ii) The Argument from Teleofunctional Purposes
But there is another argument available for why designed, non-sentient living things
would be guaranteed to have indirect moral standing.
As I have argued previously, the claim that non-designed teleofunctional structures can
malfunction or function correctly is false.
269
These structures do not teleofunctional purposes.
As such they cannot, properly speaking, be caused to malfunction.
But the proposition that designed teleofunctional structures are capable of malfunctioning
269
See sections IV through VIII of chapter four.
281
is quite reasonable. When rational agents design various objects they design them to perform
various functions. Should a non-sentient living thing be designed then it would have
teleofunctional structures that have teleofunctional purposes. Rational agents can generate
teleofunctional structures that have teleofunctional purposes because those agents can
consciously select a teleofunctional structure for a teleofunctional purpose. And if so then those
structures would have functional purposes. And if all non-sentient living beings in the actual
world were designed then it would literally be true that their teleofunctional structures have
teleofunctional purposes and are thus capable of malfunctioning.
In his book Warrant and Proper Function, Alvin Plantinga discusses how it is natural for
us to speak of designed artifacts, as well as living organisms, as having proper functions
270
. He
writes,
“Our paradigm cases of design and proper function, therefore, are artifacts, things
designed by conscious agents. This is the ancestral home of the notion; this is
where they apply most naturally and easily. Still, we certainly do apply this whole
family of concepts to the natural world. We think a hawk’s heart that beats only
twenty-five times a minute is not functioning properly, that AIDS damages the
immune system and makes it function poorly, that multiple sclerosis causes the
immune system to malfunction in such a way that white blood cells attack the
nervous system, and that the purpose or function of the heart is to pump blood,
not to make that thumpa-thumpa sound. The notions of proper function, disease,
and damage apply here and in a thousand other contexts; thinking in these terms is
natural and apparently unavoidable for human beings” (Plantinga, 1993, p. 196).
Plantinga argues that the notion of proper function, although a common notion that we
use all of the time, cannot ultimately be embraced by the strict naturalist because functional
purposes themselves cannot be accounted for, in strictly naturalist terms.
271
In addressing the
naturalist he writes,
270
By "proper function" Plantinga means functional purposes.
271
To read Plantinga's argument see the section entitled 'Naturalistic Analyses of Proper
Function' in the chapter "Naturalism versus Proper Function" in Warrant and Proper Function.
282
"So suppose you are a naturalist, and are convinced that there is no way to make
sense of the notion of proper function from a naturalistic perspective...you will
have to reject the notion of proper function as well. If you are dead certain
naturalism is true, you will have to accept the cost...[of] rejecting the very idea of
proper function. A high cost, no doubt - but no more than what a serious
naturalism exacts." (Plantinga, 1993, p. 214)
Likewise, should a naturalistically-minded biocentrist refuse to accept a design etiology
for the existence of non-sentient teleofunctional beings, then he or she must reject the notion of
proper function or functional purpose too. And, along with that, he or she must reject the notion
of biological malfunction as well. If so then the existence of functional purposes for the
teleofunctional structures of living things cannot be among the reasons that such a biocentrist
can appeal to in her efforts to argue on behalf of the protection of all non-sentient living things.
If, on the other hand, a biocentrist does not endorse a non-design etiology, but instead a
design etiology for all living beings, then making sense of the notion of functional purpose
would be rather straightforward and uncomplicated for her. Designers routinely select structures
for functional purposes. For example, spacecraft engineers can design a door hatch for the
functional purpose of allowing astronauts access into and out of the cockpit. That purpose was
given to the door hatch by its designer(s). The spacecraft engineers designed that structure for
that functional purpose. Likewise, a designer of teleofunctional features can fashion those
features for teleofunctional purposes. For example, should a scientist design the cell membrane
of a teleofunctional cell for the teleofunctional purpose of selectively filtering matter, then that
teleofunctional feature would have a teleofunctional purpose.
If someone were to puncture that membrane then such an action would result in causing it
to malfunction. Since the membrane is for selectively filtering matter, any action that causes it to
longer to do what it is for would be an action of causing it to malfunction. Causing it to
malfunction would be an instance of causing it to function in a way contrary to what the designer
283
had intended it for. The fact that such a teleofunctional structure was intended to perform a
certain function provides a reason for why that structure should not be caused to malfunction.
Notice that the existence of this reason does not depend on the preference interests or
evaluative attitudes of other agents.
This argument is meant to show four different things. 1) that if some teleofunctional
feature was not designed then that feature would not have a teleofunctional purpose and hence
would not be capable of malfunctioning, 2) that if those features are incapable of malfunctioning
then there is no reason why someone should not cause them to malfunction, 3) that if some
teleofunctional feature was designed then that feature would have a teleofunctional purpose and
hence would be capable of malfunctioning and 4) that if that teleofunctional feature has a
functional purpose then there is a reason why someone should not cause it to malfunction.
The naturalistically-minded biocentrist cannot appeal to functional purpose of the
teleofunctional structures of non-sentient beings as providing a reason for why they should not
be harmed. Non-designed objects do not have features with functional purposes. Hence, the
prospect of malfunction cannot be among the reasons available for why those objects should not
be harmed. These reasons, however, can be available to the biocentrist that accepts a design
etiology for the existence of non-sentient teleofunctional beings and their teleofunctional
features.
IV. Introduction to a Theistic, Design Etiology and Further Reasons Available for the
Indirect Moral Standing of Designed, Non-sentient Beings
At this point I want to argue that if a certain kind of design etiology for the existence of
non-sentient living things were true then those beings would have indirect moral standing for
284
reasons beyond those given in the two previous arguments. The following arguments are meant
to show that given a certain kind of design etiology that there would exist still other reasons for
why the non-sentient living things produced by that etiology should not be harmed. The reasons
cannot be available for why a similar, but non-designed, non-sentient being should not be
harmed.
Consider the following, possible scenario for a certain kind of design etiology.
Let us imagine a world in which there exists God. This agent is a being that Richard
Swinburne describes as "an omnipresent spirit who is perfectly free, creator of the Universe,
omnipotent, omniscient, perfectly good..." (Swinburne, 1993, p. 291).
272
Let us further imagine
that in this world God designed all of the non-sentient living beings that exist in it. These non-
sentient living beings are exactly like the ones that exist in the actual world. These beings,
however, were not brought about by a non-design etiology. They were designed. Let us imagine
further that God not only designed the non-sentient teleofunctional beings that we witness in that
world, but that because of his love for us God also intended for those beings to inspire us with a
sense of awe and wonder at the beings that he designed.
273
In other words, let us imagine that
God out of his love for us designed all non-sentient living beings as a means of inspiring beings
like with a sense of awe and wonder. Let us further imagine that in this world God also has an
interest in observing the self-maintaining capacities of these non-sentient beings and in taking
some satisfaction in the continued success of his own creative efforts. In this world God has a
preference interest in the continued self-maintenance of those non-sentient beings that he
272
I am not here, however, defending the proposition that such an agent exists.
273
Some, however, might think that entertaining this possibility is entirely gratuitous or without
merit. They might argue that God is the type of being that we cannot rationally comprehend and
so on that basis it wouldn't be possible for us to make any approximation as to what God would
do at all.
285
designed. In fact it might be best to describe the entire collection of interests pertaining to the
designing of these non-sentient beings as God's project. A project, as I define it, is a collection of
activities all of which are intended to bring about some goal or aim that involves the satisfaction
of numerous preference interests. In explaining Bernard Williams' idea of what a project is
Joseph Okumu writes that the projects of people are "things that count as important or
meaningful in their lives" (Okumu, 2007, p. 20). So the production and enjoyment of the non-
sentient beings that exist in this world is a project of God's because they count as important or
meaningful in God's life.
274
For the purposes of this dissertation I will refer to the above etiological story as the
"theistic design etiology".
275
As I mentioned previously the particular claim that all non-sentient teleofunctional beings
have moral standing in their own right is very difficult to defend on the basis of the various
naturalistic approaches that we have covered thus far. In fact it does not appear as if any non-
sentient teleofunctional beings can have moral standing in their own right. Furthermore,
designed non-sentient teleofunctional beings cannot have moral standing in their own right
either. Nonetheless, I will argue that there would exists special reasons for why the non-sentient
teleofunctional beings that were brought by the "theistic design etiology" should not be harmed.
Reasons that do not exist for not harming non-designed, non-sentient living things.
274
The type of theism that I have in mind here is that of a transcendent creator who created the
natural world but stands apart from it. There do exist various efforts put forward by some
environmentalists to impute purposiveness, intentionality, spiritedness or other teleological
characteristics directly onto non-sentient beings or to nature itself. In this way they claim that all
non-sentient beings are just extensions of God or that the natural world is God. I will, for this
dissertation, set aside such possibilities.
275
There could, of course, exist many other ways in which God could have brought about all
living things much different than the one being presented here.
286
Before I proceed, however, I would like to provide some background information on
what other environmentalists have said about the place of God in environmentalist ethics and of
what could motivate the argument that the existence and action of God in the world could
provide a reason for why non-sentient living things should not be harmed.
V. Theism and Its Place in Environmental Ethics
Some philosophers have discussed the connection between religious belief and how it
bears on the subject of environmental ethics including the moral standing of all living things.
For example, Scott Aikin appeals to the problem of evil as a means of suggesting that
God's existence is inconsistent with the moral standing of all living things. He writes,
"The perspective of environmental ethics attunes us to the moral significance of
pointless destruction of non-human entities. There is considerably more suffering
in the world than humans experience, but there is no other good to weigh that
suffering against. Ecosystems and groves of trees cannot have free will, and so
when they are degraded and destroyed, they are harmed in the service of goods
they cannot have. That is unjust. Animals do not have souls made to emulate God,
and so when they suffer, they are not improved and tooled in God's image. They
merely suffer and die, and they do so for goods they cannot have. That is
unjust...The lesson is that environmental ethics makes the problem of evil harder
to solve. The moral considerability of animals and ecosystems is inconsistent [my
emphasis] with God's capacity, justice, and in the end, his existence." (Aikin,
2014, pp. 38-39).
This argument might be taken to suggest that theism or religious belief cannot make a
substantial contribution to environmental ethics because the existence of evil in the world is
inconsistent with God's existence.
Other environmentalists hold the view that particular religious beliefs, such as
Christianity, are not only unable to serve the environmentalist's cause but appear to do damage to
it. They think that a particular kind of theistic belief, Christianity, is responsible for the presence
of moral disregard for the natural world by humans, one that does not care about the living
287
things on the planet and that only seeks to use up the resources of the natural world for human
ends. They claim that only by the eradication of this kind of worldview will we be able to truly
value and protect the natural world as we ought. For example, Lynn White's famous essay "The
Historical Roots of Our Ecologic Crisis" argues that Christian religious belief, as opposed to
other religious beliefs, has been detrimental to, rather than supportive of, a viable and long-term
ethic of concern for the natural world. He writes,
"Christianity, in absolute contrast to ancient paganism and Asia's religions
(except, perhaps, Zoroastrianism), not only established a dualism of man and
nature but also insisted that it is God's will that man exploit nature for his proper
ends [my emphasis]. At the level of the common people this worked out in an
interesting way.
In Antiquity every tree, every spring, every stream, every hill had its own genius
loci, its guardian spirit. These spirits were accessible to men, but were very unlike
men; centaurs, fauns, and mermaids show their ambivalence. Before one cut a
tree, mined a mountain, or dammed a brook, it was important to placate the spirit
in charge of that particular situation, and to keep it placated. By destroying pagan
animism, Christianity made it possible to exploit nature in a mood of indifference
to the feelings of natural objects." (White, 1967, p. 1205).
Bernard Zaleha also points out how the "Lynn White Thesis" (the thesis that Christian
religious belief is not supportive of a genuine environmental ethic) has not only galvanized the
view that real environmentalism is secular, but also that religion in general tends to foster moral
disregard toward the plight of the natural world. Zaleha writes,
"Poet and environmentalist Wendell Berry has noted that largely because of
White’s argument, ‘the culpability of Christianity in the destruction of the natural
world, and the uselessness of Christianity [my emphasis] to any effort to correct
that destruction, are now established clichés of the conservation movement’
(Berry 1993: 93).
The Lynn White Thesis finds an intense resonance among many secular
environmental activists (Pope 1998: 14). Further, it continues to find anecdotal
support. A Baptist church in Boise, Idaho, printed and distributed this large and
wordy four-lined bumper sticker: 'Forget "Save the Earth"; What about your soul?
The earth is going to burn, What about you?', evidencing a concern about a
different sort of global warming (Zaleha 2008b: 217). When interviewed by Bill
Moyers in his October 2006 PBS special, Is God Green?, a program exploring the
emergence of various strands of evangelical Christian environmentalism, Calvin
Beisner, a conservative Orthodox Presbyterian theologian and global warming
288
denier, when asked whether he worried that he might be wrong about global
warming, said that global warming, if real, is of little importance compared to
how one is 'going to live [in either heaven or hell for] eternity'. In both these
examples, no concern was expressed about the fate of Earth based on a conviction
that soon, after 'his' judgment, the Christian god will either make a new Earth of
send all humans to either heaven or hell, making planetary concerns unnecessary."
(Zaleha, 2013, p. 138).
Still other environmentalists think that the existence of a transcendent God might actually
detract from valuing the natural world as we ought.
Ned Hettinger, for example, defends the basic view that God, considered as a
transcendent deity, might take our attention off of the natural world and the goodness that it
contains. To him theism doesn't make a positive contribution to the moral standing of living
things in the natural world because it shifts our focus away from the natural world and sets our
eyes on other-worldly things. He writes,
"At the most general level, I worry that the appeal to a transcendent God is likely
to take the focus off valuing the earth and place it instead on valuing the
transcendent creator. Why revere the proximate cause when we can revere the
ultimate cause, especially when only the latter appreciates our attitude?"
(Hettinger, 2007, p. 73)
The acceptance of these views does not entail the view that God's existence and action in
the world provide no reason not to harm the environment. Nonetheless these views do invite the
question of just what, if any, role the existence of God might play in providing reasons for why
one should care for the natural world, reasons not available to a strictly naturalistic or secular
approach. Given widespread acceptance of the "Lynn White Thesis", the observation of the
problem of evil in the natural world, and the view that a transcendent God might take our focus
off of valuing nature, some might be tempted to think that God's existence and action in the
world cannot provide any reasons to value non-sentient living things and that a completely
naturalistic approach is the only viable option for a biocentrism.
289
These views do not prove that some environmentalists hold the view that if God exists
then his existence and action in the world provide no such reasons. Nonetheless these
philosophical positions do invite such a question especially if such positions are based on the
view that naturalistic approaches to securing the moral standing of all non-sentient
teleofunctional beings are either the only or best available.
It is not my intention here to argue that Christianity, or any other religious belief, is
useful to the environmentalist's efforts, nor to show that the problem of evil is not a problem for
theism, nor to show that God actually exists. Rather it is my intention to argue that the theistic,
design etiology mentioned in the previous section would make a substantial difference to the
claim that there exists reasons for why all non-sentient living things have indirect moral standing
and that these reasons cannot belong the naturalist. This etiology, if true, would provide certain
kinds of reasons for why all non-sentient beings made by that etiology should not be harmed and
should instead be positively regarded in some way. These kinds of reasons are not applicable to
non-designed, non-sentient beings.
VI. Information and the Design of Non-Sentient, Teleofunctional Beings
So how, precisely, could there exist another reason not to harm a non-sentient living thing
brought about by the theistic design etiology that is not available to the naturalist? A good place
to begin is by recognizing the creative ingenuity that it would take for a designer to produce the
non-sentient teleofunctional beings that exist in the natural world. If God designed those beings
then beings like us would have quite a lot to admire about his creative abilities in comparison to
our own. We should admire the designer's creative talents not because the beings produced by
the designer are instrumentally useful for our purposes, but simply because those beings would
290
show evidence of their designer's creative abilities. Things that show evidence of their designer's
great creative abilities are ones in which there exists a reason not to harm them.
Designing a non-sentient, teleofunctional form of life, particularly those forms of life
found on earth, would require the generation of massive amounts of genetic information and the
integration of precisely controlled physiological processes for their self-maintenance. In a
revealing passage in his article “Value in Nature and the Nature of Value” Holmes Rolston
points out the central role that genetic information plays in the lives of all living things. Plants,
according to Rolston, have interests that are facilitated by genetic information. He illustrates the
nature of these interests by invoking the terminology of information technology. Rolston
underscores the centrality of information to teleofunctional, life processes when he writes,
“Plants make themselves; they repair injuries; they move water, nutrients, and
photosynthate from cell to cell; they store sugars; they make tannin and other
toxins and regulate their levels of defence against grazers; they make nectars and
emit pheromones to influence the behavior of pollinating insects and the
responses of other plants; they emit allelopathic agents to suppress invaders; they
make thorns, trap insects. They can reject genetically incompatible grafts...A
plant, like any other organism, sentient or not, is a spontaneous, self-maintaining
system, sustaining and reproducing itself, executing its program [my emphasis],
making a way through the world, checking against performance be means of
responsive capacities with which to measure success. Something more than
physical causes, even when less than sentience, is operating; there is information
superintending the causes; without it the organism would collapse into a sand
heap [my emphasis]. The information is used to preserve the plant identity.”
(Rolston, 2003, p. 145).
Rolston's use of terms like "program" and "information" are not incidental. For starters,
all species of living things, from viruses and protozoans to algae and human beings, contain
genetic information. This information is the "program" that regulates and instructs biological
processes. Their "program" is bound up in the genetic sequences of nucleotides found along the
backbone of every DNA molecule of every species (see Figure 2 below). The sequences of
nucleotides in DNA dictate the initiation, production and precise topographic shape of each and
291
every protein manufactured in the cell. The protein's precise topographic shape allows it to
participate in highly regulated, teleofunctional, biochemical reactions that are essential for life.
The important thing to recognize is that the genetic information stored in an organism’s DNA
determines the precise structure and teleofunctional characteristics of every single protein found
in every cell of every individual organism including non-sentient organisms.
Figure 2. Structure of the DNA double-helix and its nucleotide base pairs.
(From: http://www.bristol.k12.ct.us/page.cfm?p=7097)
Enzyme regulation, physiological feedback loops, self-regulating metabolic processes
and other tightly, integrated and regulated functions are teleofunctional processes that require
genetic information to occur. None of the teleofunctional structures found in living organisms
would exist, much less be able to perform their teleofunctions, without the genetic information
found in their DNA.
When it comes to the existence of teleofunctional structures found in living organisms
genetic information comes first. Teleofunctional processes that routinely occur in the lives of all
living things proceed on the basis of whatever genetic information is found within their genomes.
292
Without this information there is no possibility for the existence of their teleofunctional interests.
Genetic information is a necessary condition for the existence of the teleofunctional structures
found in living organisms that we observe in the natural world.
Rolston seems to be very comfortable with using the language of information and
information processing to describe what life processes are like. Also, for Rolston, this
information exists objectively, independently of whether human beings think that such
information exists or is important. He writes,
“The Picea (spruce) and Buteo (hawk) genetic sets, for instance, are full of
information. The information is long-lived, reproducing itself by means of amino
acid replacement across millions of years, a kind of fire which outlasts the sticks
that feed it…The self-maintaining know-how is there independently of our
observation, unmodified by our sense perception, primary in Locke’s sense”
(Rolston, 1982, p. 130).
Rolston also thinks that there is some proximity between our normal language concepts
and informational concepts applicable to the biological realm. Living organisms are like
information systems. He writes,
"...living things are active information systems, as is proved by genetic and
biochemical "linguistics." The purines and pyrimidines of the DNA and RNA
helixes serve as an "alphabet," organized by codons, word units, into chains rather
like sentences and paragraphs. The double helix can be unzipped and "read"; one
stereospecific molecule can "recognize" another and by this "coded messages" are
"communicated." Life continues by a steady "problem solving," and evolution
accumulates a sophisticated "memory," as organisms are better programmed by
natural selection to "deal with" their environment. The bio-logical chemistries
have such a cybernetic power that, though it is precognitive, the information
content roughly in every human cell is more than that in any human book"
(Rolston, 1981, p. 122).
Perhaps one may think that the above example is merely an isolated case of someone
comparing a living organism to an information system. After all, on the basis of the opinions of
one person how could we be confident that this individual isn’t just giving vent to his own
uninformed opinion? Accordingly someone could reasonably say, “Just because some
293
environmental ethicist talks about living organisms as information systems doesn’t mean that
living organisms really are information systems. Rolston is just one figure and a philosopher at
that. Are there any biologists that hold such a view?”
It turns out there are.
John Maynard Smith, the theoretical evolutionary biologist and geneticist, describes
living systems in informational terms particularly those aspects of living systems that are cellular
or molecular. In fact, he argues that this is common parlance. He writes,
“The colloquial use of informational terms is all-pervasive in molecular biology.
Transcription, translation, code, redundancy, synonymous, messenger, and
editing, proofreading, library - these are all technical terms in biology. I am not
aware of any confusions arising because their meanings are not understood. In
fact, the similarities between their meanings when referring to human
communication and genetics are surprisingly close” (Smith, 1999, p. 178).
Human-designed living artifacts would rely on the genetic information stored in their
DNA just as much as their naturally-evolved counterparts do. When researchers produce
synthetic organisms they may do so by either copying the original genetic information from an
already-existing organism, inserting novel genetic information into an existing sequence or
writing an entirely new genetic sequence from scratch.
276
This overlap between human
contrivances and living organisms is informational in nature. Take the following passage from
Nicholas Agar regarding the customization of the gene-bearer as being problematic for a
common sense notion of life. The information content in genes is easily transposable with the
digital information stored on a computer’s hard drive. He compares human-designed,
information technology to life when he writes,
“…the emerging area of Artificial Life make a further demand on the
commonsense concept [of life]. Many claim that the self-replicating, self-
organizing structures generated in computers are more than just simulations of
276
See, Holm, 2012, pp. 532-535.
294
life. This claim requires a notion that abstracts away familiar ideas about how life
is physically constituted” (Agar, 1997, p. 153).
Human contrivances such as ‘Artificial Life’ clearly contain genes and genes contain
information. The ‘self-replicating, self-organizing structures generated in computers also exhibit
their own informational attributes. The only difference between the computer program and a
synthetically-produced bacterial genome is that the information content of the program was
coded into it by a magnetic medium as a sequence of zeros and ones. The information content of
the synthetic bacterium's genome, on the other hand, was coded into it by inserting a precise
sequence of nucleotides into its DNA. The key point is that they both contain information useful
for the construction of functioning proteins.
In his book “Information and the Origin of Life” the biophysicist and philosopher Bernd-
Olaf Küppers writes, “the problem of the origin of life is clearly basically equivalent to the
problem of the origin of biological information” (Küppers, 1990, p. 170). And Francis Crick, one
of the co-discoverers of the DNA double-helix structure regards genetic information to be the set
of instructions
277
that "tells" the cell how to construct a properly-functioning protein. For him
information, regarded as a set of instructions, is crucial to all living things. He writes, “By
information I mean the specification of the amino acid sequence in protein…Information means
here the precise determination of sequence, either of bases in the nucleic acid or of amino acid
residues in the protein” (Crick, 1958, 32, p.144). The "precise determination of sequence" that he
277
Some philosophical naturalists might object to the claim that DNA is a set of instructions.
They might argue that instructions can only be brought about by an instructor as a being that has
a mind and since there is no instructor that brought about DNA there really are no instructions to
be found in DNA. Hence, for them DNA would not be a set of instructions. An example of usage
of the term "instructions" to describe what DNA is can be found in the Live Science online article
"Genes: The Instruction Manuals for Life" at http://www.livescience.com/10486-genes-
instruction-manuals-life.html. (Binns, 2006).
295
is referring to here is a kind of genetic "message", one that "instructs" the protein-making
equipment of the cell to produce the right kind of teleofunctional structures.
278
As such I will use the term "genetic information" to refer to a set of instructions found in
the genome of a living thing that dictates how it is to produce its own proteins as teleofunctional
structures.
279
The precise three-dimensional structure of all proteins is dictated by the precise sequence
of nucleotides found in DNA. As Achuthsankar Nair puts it,
“DNA, RNA and protein sequences are mere text data [my emphasis] (strings,
more formally) that can be opened with a text editor” (Nair, 2007, p.3).
The three-dimensional structure of each protein coded by DNA participates in many
integrated, biological processes such as metabolism, muscular contraction, digestion, energy
production and energy storage just to name a few (see Figure 3 below). These structures catalyze
thousands (if not hundreds of thousands) of different precise, teleofunctional reactions from
osmoregulation and protein construction to tissue development and food digestion.
278
Note that if all living things were not the product of some intentional design, then all living
things would appear to be teleologically-organized systems but they would not be teleologically
organized in a way that some future state of affairs could be obtained or that some "intended
target" was reached.
279
This is not meant to serve as a definition of information. Rather it is a definition of genetic
information. There can exist other kinds of information besides genetic information. In fact there
are a variety of different definitions of information. I will not attempt to provide a complete
definition of information here. Genetic information is instructive to our understanding of how
designed, living things might be said to "contain information". The sequences of nucleotides
found within a living thing's genome is the genetic information that enables it to be a
teleofunctional thing.
296
Figure 3. Metabolic diagram for tryptophan metabolism in yeast.
(From: http://www.bio.davidson.edu/courses/genomics/2002/cubre/project3.html)
Figure 3 above illustrates just one of the thousands of different metabolic processes that
take place in living organisms. All of these processes require precise genetic information to be
properly regulated. In all phases of life, proteins are at work maintaining and contributing to the
self-regulation of the organism itself. The strings of genetic “text data” are what dictate the
precise biochemical properties of all proteins. Thus, genetic information is quite necessary for an
organism's ability to carry out its teleofunctional processes, processes that it has a teleofunctional
interest in. Mossio et al. regard these kinds of metabolic systems as instances of complex,
functional systems that possess organisational differentiation. This kind of differentiation is a
hallmark feature of self-maintaining, teleofunctional systems. He writes,
“…DNA (among other things) acts as a template for the synthesis of the proteins,
which have to be continuously renewed due to their high rate of decay. In a word,
297
the cell possesses different parts [their emphasis], produced within and by the
system, that contribute differently to the maintenance of the system itself. In this
way functional attributions to each part are grounded. The understanding of
metabolic networks as organizationally closed and differentiated systems was put
forward several decades ago by pioneers such...Beyond the specific (and
sometimes simplistic) formulations of these authors, this approach is now
increasingly accepted and has been developed in various scientific fields,
including theoretical biology, biochemistry, and synthetic biology...” (Mossio et
al., 2009, p. 827).
Some have suggested that the information that is found in living things is a blueprint of
information for constructing an individual organism of a species. The information in DNA is a
blueprint for constructing living things.
As Peter Medawar writes,
"...in a professional vocabulary, 'information'
280
connotes structure or
orderliness, especially of the kind that makes possible the transmission of a
meaningful message or in the form of a communication that prescribes and
confers specificity upon any structure or performance. Thus, the information
structurally encoded in the huge molecule of deoxyribonucleic acid (DNA) is
such as to specify the development of the particular organism and no other, and
the wealth of information embodied in an architect's blueprint [my emphasis]
specifies some one building and no other." (Medawar, 1984, p. 79)
Rolston also draws an analogy between species and other information systems designed
by human beings. Living organisms are like teleofunctional artifacts produced on the basis of a
blueprint or template that contains information. For example, in addressing the importance of
protecting endangered species Rolston writes, “Destroying species is like tearing pages out of an
unread book, written in a language humans hardly know how to read, about the place where they
live” (Rolston, 1985, p. 718). A species, for Rolston, represents a unique form of information
and in particular endangered species contain information that is in danger of being lost forever.
In this case they are like “unread books” that are waiting to be read but highly susceptible to
280
Medawar is talking about genetic information here.
298
being lost or destroyed.
281
In short, a species’ way of life is as unique as the genetic information that “directs” and
“orchestrates” its life processes. Accordingly, Rolston adds,
“A species is a coherent, ongoing form of life expressed in organisms, encoded in
gene flow, and shaped by the environment…At this point, we can anticipate how
there can be duties to species.
282
What humans ought to respect are dynamic life
forms preserved in historical lines, vital informational processes [my emphasis]
that persist genetically over millions of years, overleaping short-lived
individuals…Though species are not moral agents a biological identity a kind of
value is here defended. The dignity resides in the dynamic form” (Rolston,
1985, p. 721-722).
So just as books and architectural blueprints are a form of information, a species can also
be a form of information.
But perhaps we shouldn’t take this particular metaphor too far. After all organisms and
their DNA cannot literally be read like books. But the metaphor is highly suggestive nonetheless
in that a species has a unique “story” to tell about an organism's own way of life
283
as unique as
281
In addition to the instrumental role that information plays in the life of the organism, Rolston
also thinks that the information content found in living organisms is good in itself independently
of whether human beings may happen to use that information or even know about it. He writes,
“It is not merely the loss of potential human information that is tragic, but the loss of biological
information, present independently of instrumental human uses of it…duties to a species are not
duties to a class or category, not to an aggregation of sentient creatures but to a lifeline [my
emphasis]” (Rolston, 1985, p. 723). Species for Rolston represent ‘lifelines’ each unique and
worthy of some protection out of their possession of unique information.
282
At this point I do not wish to argue that whole species do have value based on their
possession of teleofunctional interests. I only intend here to highlight the informational aspect of
whole species in that they can be referred to as “information systems”. The biocentric
individualist would disagree with the idea that individual living things don’t have value in
themselves but that only species do.
283
In a separate paper Rolston suggests that the chambered nautilus can be “read” in a certain
kind of way. He writes,
“A book can be read, but so too can a chambered nautilus. The microscopic ribs, typically thirty
in a chamber, seem to be secreted daily in relation to the lunar-tidal cycle, forming a logarithmic
spiral known as the Fibonacci series…Nautilus is an intelligible organic system quite as
impressive as the atomic submarine named for it, and the beauty of its pearly orange and white
299
its own genomic information. A species’ way of life is largely determined by its specific
metabolic requirements, physiological processes, behavioral strategies, and morphology. DNA
and genetic information are the central factors that determine these biological processes as well
as the organism’s final form.
284
A competent designer can certainly create "text data" in the form of genetic information
as a means of providing instructions on how the structures of a living, teleofunctional system are
to be produced and how those structures are to interact and coordinate with one another. Such a
designer can use her creativity to intentionally conceive of these precise instructions, write out
these instructions and then place them within a teleofunctional system so that it can make its own
teleofunctional structures and hence be capable of governing its own self-regulation.
It would be reasonable for beings like us to be rather astonished at the level of creative
genius and sophistication that it would take to produce such genetic information.
The amount of "text data" that it takes to produce the kinds of teleofunctional living
beings that observe in the actual world is quite high. It is above and beyond what human beings
are at present capable of designing. The information that human beings produce and which make
up present-day computer software programs obviously requires human ingenuity to produce. But
the information content of living organisms, if designed, would have taken a kind of ingenuity
above and beyond the level of ingenuity that human beings have.
For example, Bill Gates has said that "Biological information is the most important
information we can discover...Human DNA is like a computer program but far, far more
spiral vault is greater. We congratulate Leonardo Fibonacci for discovering that series, but why
not value the Nautilus for so exquisitely graphing it?” (Rolston, 1981, p. 122).
284
DNA doesn’t just specify the precise structure of all proteins, it also determines how an
organism will develop from a single, fertilized cell, to an embryo, to its adult form.
300
advanced than any software ever created” (Gates, 1996, p.228).
285
The genetic information
found in living organisms is analogous to a computer program made by human beings, but far
more advanced than any computer program currently conceived.
As I mentioned in chapter three synthetic biologists are already using their creativity to
intentionally write genetic instructions in the form of nucleotide sequences. In fact synthetic
biology is an active field of scientific inquiry at present. Many researchers in the field of
artificial life are getting closer to creating forms of life that can carry out their own internal, self-
regulation in the conditions in which they are found. In a footnote to their paper “Lessons from
Environmental Ethics about the Intrinsic Value of Synthetic Life” Mark Bedau and Ben Larson
point out,
“An explicit goal of much of bottom-up synthetic biology is to make protocells
that possess and can sustain an integrated and mutually supporting triad of
chemical processes, specifically the processes of programmed control,
metabolism, and compartmentation (Rasmussen et al. 2004; Rasmussen, Bedau,
McCaskill, and Packard 2009). Such mutually supporting chemical triads exhibit
many of the objective systemic properties characteristic of minimal chemical life,
such as the properties of autonomy, self-regulation, and evolution (Bedau 2010)”
285
Much has happened in both molecular genetics and computer technology since 1996, but I
maintain that it is still true that what we observe in DNA is in many ways like a digital code. For
a more recent discussion of the association between DNA and computer technology (September
20, 2015) see the news article discussing "DNA computers" by Marta Kwiatkowska entitled
"Organic ‘computers’ made of DNA could process data inside our bodies" from
http://thenextweb.com/insider/2015/09/20/organic-computers-made-of-dna-could-process-data-
inside-our-bodies/#gref. In it she writes,
"DNA molecules can be used to process information, using a bonding process between DNA
pairs known as hybridisation. This takes single strands of DNA as input and produces subsequent
strands of DNA through transformation as output...many DNA-based “circuits” have been
proposed that implement computational methods such as Boolean logic, arithmetical formulas,
and neural network computation. Called molecular programming, this approach applies concepts
and designs customary to computing to nano-scale approaches appropriate for working with
DNA...DNA molecules’ many appealing features include their size (2nm width),
programmability and high storage capacity much greater than their silicon counterparts. DNA
is also versatile, cheap and easy to synthesize, and computing with DNA requires much less
energy than electric powered silicon processors." (Kwiatkowska, 2015)
301
(Bedau and Larson, 2013, p. 84)
But if we were to think that the production of these artificial forms of life took human
ingenuity to produce, then it certainly seems reasonable to think that if the complex,
teleofunctional beings that we observe in the natural world were also designed, then those things
were produced by some kind of creative mind that is at least, if not more, creative than our own.
Creating a new artificial form of life from scratch would require inventing and contriving
thousands, if not tens of thousands, of new structures with novel functions capable of sustaining
it. It would require the generation of massive amounts of genetic, instructional information.
Artificial forms of life, just like their natural cousins, are teleofunctional systems of enormous
complexity and self-maintenance. But human beings have yet to produce an entirely new form of
life. Moreover the living things that are found in nature are far more advanced than any of the
synthetic forms of life that human beings have currently produced. As such it would be entirely
appropriate for us to think that if the non-sentient teleofunctional beings that we see in nature
were designed that that designer would have creative abilities that surpass our own, creative
abilities capable of generating billions of nucleotide "text data" needed for the making of the
teleofunctional structures of all non-sentient living things.
Synthetic biology, however, is not the only field of interest to those attempting to create
self-regulating teleofunctional beings. Scientists involved in robotics research are likewise trying
to apply the standards of teleofunctional systems to inorganic systems. That is, designing
sophisticated robots takes some creative genius are the part of us humans. For example, scientists
have recently developed a robot that is capable of adapting to sustained damage by making
adjustments in its own behavior. These robots can,
"create a detailed map of the space of high-performing behaviours. This map
represents the robot’s prior knowledge about what behaviours it can perform and
their value. When the robot is damaged, it uses this prior knowledge to guide a
302
trial-and-error learning algorithm that conducts intelligent experiments to rapidly
discover a behaviour that compensates for the damage." (Cully et al. 2015, p.
503).
Consider also Delancey’s comment on the possibility of future, designed machines that
could have their own teleofunctional capacities. He writes,
“I consider it acceptable that some future machine, with highly complex self-
regulating capacities, may have teleofunctions [my emphasis]. Furthermore, note
that the criterion that appears to rule out artifacts in the evolutionary etiological
account the ability to self-reproduce is one which future artifacts may have”
(Delancey, 2004, p. 184)
Hence, we could reasonably think that a possible, designed future machine (as an
inorganic system) or a possible, designed, future form of life (as an organic system) could exist
that also had teleofunctions. This would then mean that the teleofunctional interests of these
beings would have been brought about by our creative means.
Thus, it is reasonable for us to think that if all existing living things were designed, by
God or any other being, then they were designed with a level of creative genius that relative to
beings like us is rather astonishing. There would thus be a reason for beings like us not to harm
the non-sentient living things produced by design. Evidence of the designer's creativity would be
available in the form of the non-sentient living things that the designer had brought about, most
notably the sophisticated set of instructions found in their DNA. Non-sentient living things that
show evidence of their designer's great creativity are ones that beings like us have a reason not to
harm.
VII. Is Natural Selection Creative or Brilliant?
Some at this point might object to the notion that God, or any other rational agent, is the
only thing that can design things or be astonishingly creative. They might argue that natural
selection itself can also design things with its astonishing creativity. They might say, "Naturally-
303
selected teleofunctional interests are just as technologically sophisticated as designed ones are.
The process of natural selection is just as creative and innovative as God, or any other rational
agent, can be. It can produce everything from single cells all the way up to complex creatures
such as human beings. What could be more astonishingly creative than that?"
The biocentrist that advances this line of argumentation relies on the claim that natural
selection is capable of doing some rather creative things. Natural selection, they claim, is rather
clever and amazingly ingenious at building teleofunctional systems. For example, Daniel
Dennett has advocated this kind of understanding of the creative nature of Darwinian, natural
selection. He writes,
"There is simply no denying the breathtaking brilliance of the designs [my
emphasis] to be found in nature. Time and again, biologists baffled by some
apparently futile or maladroit bit of bad design in nature have eventually come to
see that they have underestimated the ingenuity, the sheer brilliance, the depth of
insight to be discovered in one of Mother Nature's creations. Francis Crick has
mischievously baptized this trend in the name of his colleague Leslie Orgel,
speaking of what he calls "Orgel's Second Rule: Evolution is cleverer than you
are." (Dennett, 1995, p. 74).
It might be urged that Dennett is too smart to suggest that natural selection itself has a
mind by using terms such as brilliant, ingenuity or clever to describe it. However, those that
happen to read Dennett's claim above might be misled into thinking that natural selection has a
mind even if that was not his intention. One of the definitions that Merriam-Webster has for the
term "brilliant" is that of being "very smart or clever". But it takes a mind to be "brilliant" in this
sense. So when Dennett uses of the term "brilliant" to describe natural selection it might be a
little difficult to discern just what he is actually up to. The same thing goes for the term
"ingenuity". People can be described as being "ingenious" in the sense of having "an unusual
aptitude for discovering, inventing, or contriving" things. But natural selection cannot be
described as "ingenious" in this same sense. Natural selection cannot discover, invent, or
304
contrive anything. Minds can. Natural selection cannot be "very smart or clever". Minds can.
When Dennett uses the term 'design' to describe what natural selection can do he is using
that word in a sense different than what I have defined the term "design" to mean. On my
definition something is designed if some agent "employed her creativity to intentionally bring it
about". But natural selection cannot "employ its creativity to intentionally bring something
about". Natural selection has no intention and so it cannot intend to bring anything about.
Tom Bethell points out a tension that exists between efforts to describe the process of
natural selection in teleological terms and the understanding that natural selection is actually a
completely blind process that involves no intentionality at all. He writes,
"The geneticist Theodosius Dobzhansky compared natural selection to "a human
activity such as performing or composing music." Sir Gavin de Beer described it
as a "master of ceremonies." George Gaylord Simpson at one point likened
selection to a poet, at another to a builder. Ernst Mayr, Lewontin's predecessor at
Harvard, compared selection to a sculptor. Sir Julian Huxley topped them all,
however, by comparing natural selection to William Shakespeare."
"Life on Earth, initially thought to constitute a sort of prima facie case for a
creator, was, as a result of Darwin's idea, envisioned merely as being the outcome
of a process and a process that was, according to Dobzhansky, "blind, mechanical,
automatic, impersonal," and, according to de Beer, was "wasteful, blind, and
blundering." But as soon as the criticisms were leveled at natural selection, the
"blind process" itself was compared to a poet, a composer, a sculptor,
Shakespeare - to the very notion of creativity that the idea of natural selection has
originally replaced. It is clear, I think, that there is something very, very wrong
with such an idea." (Bethell, 1976, p. 75).
Likewise, Denis Walsh has commented on the regrettable fact that many evolutionary
biologists continue to invoke teleological concepts in their explanations of biological phenomena
invoking natural selection all the while knowing that such concepts do not really belong within
the field of evolutionary biology itself. Teleology is a kind of "mistress" that evolutionary
biologists use for their purposes but whom they will not be seen in public with. Walsh writes,
"...even committed Darwinians continue to feel the Kantian tension between the
requirement of teleology and its unavailability. J.B.S. Haldane is said to have
305
quipped that teleology, to a biologist, is like a mistress. He can't be without her,
but he is ashamed to be seen with her in public. The claim is as apt as it is
inappropriate. Biology seems to be inexorably drawn to teleology, and yet its
credentials as a science in good standing appear to require that either it renounce
its dalliance with teleology or make a legitimate partner of it. Biology, it seems,
can't live with teleology, and it can't live without it." (Walsh, pp. 115-116)
The point I want to make here is that natural selection is not like the creative processes of
actual designers including God. Composers, poets and sculptors are all conscious agents that
make intentional plans to create the things that they do and they employ their creativity to
intentionally bring those things about. Natural selection, on the other hand, cannot employ its
creativity to intentionally bring anything about.
As such there cannot be anything truly "astonishing" about natural selection's cleverness.
There is no cleverness there to be astonished by. The living things that natural selection leaves
behind might astonish us. But we should not be astonished at its cleverness per se. Should
someone believe that naturally-selected living things are the result of a clever designer their
belief would not be justified. Natural selection, as Dobzhansky himself describes it, is "blind,
mechanical, automatic, impersonal". But blind, mechanical, automatic, and impersonal processes
are not really clever.
Evolution by natural selection tells us that there really are no overarching teleological
goals or purposes inherent in the processes that give rise to life. Butterfly wings are not made for
flight. They just happen to be structures capable of flight by a process that did not have flight as
an end goal for them in mind. Butterfly wings are useful structures in the spreading of butterfly
genes because flight is conducive to the spreading of butterfly genes but they have no functional
purposes as such. Matthew Wheeler underscores this when he writes, “By way of this
Darwinization, teleological concepts are underwritten historically, and are thereby made to
behave themselves in relation to a physics that has discarded teleology altogether” (Wheeler,
306
2005, p. 274).
If the non-sentient teleofunctional beings that we observe in the natural world were
designed by God, then he would, relative to beings like us, be a rather remarkable kind of
creator. He would be a rather clever designer. We can't attribute that kind of ability to nature
because nature itself is of course blind and has no mind.
VIII. The Argument from Awe, Wonder and Thankfulness to God
I have suggested that if God had designed the non-sentient teleofunctional beings that we
observe in the world then his level of creative ingenuity would be much greater than our
own.
286
Non-designed, non-sentient beings cannot be evidence of their designer's creativity
because they were not made with creativity at all. However, designed, non-sentient beings can be
evidence of their designer's creativity.
287
Right now I want to argue that there would be yet another reason for us to not harm all
non-sentient living beings that were brought about by the "theistic design etiology".
Consider these comments from Katie McShane.
"John Fowles and John Muir compare the awe, wonder, and reverence that nature
inspires to that which cathedrals and temples are meant to inspire [my emphasis].
Fowles even goes so far as to claim, “...I am certain that all sacred buildings, from
the greatest cathedral to the smallest chapel, and in all religions, derive from the
natural aura of certain woodland or forest settings. In them we stand among older,
larger, and infinitely other beings, remoter from us than the most bizarre other
286
Many theologians might suggest that God's intelligence is in a different league altogether
from our own.
287
This argument would also apply to a case of design in which the designer is not God. There
might exist some other non-theistic rational agent that could be the designer for non-sentient
living things that are either exactly like, or much like, the non-sentient living things that we
observe in the actual world. If those beings were designed, then the designer of those beings
would have, relative to beings like us, great creative ingenuity. Such a designer, however, would
not necessarily have to be God.
307
nonhuman forms of life: blind, immobile, speechless..., waiting...”
288
(McShane,
2007, p. 54)
If the trees that Fowles is referring to were designed by God in the manner described in
the theistic design etiology, then God also intended for those non-sentient living beings to inspire
beings like us with awe and wonder
289
. For the purposes of this argument, I will grant that not
all rational beings would be struck with a sense of awe and wonder at the non-sentient living
things that God designed in the theistic design etiology. Agents much more creative or powerful
than beings like us might not regard God's creative genius as particularly incredible or
remarkable. And so there would not, for them, necessarily be anything to be "wowed" about,
nothing to be in awe over. Rational agents are more or less inspired (or even not at all) by some
designed artifacts depending on various characteristics that they have. For beings like us,
however, it is hard to imagine how we could design such things as the non-sentient living beings
that exist in this world. And so if those things were designed and God intended for those things
to inspire us with a sense of awe and wonder, then it seems reasonable to think that we should be
thankful to God for designing such beings, beings that strike us as particularly awesome
examples of his great creative abilities. So the kind of awe or wonder that I am speaking about
here is an awe or wonder relative to beings like us and a kind of awe and wonder that we should
be thankful to God for inspiring in beings like us.
Human beings routinely design things for the purpose of inspiring other human beings
with a sense of awe, wonder or amazement. For instance, architects often attempt to inspire a
sense of awe or wonder in observers of their work. As Katie McShane points out in the above
288
McShane enters the following footnote here: John Fowles, The Tree (New York: Ecco Press,
1983), p. 58. See also John Muir, My First Summer in the Sierra (New York: Penguin Books,
1987), p. 49.
289
God might intend to reveal other things to us as well.
308
quote, some "sacred buildings, from the greatest cathedral to the smallest chapel" (structures
produced by human designers) were "meant to inspire" observers of their work. These structures
were not produced by some accident on the part of the architect that made them. The architect
intended for beings like us to be awed and amazed by that work.
290
Having feelings of admiration, awe, reverence, amazement and the like are not
uncommon emotions for beings like us to have when confronted with many of the non-sentient
living things that we encounter in the natural world. Things that we have these kinds of feelings
toward are things that we think shouldn't be harmed. But more to the point if these kinds of
things were intended by a designer to inspire beings like us with a sense of awe and wonder then
that provides are a reason for why we should be thankful to the designer of those things.
Observers of an architect's awe-inspiring "sacred building" have a reason to be thankful to the
architect for designing that structure.
Nonetheless, other environmentalists think that we can have an attitude of awe and
wonder toward the natural world but without having to resort to transcendent theism, without
thinking that those beings exist for the purpose of inspiring beings like us with a sense of awe
and wonder. They think that we can still have religious-type attitudes directed at the natural
world, attitudes of thankfulness toward it. For example, Ned Hettinger writes,
"Some will object to naturalistic spirituality because they think the religious
attitudes involved require an intentional or conscious being as an appropriate
object, something nature spirituality purports to do without. Talk of the earth as
our creator, or of being thankful to earth, would seem to treat the earth as a
conscious intentional being. If life on earth is a gift, it might be argued, this
requires a giver to whom we can be thankful. How can one revere and be devoted
to something that is not kindly or lovingly disposed towards us?
Some religious attitudes are, however, perfectly legitimate when directed at non-
intentional, non-conscious entities. That this spectacular planet and the natural
290
If so, then why not think that a designed woodland could not likewise have been brought by
God for the purpose of inspiring a sense of awe and wonder in beings like us too?
309
history that underlies it were unplanned and not created by an intelligent designer
does not lessen our ability or duty to love or defend it. Nor does it entail that we
should be any less thankful. It is true that such attitudes will differ in some of
their details when they are not directed at a personal, loving deity. Reverence for
earth is not likely to be the identical type of attitude as reverence for a personal
God. Love and thankfulness when directed at beings that cannot be aware of these
attitudes are different than are love and thankfulness directed at a person. In the
latter sense, one expects some kind of response; one expects that these attitudes
will make a difference to their object. The earth will not respond to those who
love it and are thankful for it any differently than to those who fear and denigrate
it. Nevertheless, for nature spirituality, these are appropriate attitudes and they
make a difference in the lives of those who are so disposed and in how they
respond to and treat the earth." (Hettinger, 2007, p. 72).
Hettinger seems to suggest that our thankfulness can be directed at the natural world even
if the natural world was not designed. But there is a problem for this view. The problem with this
claim rests, I think, on an equivocation of what it means to be thankful.
In some cases we often talk about being "thankful to" someone for something good that
they had done for us. For instance we might say something like, "I am thankful to Nathan for
preparing the meal today." But on other occasions we talk about being "thankful for" something
that has happened to us. In cases such as these we say things like, "I am thankful for the rain
today." or "I am thankful that there is less traffic today."
The kind of thankfulness that I am envisioning that a naturalistically-minded
environmentalist can have toward nature and that Hettinger is suggesting is that of thankfulness
for or thankfulness that, but not thankfulness to. Thankfulness for or thankfulness that is roughly
the same kind of thankfulness that one can have when a cloud brings rain. The cloud itself has no
aim or plans to produce rain. Nor does the cloud have an aim to please other beings by bringing
them rain. Clouds produce rain, but being thankful for the rain that they produce does not mean
that we should be thankful to them for producing the rain.
So we cannot, as Hettinger seems to suggest, be thankful to nature and as such nature is
not something that on that basis we should think deserves our thankfulness.
310
The naturalistically-minded biocentrist can be thankful for the non-sentient living beings
that she encounters in the natural world, but she cannot be thankful to nature for bringing those
beings about. Nature does not deserve our thankfulness even though some of the things that it
produces happen to be good for us. If the naturalistically-minded biocentrist happens to find
some utilitarian value in the non-sentient beings produced by natural selection, then she too
might be thankful for those utilitarian benefits. But she cannot be thankful to nature itself for
producing those things. To do so would be a category mistake. Nature can neither love others nor
creatively express any love to others and so we shouldn't think that we can be thankful to nature
for bringing about something on our behalf and hence think that nature deserves our
thankfulness.
Darwin's theory and modern reductionist science has done much to weaken the view that
nature is spirited or that it intentionally aims to be benevolent toward others, as such some
environmentalists believe that environmental ethics should be distanced from evolutionary
biology because of its implication that nature is not something that has benevolent intentions.
These environmentalists want to find some kind of accommodation between the reality of
Darwinism on the one hand and the need to keep nature "sacred" and viewed through a spiritual
or religious lens on the other.
As Lisa Sideris writes,
"...some environmental ethicists and theologians actively distance their enterprise
from evolutionary science, which is seen...to operate on the principles of the “old”
Baconian, despotic, mechanical model that dominates and controls nature.
Darwin’s theory is not seen as passing the ecological litmus test." (Sideris, 2007,
p. 64)
"Dawkins and others of his ilk (particularly sociobiologist E.O. Wilson and, at
times, philosopher Daniel Dennett) have undertaken the greatest reductionist
move
291
of all by rendering everything that is connoted by Darwinism - good,
291
The "reductionist move" that I think Sideris is talking about here is the move of explaining
311
bad, and indifferent - down to one rather narrow and dogmatic interpretation. This
move has undoubtedly given greater urgency to the search for alternatives [my
emphasis], for something that appears to be a legitimate middle ground between
biology and religious belief." (Sideris, 2007, p.74-75)
Evolutionary biology and its associated scientific reductionism has "disenchanted" the
natural world to such an extent that we don't have much of a reason to think that it has intentions
for anything.
Still there are some environmentalists who think that nature really is a kind of being that
does things on our behalf and to that extent deserves our thankfulness. They claim that there
might exist some religious way of "reenchanting" nature.
In the wake of the scientific reductionism of biological phenomena that Darwin's theory
has ushered in, these environmentalists insist on bringing an intentionalist interpretation back to
nature where nature is interpreted to have some kind of spiritedness or to be an extension of
God's being. The "desacrilization" of the natural world, as a result of Darwinism, has compelled
some biocentrists to rescue nature from such an interpretation through various "religious" means
of viewing nature as having some kind of spirit or intentionality. These individuals attempt to
"resacrilize" nature and view it as either spirited in some way or perhaps a part of God himself.
According to Lisa Sideris,
"A number of liberal Christian theologians, including Sallie McFague (1993),
Rosemary Radford Ruether (1992), Mark I. Wallace (2005), Leonardo Boff
(1997), Thomas Berry (1988)
292
, and Matthew Fox (1988), continue to carry
forward Hartshorne’s resacralization project (Zaleha 2008a: 58-77). The possible
all biological phenomena by recourse to random mutations and natural selection an explanation
that seems to leave no ground for religious belief.
292
Thomas Berry speaks of the compassionate nature of the universe when he writes, "...we
might consider our intimate and compassionate presence to the earth as originating ultimately in
the curvature of space, as it is presented in modern science. The entire earth community is
infolded in this compassionate curve whereby the universe bends inwardly in a manner
sufficiently closed to hold all things together and yet remains sufficiently open so that
compassion does not confine, but fosters, the creative process." (Berry, 1988, p. 20).
312
significance of this trend in liberal Christian thought is that if the planetary
environment is not merely God’s property, but actually part of God [my
emphasis], then environmental protection becomes even more important [my
emphasis] and urgent, because humanity becomes capable in this view of at least
partial deicide (Fox 1988: 17)." (Zaleha, 2015, p. 139)
"One antidote to an overly literal reading of Darwinism is a more literary one. A
secular version of enchanted Darwinism has recently been put forward by George
Levine. In Darwin Loves You: Darwinism and the Re-enchantment of the World,
Levinean English professorargues that critics of the Darwinian worldview
overlook the deeply Romantic view of nature that pervades Darwin’s writing. He
correctly notes that Darwin inhabited, and wrote about, a natural world densely
layered with value, wonder, even mystery, not a mechanical, inert, insensitive
one...It is, after all, Darwin’s theory, more so than any other scientific theory we
have, that connects us with a primordial past and with all other life forms, past
and present
293
...For those who choose to embrace it, theology plays an
explanatory role in “formaliz[ing] the intuitions of this depth that first erupt in
metaphor and religious symbol” (Haught 2003:102)...Interestingly, Levine, like
Haught, sometimes characterizes this misunderstanding as a too literal reading of
Darwin. Neo-Darwinists follow Darwin in letter, perhaps, but not in spirit. Yes,
Darwin attempted to explain the human speciesphysical, mental, and moral
evolutionexclusively from the side of natural history, as he characterizes his
project in The Descent of Man. And yes, Darwin believed that his theory would
shed light on other disciplines that seek to explain human behavior. Therein lies a
certain type of reductionism. But it is an oddly expansive kind of reductionism
that remains compatible with a sense of wonder, because the recognition of our
biological nature, our ties to lower animals and a distant evolutionary past, was, in
Darwin’s view, utterly ennobling..." (Sideris, 2007, p.76-78).
But Sideris also recognizes that efforts to "reenchant" the natural world are at odds with
what the science of natural selection has revealed to us about the natural world itself. She
recognizes that nature construed as a benevolent being is quite counterintuitive with the view that
all living things arose by the undirected, brutal process of natural selection. Natural selection
does not seek to express love or care for others. Teleofunctional interests, produced by natural
selection, like all other aspects of living things operate in the context of a blind process that itself
293
Siders inserts the following footnote here: "I confess to finding none of the vital warmth and
beauty and tragedy of the Darwinian worldview in the theories of the new physics. Quite
possibly, I do not understand them well enough, given that physicist Richard Feynman is reputed
to have said that no one understands quantum theory." (Sideris, 2007, p. 77)
313
has no concern for virtue at all or to inspire beings like us with a sense of awe and wonder. It's
only "concern" is with the replication of genes. She writes,
"...what Darwinism contributed to the study of nature was a clear counterpoint to
the impression of a benevolent communal interdependence in nature...With the
advent of Darwinism the suspicion that the natural world was the arena of a war
of all against all appeared to be confirmed." (Sideris, 2003, p. 27).
"Evolution [is] a fierce, competitive struggle for food, shelter, and mates. The
processes of evolution are described with such words as blind, random, and
purposeless. Natural selection, we are told, operates according to "chance"; in
fact, some recent evolutionists have begun to highlight the aspects of evolution
that reveal its deeper connection to chaos theory. The picture of nature is one that
is already as disturbed as it is disturbing..." (Sideris, 2003, p. 22).
In other words, if we observe the teleofunctional interests of naturally-selected living
things, we will not find the work of a benevolent being. Rather we will be witnessing the pursuit
of interests that take place within the brutal struggle for life. Darwin's theory has undermined the
claim that nature contains within itself some principle of benevolence or a spirit worthy of some
worship, a spirit that we should somehow be thankful to.
If this is true then how can we maintain the view that naturally-selected, and thus non-
designed, non-sentient teleofunctional beings are the kinds of things that we should be thankful
to nature for producing or that we have an obligation to nature to be thankful to it? Being
thankful for the existence of naturally-selected, non-sentient living things can be a reason for
why we should not harm those beings. Some might even argue that we have an obligation to be
thankful for the existence of all non-sentient living things regardless of their etiology. We can
have that obligation with regard to designed, non-sentient living things as we can for non-
designed, non-sentient living things. We do not, however, have an obligation to be thankful to
nature for producing non-sentient living things. As such that obligation cannot be among the
reasons available for why we should not harm naturally-selected, non-sentient living things.
While it may be true that Darwin himself expressed some feelings of wonder toward the
314
natural world, that does not mean that nature is something that we should be thankful to. And just
because Darwin had a romantic view of nature that does not mean that nature does things on our
behalf or that we should hold a romantic view of nature or that nature has some spirit that makes
it worthy of our thankfulness.
As I have been arguing here the best that an environmentalist can hope for is some form
of indirect moral standing for non-sentient teleofunctional beings. But projecting intentionality
onto naturally-selected, non-sentient, teleofunctional beings or seeking other ways to "reenchant"
nature through "metaphor and religious symbols" is simply a way putting an intentionalist gloss
on what otherwise is actually a mindless state of affairs. As such that state of affairs isn't
anything that we actually can be, let alone must be thankful to much less have an obligation to
be thankful to. If all non-sentient teleofunctional beings were not designed, then the
naturalistically-minded biocentrist cannot possibly appeal to the claim that we should be thankful
to nature for producing some non-sentient teleofunctional beings or that such thankfulness
provides a reason for why non-designed, non-sentient living things should not be harmed.
If, on the other hand, some of the non-sentient teleofunctional living things that we
observe in the world were intentionally brought about by a God who had aims or purposes to
produce those beings in order to inspire beings like us with a sense of awe and wonder, then we
do have an obligation to be thankful to God for bringing those beings about. God would deserve
our thankfulness in that case.
294
Note that if the theistic design etiology were true, then God's purpose would exist
294
If, on the other hand, God designed some non-sentient teleofunctional beings for the purpose
of giving human beings something to despise, then those designed beings would not be ones that
we have an obligation to be thankful to God for bringing about. Some might argue that we have
an obligation to despise those things, if our despising those things was God's purpose.
315
independently of our anthropomorphic tendencies to project intentionality onto nature or to
enchant it with some kind of spirit. Some biocentrists might find that implication favorable
because they think that our attitudes about the natural world should not be the deciding factor in
whether non-sentient teleofunctional beings have moral standing. They think that all living
things have moral standing independently of human interests. Although it is true that under the
"theistic design etiology" all living things would have moral standing that is independent of
human interests, the reason not to harm them would be dependent on God's purposes. If the
biocentrist is willing to accept that limitation, then all of God's designed non-sentient
teleofunctional beings would have indirect moral standing by recourse to his purposes for them.
But this purpose would exist independently of whether human beings are inspired with a sense of
awe and wonder by those things or not or whether human beings believe that they have an
obligation to God for bringing those beings about. Those things would exist for a divinely
appointed purpose whether human beings find moral value in God's purpose or even recognize
the existence of that purpose.
Since indirect moral standing is the only kind of moral standing that remains for non-
sentient teleofunctional beings, the biocentrist who embraces a non-design etiology for all non-
sentient teleofunctional beings cannot appeal to the claim that we should be, or have an
obligation to be, thankful to some agent for bringing those beings about. However, a biocentrist
that embraces a design etiology for all non-sentient teleofunctional beings can appeal to such a
claim. If non-sentient teleofunctional beings were brought about for the purpose of inspiring
beings like with a sense of awe and wonder then we should be thankful to the designer for the
non-sentient teleofunctional beings that she brought about. That thankfulness can further
motivate us to treat that designer's creation with care. The naturalistically-minded biocentrist,
316
however, cannot be motivated to protect non-sentient living things in that way.
IX. The Argument from Projects
If all non-sentient living beings were brought about by the theistic design etiology then
there would exist still other purposes that God has for the non-sentient teleofunctional beings
that he created, purposes as being a part of his project.
I want to make the "argument from projects" by considering an analogy between a case of
design that involves a human being's project and a case of design instead that involve a project of
God's.
Let us assume that there is a scientist that designs a sophisticated, teleofunctional robot
which contains tens of thousands of essential teleofunctional features that all work together for
its self-regulation and maintenance. In order for our scientist to bring about this kind of
teleofunctional system, he must carefully consider how each structure of the robot will interact
with every other structure so that its self-regulation is achieved. Our scientist must have some
technical savvy in doing this. He must have substantial knowledge of electronics, circuitry,
physics, chemistry, computers, etc. and be able to bring his knowledge of these subjects to bear
in bringing about his novel idea which is the design plan for the robot. The construction of this
robot relies on the satisfaction of numerous preference interests or desires of the scientist, a
desire to obtain knowledge of physics, a desire to become proficient in designing efficient
mechanical devices, a desire to successfully arrive at the local electronics store in order to
purchase a calculator, a desire to build each of the robot's part, a desire to put each part together,
a desire to get enough sleep so that the project might continue the next day, etc. We could
imagine a seemingly endless number of preference interests here.
317
To say that this scientist "has an interest" in this robot would be more than to simply say
that he "likes" it, or that he "has an interest in it functioning correctly". This robot is the
scientist's project. It is something that "counts as important or meaningful" in his life.
Should someone destroy this robot before completion for no morally compelling reason,
then that person would be harming the scientist without cause by frustrating the completion of
his project, a project that involves numerous desires and meaningful pursuits that the scientist
has. Many creative endeavors are ones in which the designer intends to bring about some
completed end goal. If a designer intends or desires to bring about some created object, then that
means that she has a preference interest in her designed object coming into existence. She prefers
for that designed object to exist. And so should someone destroy that designed object, without
some overriding consideration before it is completed, such an act would be in violation of her
preference for that designed object to exist.
But now let us suppose that this same scientist not only has an interest in designing the
robot but also an interest in its continued self-maintenance. When designers create things, they
usually not only intend for those things to be brought about, they also intend for those things to
have a certain kind of future. The scientist not only takes satisfaction in the completion of the
robot, she also takes satisfaction in observing its ability to routinely maintain itself in the midst
of varying environmental circumstances. Should someone destroy this robot after completion for
no morally compelling reason then we must also deal with the frustration of her interests in its
continued self-maintenance and in her interests in observing its successful self-maintenance. Her
interest in observing the self-maintenance in something that was designed by her includes among
other things her interest in her designed robot having a certain kind of future, her interest in some
future instances of its teleofunctional structures functioning properly, her interest in it not being
318
harmed by others in the future, etc.
The scientist's desires and preferences should be "taken into account" by others when it
comes to the question of how it should be treated. Evan Williams defines "taking a preference
into account" in the following way.
"I shall say that an agent “takes a preference into account,” if, finding himself
making a decision between an action which frustrates someone’s preference and
an action which fulfills it, he regards the preference as giving a pro tanto moral
reason for acting in the way that fulfills it." (Williams, 2016, p. 213)
In other words, to take this scientist's preference interests in her robot into account means
to regard her preference interests as giving a pro tanto moral reason for acting in way that does
not harm it. This means that the scientist's preference interests in her robot provide a reason for
why it should not be harmed that is not based on any intrinsic properties of the robot. The robot
is guaranteed then to have indirect moral standing.
It seems reasonable to suppose that a person's projects, plans or goals matter from an
ethical point of view. We can draw upon various ethical theories to support this basic claim.
Consider the following from Evan Williams. He writes,
"While I do not wish to endorse any particular theory of why preferences are
morally significant, I do think that it is worth observing that on many different
theoriese.g. contractarian theories which tell us to help others get what they
want in exchange for their help getting what we want, and universalization-type
theories which have us regard others’ desires as giving us reason to help them
because we wish that others would regard our desires as giving them reason to
help us
295
- what matters is how we want our own desires to be treated; and, of
course, by definition we care more about the fulfillment of our stronger desires
than about the fulfillment of our weaker desires, regardless of their respective
degrees of externality." (Williams, 2016, p. 220)
Here I will argue that human beings in some worlds in which there exists a designer of a
non-sentient teleofunctional being (what I call a "design world") would have reasons, in the form
295
Here Williams inserts the following footnote: e.g. Hare, Moral Thinking, pp. 87116.
319
of the designer's preference interests, not to harm that being than they would have not to harm
the same being that was brought about by a non-design etiology.
There could be numerous preference interests at stake in the proper treatment of some
designed objects. But these same preference interests would not be at stake regarding the proper
treatment of the same non-designed object.
Consider the following contrasting cases.
Case 1:
Seth, a lover of flowers, takes up a preference interest in a wild violet that is
growing in his backyard. Seth enjoys this plant and obtains much personal
satisfaction by observing how it is able to maintain its own self-maintenance
through the utilization of its own numerous, essential teleofunctional features.
Seth also brings it about that the plant is watered properly, fertilized properly and
protected from herbivorous predators. This plant was brought into existence by
the process of natural selection.
Case 2:
Seth, a lover of flowers, not only likes the violet that is growing in his backyard,
but he designed it. Seth used his skillful creativity to intentionally bring this
flower and its essential teleofunctional features about. This plant is a project of
Seth's in that Seth put his own creativity and skill into making it. Seth planted the
violet in his backyard where it grows amongst the other violets that were not
designed by anyone. Seth cares for all of these plants and brings it about that they
are watered properly, fertilized properly and protected from herbivorous
predators.
I want to argue that in case 2 there are certain reasons available for why the plant should
not be harmed that are not available for why any of the non-designed plants should not be
harmed. Rational agents have reasons, in the form of another person's preference interests as well
as their own, to refrain from harming a designed non-sentient living thing. These reasons are
available for why Seth's designed violet should not be harmed. But these reasons are not
available for why the violet in case 1 should not be harmed, a violet that Seth did not design.
In case 1 Seth did nothing to bring about the self-maintenance of the violet growing in his
320
backyard. He had a variety of preference interests associated with its self-maintenance,
preference interests associated with its well-being and the like. Furthermore, he took pains to
sustain the plant's well-being by making sure that it was watered properly, etc. But in case 2 Seth
is not only able to observe his designed violet and acquire the satisfaction of many interests in
the plant's well-being, he can also acquire satisfaction from knowing that this plant is capable of
surviving on its own because of his own creativity. Seth can, on the occasion of observing his
designed violet, remember the pains that it took for him to design it, remember the previous
successes of those efforts and take further satisfaction in knowing that those efforts were
successful in bringing about the self-maintaining capacities that he currently witnesses. On this
occasion Seth can enjoy still further satisfaction in knowing that his previous efforts to design
the violet were not only successful in the past but are currently successful and, if no harm is
brought to the plant, would probably be successful in the future.
296
In case 1 Seth is unable to
have these kinds of preference interests because he had nothing to do with bringing about any of
the essential teleofunctional features of the violet in his backyard. In case 1 Seth cannot have the
satisfaction of knowing what is it like to successfully design a violet, nor can he have the
satisfaction of observing the current success of any previous creative activity to bring it about. In
case 1 Seth did not bring about the self-maintaining capacity of the violet. He may have brought
about an enhancement or sustenance of the violet's self-maintenance by watering it, fertilizing it,
296
Some might argue that Seth's efforts (construed as "hard work" and the like) are not
analogous to God's efforts in the theistic design etiology because either God is so powerful that
he did not have to work hard to bring non-sentient living things about or that we simply cannot
know how much hard work it took, if any, for him to bring non-sentient living things about.
Some, however, think that there is a biblical reason for thinking that God expended considerable
effort or hard work in bringing about non-sentient living things by pointing to Genesis 2:2 which
points out the God "rested on the seventh day from all his work that he had done" (ESV
translation).
321
etc., but he did not design the violet's ability to maintain itself in the first place. In case 1 Seth
can admire the ability of the violet to maintain itself, but he cannot take credit for that capacity.
Other valuers cannot congratulate him for bringing the flower about. In case 1 Seth also cannot
have the satisfaction of knowing that his act of bringing about of the violet's self-maintaining
capacities was successful.
If the plant, and all other non-sentient living things were brought about by the theistic
design etiology then there would be other preferences at stake, preferences that cannot be at stake
if those living things were not designed it. These preference interest would serve as further
reasons for why those beings should not be harmed.
An act of killing a plant designed by God would be more than just an act of killing it and
an act of disregarding God's preferences in its well-being. It would, in addition to those things, be
an act of disregarding God's preferences in enjoying the success of his own project, an action
which would violate all of the preference interests involved in his designing of the plant and in
his desire to be satisfied by his own creative efforts. It is not simply that the plant was important
to God. After all even a non-designed plant can be important to God. It is that this plant would be
more important to God for reasons pertaining to his preferences associated with own
creativity.
297
297
An additional argument for how a design etiology could provide a reason not to harm non-
sentient teleofunctional beings is the argument that designed, non-sentient living beings are some
designer's intellectual property. The owner has certain rights and privileges associated with the
proper use and distribution of her intellectual property. These rights and privileges provide a
reason why her intellectual property should not be harmed.
Since destroying another person's property is prima facie wrong, and since a designed, non-
sentient living thing is instance of someone's property, then destroying that property is prima
facie wrong. To destroy or degrade an organism that is a designed work, would prima facie be
wrong precisely because it is a designer's property, in this case her intellectual property.
As Ricardo Pozzo writes,
"Corpus mysticum, opus mysticum, propriété incorporelle, proprietà letteraria, geistiges
322
X. Conclusion
In this dissertation I have argued that all living things have interests regardless of their
etiology. How a living, teleofunctional being was brought about is irrelevant to whether it has
interests. But etiology can make a difference to whether a non-sentient living being has indirect
Eigentum. All these terms mean intellectual property, the existence of which is intuitively clear
because of the unbreakable bond that ties the work to its creator. The book belongs to [my
emphasis] whomever has written it, the picture to whomever has painted it, the sculpture to
whomever has sculpted it; and this independently from the number of exemplars of the book or
of the work of art in their passages from owner to owner. The initial bond cannot change and it
ensures the author authority on the work." (Pozzo, 2006).
The proposition that all living things are a designer's intellectual property has one rather
interesting implication regarding gene patents and genes as intellectual property. The question of
who can obtain a patent on a gene or some other biological product, or even if anyone has the
right to such a patent, is a hotly contested issue in environmental ethics. Many environmentalists
argue that only the indigenous peoples of the land that cultivate a naturally-occurring living
organism have exclusive ownership rights to the use of that organism and its genetic resources.
They claim that it is unjust for any outside entity, be it a corporation, a visiting research scientist
or another country, to attempt to patent a biological product or harvesting procedure from the
land that these native people have cultivated and invested with their own capital. This amounts
to what environmentalists call "biopiracy" or the using of the knowledge of indigenous peoples
pertaining to nature but without fairly compensating those indigenous peoples for that
knowledge.
Many naturally-occurring biological resources including genes and the products of genes are
very useful to human beings.
For example the neem tree, Azadirachta indica, produces a wide array of biopesticide molecules
that can be used to control many pests and pathogens of crop plants. One such compound,
azadirachtin, has been isolated from the oil of neem tree seeds and is a genetic product known to
control some arthropod pests (Veitch et al., 2007). Snake venom also contains an array of
biologically useful proteins and enzymes that scientists believe can treat blood clots, strokes,
cancers and neurological disorders. These are but two examples of the many beneficial uses of
genes and proteins from plant and animal sources.
Since the gene products of the neem tree are beneficial, the ownership of them as intellectual
property might seem quite appealing.
But if the genes of all living things are the intellectual property of their designer, it would be
improper to claim that the genetic information found within any of those living things is the
intellectual property of any other rational agent. In that case, the genes of the neem tree, if
designed, would not belong to native the people that had cultivated or harvested that tree. Nor
would they belong to any outside research scientist or corporation hoping to profit from its
genes. These genes would be the intellectual property of the neem tree's designer.
323
moral standing, the only kind of moral standing available for them.
First, designed non-sentient living thing are guaranteed to have indirect moral standing
by recourse to the fact that they were brought about by an intrinsically good activity, creativity.
Being produced by an intrinsically good or virtuous activity provides a reason for a non-sentient
living thing should not be harmed. Non-designed, non-sentient living things cannot be
guaranteed to have indirect moral standing. And since they were not brought about by an
intrinsically good activity then being brought about by an intrinsically good activity cannot be
one of the reasons available for why those beings should not be harmed.
Second, designed non-sentient living things are also guaranteed to have indirect moral
standing by recourse to the fact that they have teleofunctional structures that have teleofunctional
purposes. Their teleofunctional structures were intended by their designer to have the functions
that they do. A designer's intention for a structure to have a functional purpose is another reason
why a designed, non-sentient living thing should not be harmed. To damage a designed
teleofunctional structure is to cause it to malfunction. Causing these structures to malfunction
goes against their designer's intention. Hence, designed non-sentient living things are guaranteed
to have indirect moral standing by recourse to the existence of their teleofunctional purposes.
But non-designed, teleofunctional structures cannot malfunction. They might be caused
to function differently, but not to malfunction per se. As such having the ability to malfunction
cannot be among the reasons available for why one should not harm a non-designed, non-
sentient living things or its teleofunctional structures.
A design etiology is capable of explaining how there could be normative functional
purposes for all non-sentient living things. This etiology at least gives the biocentrist a way out
of the quandary of explaining how non-sentient living things could have normative, functional
324
purposes.
This means that the biocentrist is faced with either accepting some non-design etiology
and not having the ability to explain the existence of functional purposes for living things or
accepting a design etiology and having the ability to explain the existence of functional purposes
for living things.
If she accepts a design etiological view for the existence of all non-sentient living things
then she will be also be able to claim that all living things have indirect moral standing
independently of human preferences or desires. If she accept a non-design etiological view for
the existence of all non-sentient living things then she must be willing to live with the claim that
those beings will not be guaranteed to have indirect moral standing.
I, however, maintain that if indirect moral standing is the only kind of standing left non-
sentient living things, then if those beings were brought about by the theistic design etiology she
would have further reasons not to harm those beings, reasons that would exist independently of
her preference interests or desires.
If God had designed all non-sentient living thing for the purpose of inspiring beings like
us with a sense of awe and wonder then all valuers would have another reason not to harm those
beings. Our obligation to be thankful to God for bringing those beings about would be a reason
not to harm those beings. But since we cannot have an obligation to be thankful to nature for
bringing about any non-sentient living beings then having that obligation cannot be reason for
why non-designed, non-sentient living things should not be harmed.
Furthermore, if all non-sentient living things were God's project then God would have
numerous preference interests in how those beings were brought about and in how those beings
are treated over time. These preference interests provide further reasons for why non-sentient
325
living beings produced by the theistic design etiology should not be harmed. But since no such
preference interests are involved in bringing about a non-designed, non-sentient living thing, the
biocentrist cannot appeal to those preference interests as providing a reason for why non-
designed, non-sentient living things should not be harmed.
If all non-sentient living beings and their teleofunctional interests were brought about by
the theistic design etiology then there would be some purpose for the existence of all non-
sentient living things not associated merely with genetic replication. They would have been
brought about for a variety of morally-good purposes, purposes that were given to them by their
designer and not based on whether rational agents such as ourselves happen to value them or
impute our purposes to them. One such purpose could be to exhibit or illustrate their designer's
remarkable creativity, to inspire beings like us with a sense of awe and wonder or to simply
please God himself.
326
REFERENCES CITED
Aikin, Scott F. (2014). "Environmental Ethics and the Expanding Problem of Evil." Think, 13:
33-39.
Agar, Nicholas (1997). "Biocentrism and the Concept of Life." Ethics, 108: 147-168.
Alberts, B., D. Bray, J. Lewis, M. Raff, K. Roberts and J.D. Watson (1989). The Molecular
Biology of the Cell, second edition. New York, NY: Garland.
Amundson, Ron and George V. Lauder (1998). “Function without purpose: The uses of causal
role function in evolutionary biology.” Biology and Philosophy, 9: 443-469.
Anderson-Gold, Sharon (2003). “Objective Value in Environmental Ethics: Towards a
Reconstituted Anthropocentric Ethic.” Social Philosophy Today, 18: 111-124.
Arbor, J.L. (1986). "Animal chauvinism, plant-regarding ethics and the torture of trees."
Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 64: 335-339.
Aristotle (1941). Physics, Translated by R.P. Hardie and R.K. Gaye. In The Basic Works of
Aristotle, edited by Richard McKeon (New York, NY: Random House): 213-394.
Attfield, Robin (1981). "The Good of Trees." Journal of Value Inquiry, 15: 35-54.
Attfield, Robin (2012) “Biocentrism and Artificial Life.” Environmental Values, 21: 83-94.
Ayala, Francisco (2007). “Darwin’s greatest discovery: Design without designer.Proceedings
of the National Academy of Sciences, 104: 8567-8573.
Baertschi, Bernard (2012). "The Moral Status of Artificial Life." Environmental Values, 21: 5-
18.
Basl, John (2012). "Nothing Good Will Come from Giving Up on Aetiological Accounts of
Teleology." Philosophy & Technology, 25: 543-546.
Baxter, W. (1974). People or penguins: The case for optimum pollution. New York: Columbia
University Press.
Bedau, M. A. (2010). "An Aristotelian account of minimal chemical life." Astrobiology, 10: 1-
10.
Bedau, M. and E. Parke (2009). The Ethics of Protocells: Moral and Social Implications of
Creating Life in the Laboratory. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.
Bedau, Mark and Ben Larson (2013). “Lessons from Environmental Ethics about the Intrinsic
Value of Synthetic Life.” In Synthetic Biology and Morality: Artificial Life and the Bounds of
Nature, edited by G. E. Kaebnick (Cumberland, RI: MIT Press): 69-87.
Berry, Thomas Mary (1988). The Dream of the Earth. San Francisco: Sierra Club Books.
327
Berry, Wendell (1993). Sex, Economy, Freedom & Community: Eight Essays. New York, NY:
Pantheon Books.
Bethell, Tom (1976). "Darwin's Mistake." Harper's Magazine, 252 (1509): 70-75.
Binns, Corey (2006). "Genes: The Instruction Manuals for Life", Live Science, from:
http://www.livescience.com/10486-genes-instruction-manuals-life.html.
Boff, Leonardo (1997). Cry of the Earth, Cry of the Poor, Ecology and Justice. Maryknoll, NY:
Orbis Books.
Boorse, Christopher (1976). “Wright on Functions.” The Philosophical Review, LXXXV: 70-86.
Boyle, Robert (1666). “The Origin of Form and Qualities.” in The Works of the Honourable
Robert Boyle. London. t. 3.
Bridge, A. P., R. W. Elwood and J. T. A. Dick (2000). "Imperfect assessment and limited
information preclude optimal strategies in malemale fights in the orb-weaving spider
Metellina mengei." Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, Series B, 267, 273279.
Burge, Tyler (2010). Origins of Objectivity. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Cahen, Harley (1988). "Against the Moral Considerability of Ecosystems." Environmental
Ethics, 10: 195-216.
Callicott, J. Baird (1980). “Animal Liberation: A Triangular Affair.” In In Defense of The Land
Ethic: Essays in Environmental Philosophy, by J. Baird Callicott (Albany, N.Y.: State
University of New York Press): 15-38.
Callicott, J, Baird (1992). "Rolston on Intrinsic Value: A Deconstruction." Environmental Ethics,
14: 129-143.
Callicott, J. Baird (1995). “Intrinsic Value in Nature: a Metaethical Analysis.”
http://ejap.louisiana.edu/EJAP/1995.spring/callicott.1995.spring.html
Carafo, Philip (2001). “For a Grounded Conception of Wilderness and More Wilderness on the
Ground”, Ethics and the Environment, 6:1-17
Christensen, Wayne and Mark H. Bickhard (2014). “Function as Design versus Function as
Usefulness.” from: http://www.lehigh.edu/~mhb0/funcdesignfuncuseful.pdf.
Clements, Colleen D. (1976). “Stasis: The Unnatural Value.” Ethics, 86: 136-144.
Clewell, Timothy J. (2011). The Promise and Limits of Natural Normativity in a Neo-
Aristotelian Virtue Ethics. Master's Thesis, Georgia State University, Department of
Philosophy. From:
http://scholarworks.gsu.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1081&context=philosophy_theses
328
Council of Europe (1998). “Additional Protocol to the Convention for the Protection of Human
Rights and Dignity of the Human Being with regard to the Application of Biology and
Medicine, on the Prohibition of Cloning Human Beings.” Paris, December 1
st
, 1998. From:
http://conventions.coe.int/Treaty/en/Treaties/Html/168.htm
Coyne, Jerry (2012). “What’s the problem with unguided evolution?” From:
https://whyevolutionistrue.wordpress.com/2012/07/17/whats-the-problem-with-unguided-
evolution/ (Accessed April 15, 2014).
Crick, Francis (1958). “On Protein Synthesis.” Symposium for the Society of Experimental
Biology, 12:138-63.
Crisp, Roger (1998). "Animal liberation is not an environmental ethic: A response to Dale
Jamieson." Environmental Values, 7: 476-478.
Cropley, Arthur J. (1999). “Creativity and cognition: Producing effective novelty”. Roeper
Review. 21: 253-261.
Cully, Antoine, et al. (2015). “Robots that can adapt like animals.” Nature, 521: 503-507.
Dabrock, P. (2009). “Playing god? Synthetic biology as a theological and ethical challenge.”
Systems and Synthetic Biology, 3: 47-54.
Davidson, Donald (1987). “Knowing One’s Own Mind.” Proceedings and Addresses of the
American Philosophical Association, 60: 441-458.
Davies, Paul Sheldon (2000). “The Nature of Natural Norms: Why Selected Functions are
Systemic Capacity Functions.” Noûs, 34: 85-107.
Davies, Paul Sheldon (2001). Norms of Nature: Naturalism and the Nature of Functions.
Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Davies, Paul Sheldon (2009). Subjects of the World: Darwin’s Rhetoric and The Study of Agency
in Nature. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Dawkins, Richard (1986). The Blind Watchmaker. New York: Norton Press.
Dawkins, Richard (1999). The Selfish Gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
de Vriend, H. (2006). Constructing Life. Early social reflections on the emerging field of
synthetic biology. The Hague, the Netherlands: Rathenau Institute. Working Document 97.
Delancey, Craig (2004). "Teleofunctions and Oncomice." Environmental Ethics, 26: 171-188.
Delancey, Craig (2006). “Ontology and Teleofunctions: A Defense and Revision of the
Systematic Account of Teleological Explanation.” Synthese, 150: 69-98.
329
Dennett, Daniel (1995). Darwin’s Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life. New
York, NY: Simon and Schuster.
Dewey, John (2009). "The Influence of Darwinism on Philosophy." In Philosophy after Darwin:
Classic and Contemporary Readings, edited by Michael Ruse (Princeton: Princeton
University Press), 55-62.
Dyke, James G. and Iain S. Weaver (2013). “The Emergence of Environmental Homeostasis in
Complex Ecosystems.” PLoS Computational Biology, 9: 1-9.
Elliot, Robert (1982). “Faking Nature.” Inquiry, 25: 81-93.
Elwood, Robert W. and Mirjam Appel (2009). "Pain experience in hermit crabs?" Animal
Behaviour, 77: 1243-1246.
ETC Group (2007). Extreme Genetic Engineering: An Introduction to Synthetic Biology. From:
http://www.etcgroup.org/sites/www.etcgroup.org/files/publication/602/01/synbioreportweb.p
df
Findlay, Roger D. (2004). “Mycorrhizal fungi and their multifunctional roles.” Mycologist, 18:
91-96.
Fisher Jun, F. M. and R. C. Sanborn (1962). “Production of Insect Juvenile Hormone by the
Microsporidian Parasite Nosema.” Nature, 194: 1193.
FitzPatrick, William J. (2000.) Teleology and the Norms of Nature, New York, N.Y.: Garland
Publishing Inc.
Fodor, Jerry (2007). "Why Pigs Don't Have Wings", London Review of Books, 29: 19-22.
Fodor, Jerry (2008a). "Against Darwinism", Mind & Language, 23: 1-24.
Fodor, Jerry (2008b). "Against Darwinism" From: http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/images/personal-jerry-
fodor/fodor_against_darwinism.pdf
Foot, Philippa (2001). Natural Goodness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Fox, Matthew (1988). The Coming of the Cosmic Christ: The Healing of Mother Earth and the
Birth of a Global Renaissance. San Francisco: HarperSanFrancisco.
Gates, Bill (1996). The Road Ahead. Revised Ed., London: Penguin.
Gaut, Berys (2014). “Mixed Motivations: Creativity as a Virtue.” Royal Institute of Philosophy
Supplement, 75: 183-202.
Gibson, Daniel G., John I. Glass, Carole Lartigue, Vladimir N. Noskov, et al. (2010). “Creation
of a Bacterial Cell Controlled by a Chemically Synmthesized Genome.” Science, 329: 52-56.
330
Goodpaster, Kenneth E. (1980). "On Stopping at Everything: A Reply to W. M. Hunt."
Environmental Ethics, 2: 281-284.
Gould, Stephen J. (1989). Wonderful Life. New York, N.Y.: W.W. Norton and Company, Inc.
Gutmann, Amy (2011). “The Ethics of Synthetic Biology: Guiding Principles for Emerging
Technologies.” Hastings Center Report, 41: 17-22. From: http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/hcr/
summary/v041/41.4.gutmann.html.
Hack, M.A., J.D. Thompson and D.M. Fernandes. (1997). "Fighting of males of the autumn
spider, Metellina segmentata: the effects of relative body size, prior residency and female
value on contest outcome and duration." Ethology, 103: 488-498.
Hagen, Edward H (2005). “Controversial issues in evolutionary psychology”. In The Handbook
of Evolutionary Psychology, edited by D. Buss (Hoboken, NJ: Wiley): 145-176.
Hansson, Bengt, Staffan Bensch and Dennis Hasselquist (1997). “Infanticide in Great Reed
Warblers: Secondary Females Destroy Eggs of Primary Females.” Animal Behavior, 54: 297-
304.
Hargrove, Eugene. (1989). The Foundations of Environmental Ethics. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.:
Prentice Hall.
Hargrove, Eugene (1992) “Weak Anthropocentric Intrinsic Value”, Monist, 75:183-207.
Haught, John (2003). Deeper than Darwin. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Hettinger, Ned (2007). "Religion in Rolston's Environmental Ethics." In Nature, Value, Duty:
Life on Earth with Holmes Rolston, III, edited by C.J. Preston and W. Ouderkirk (Dordrecht:
Springer), 63-76.
Hettinger, Ned and Bill Throop (1999). “Refocusing ecocentrism: De-emphasizing Stability and
defending wildness.” Environmental Ethics 21: 3-21.
Holm, Sune (2012). “Biological Interests, Normative Functions, and Synthetic Biology.”
Philosophy and Technology, 25: 525-541.
Holm, Sune (2013). "The Capacities, Interests, and Organisation of Artifactual Organisms." In
Designer Biology: The Ethics of Intensively Engineering Biological and Ecological Systems,
edited by R.L. Sandler and J. Basl (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield): 233-252.
Hull, David L. (1976). “Are species really individuals?” Systematic Biology, 25: 174-191.
Hume, David (1799). Essays on suicide and the immortality of the soul. By the late David Hume,
Esq. With remarks by the editor. To which are added, two letters on suicide, from Rousseau's
Eloisa.: A New Edition: Basil. Eighteenth Century Collections Online.
Hursthouse, Rosalind (1999). On Virtue Ethics. New York, N.Y.: Oxford University Press.
331
Jablonka, Eva and Marion J. Lamb (2005). Evolution in Four Dimensions: Genetic, Epigenetic,
Behavioral, and Symbolic Variation in the History of Life. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Jamieson, Dale. (1998). "Animal liberation is an environmental ethics." Environmental Values,
7: 4157.
Jamieson, Dale. (2008). Ethics and the Environment: An Introduction. Cambridge, New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Joppa L.N., et al. (2011a). "How many species of flowering plants are there?" Proceedings of the
Royal Society of London B, 278: 554559.
Joppa L.N., et al. (2011b). "Biodiversity hotspots house most undiscovered plant species."
Proceeding of the Royal Society of London B, 108: 13171-13176.
Kant, Immanuel (1790). Critique of Judgement, Second Edition, Revised, Trans. by J.H.
Bernard, 1914. London: Macmillan and Co., Limited.
Katz, Eric (1992). “The Call of the Wild: The Struggle Against Domination and the
Technological Fix of Nature.” Environmental Ethics, 14: 265-273.
Katz, Eric (2003). “Is There a Place for Animals in the Moral Consideration of Nature?” In
Environmental Ethics: An Anthology, edited by A. Light and H. Rolston III (Malden, Mass.:
Blackwell Publishing): 85-94.
Kitcher, Philip (1993). Function and Design. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, XVIII: 379-97.
Kricher, John (2009). The Balance of Nature: Ecology's Enduring Myth. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
Korsgard, Christine M. (1983). “Two Distinctions in Goodness.” The Philosophical Review, 92:
169-195.
Küppers, Bernd-Olaf (1990). Information and the Origin of Life. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Kwiatkowska, Marta (2015). "Organic ‘computers’ made of DNA could process data inside our
bodies." From: http://thenextweb.com/insider/2015/09/20/organic-computers-made-of-dna-
could-process-data-inside-our-bodies/#gref.
Kwiatkowska, Teresa (2008). “The Natural: So Ambiguous A Word.” Dialogue and
Universalism, 18: 87-99.
Lee, Keekok (1999). The Natural and the Artificial: The Implications of Deep Science and Deep
Technology f or Environmental Philosophy. New York, N.Y.: Lexington Books.
Leopold, Aldo (2003). "The Land Ethic." In Environmental Ethics: An Anthology, edited by A.
Light and H. L. Rolston III (Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing): 38-46.
332
Leopold, Aldo (2013). A Sand County Almanac, edited by Curt Meine. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Light, Andrew (2002). "Contemporary Environmental Ethics from Metaethics to Public
Philosophy." Metaphilosophy, 33: 426-449.
Link, Hans-Jürgen (2013). “Playing God and the Intrinsic Value of Life: Moral Problems for
Synthetic Biology.” Science and Engineering Ethics, 19: 435-448.
Lo, Y.S. (2006). "Making and Finding Values in Nature: From a Humean Point of View."
Inquiry, 49: 123-147.
Lott, Micah (2012). “Have Elephant Seals Refuted Aristotle? Nature, Function, and Moral
Goodness.” Journal of Moral Philosophy, 9: 353-375.
Lunger, Frank (2000). “Anthropocentrism vs. Cosmocentrism: Groping Towards a Paradigm
Shift”, The Newsletter of the Philosophical Discussion Group of British Mensa, 102,
(http://theotodman.com/c10208.htm)
Lupisella, M.L. (2010). “Cosmocentrism and the Active Search for Extraterrestrial Intelligence”,
Astrobiology Science Conference 2010: Evolution and Life: Surviving Catastrophes and
Extremes on Earth and Beyond, held April 26-20, 2010 in League City, Texas. LPI
Contribution No. 1538, p.5597.
Marrieta, Jr. Don E. (1979) "The Interrelationship of Ecological Science and Environmental
Ethics." Environmental Ethics, 1: 195-207.
Martin, Mike W. (2007). Albert Schweitzer's Reverence for Life: Ethical Idealism and Self-
Realization. Burlington, VT: Ashgate Publishing Company.
May, Robert M. and R.J.H. Beverton (1990). "How Many Species? [and Discussion]."
Philosophical Transactions: Biological Sciences, 330: 293-3-4.
Mayr, Ernst (2001). What Evolution Is. New York, NY: Basic Books.
McDonald, Hugh P. (2003). “Environmental Ethics and Intrinsic Value.” In John Dewey and
Environmental Ethics, SUNY Series in Environmental Philosophy and Ethics, (Albany, NY:
State University or New York Press) 1-56.
McFague, Sallie (1993). The Body of God: An Ecological Theology. Minneapolis: Fortress Press.
McKibben, Bill (2006). The End of Nature. New York: Random House.
McShane, Katie (2007). "Why Environmental Ethics Shouldn't Give Up on Intrinsic Value."
Environmental Ethics, 29: 43-61.
Mill, John Stuart (1885). “On Nature.” in Three Essays on Religion, 3
rd
edition. London:
Longman, Green & Co.
333
Millikan, Ruth (1984). Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories, Cambridge, MA:
The MIT Press.
Millikan, Ruth (1989). “In Defense of Proper Functions.” Philosophy of Science, 56: 288-302.
Millikan, Ruth (1991). "Speaking up for Darwin." In Meaning in Mind: Fodor and His Critics,
edited by Barry M. Loewer and Georges Rey (Cambridge, MA: Blackwell Publishing) 151-
164.
Millikan, Ruth (2002). Biofunctions: Two Paradigms, Available online at:
http://philosophy.uconn.edu/wp-content/uploads/sites/365/2014/02/Biofunctions-Two-
Paradigms.pdf
Millikan, Ruth (2004). Varieties of Meaning: The 2002 Jean Nicod Lectures, Cambridge, MA:
The MIT Press.
Moore, G.E. (1948) Principia Ethica. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.
Morgan, D. N. (1953). “Creativity today”. Journal of Aesthetics, 12: 1-24.
Morito, Bruce (2003) “Intrinsic Value: A Modern Albatross for the Ecological Approach.”
Environmental Values, 12: 317-336
Mossio, Matteo, Cristian Saborido and Alvaro Moreno. (2009). “An Organizational Account of
Biological Functions.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60: 813-841.
Muraca, Barbara. (2011). “The Map of Moral Significance: A New Axiological Matrix for
Environmental Ethics”, Environmental Values, 20: 375-396.
Naess,Arne (1973). “The Shallow and the Deep Ecology Movement”, Inquiry, 16:95-100.
Naess, Arne (1984). "A Defense of the Deep Ecology Movement", Environmental Ethics, 6:
265-270.
Nair, Achuthsankar S (2007). “Computational Biology & Bioinformatics: A Gentle Overview”,
Communications of the Computer Society of India, January: 1-13.
Nagel, Ernest (1977). “Teleology Revisited: Goal-Directed Processes in Biology.” The Journal
of Philosophy, 74: 261-279.
Neander, Karen (1991). "Functions as Selected Effects: The Conceptual Analyst's Defense."
Philosophy of Science, 58: 168-184.
Nelson, Gabe, Aaron Saunders, Neil Neville, Ben Swilling, Joe Bondaryk, Devin Billings, Chris
Lee, Robert Playter and Marc Raibert. (2012). “PETMAN: A Humanoid Robot for Testing
Chemical Protective Clothing.”, Journal of the Robotics Society of Japan, 30 (4): 372-377.
2012.
334
Newman, S.W. (1999). “The Medial Extended Amygdala in Male Reproductive Behavior: A
Node in the Mammalian Social Behavior Network.” Annals of the New York Academy of
Sciences, 877: 242-257.
Nicholson, Daniel J. (2013). "Organisms ≠ Machines." Studies in History and Philosophy of
Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 44: 669-678.
Nissen, Lowell (1997). Teleological Language in the Life Sciences, New York, NY: Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers Inc.
Nolt, John (2009). “The Move from Is to Good in Environmental Ethics.” Environmental Ethics,
31: 135-154.
Norton, Bryan (ed). (1986). The Preservation of Species: The Value of Biological Diversity.
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Norton, Bryan (1987) Why Preserve Natural Variety? Princeton: Princeton University Press
O'Brien, Lilian (2015). Philosophy of Action. New York, NT: Palgrave Macmillan.
Odenbaugh, Jay (2015). “Nothing in Ethics Makes Sense Except in the Light of Evolution?
Natural Goodness and Evolutionary Biology.” Synthese: Published Online February 20,
2015.
Okumu, Joseph and K.U. Leuven (2007). "Personal identity, projects, and morality in Bernard
Williams' earlier writings." Ethical Perspectives: Journal of the European Ethics Network,
14: 13-28.
O’Neill, Jonathan (1992). “The Varieties of Intrinsic Value.” The Monist, 75: 119-37.
Ott Paul (2010). "Value as Practice and the Practice of Value: Dewey’s Value Theory for
Environmental Ethics." Environmental Ethics, 32: 285-304.
Palmer, Clare (2003). “An Overview of Environmental Ethics.” in Environmental Ethics: An
Anthology. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.
Patten, Bernard C. and Eugene P. Odum (1981). "The Cybernetic Nature of Ecosystems." The
American Naturalist, 118: 886-895.
Petersen, John E. (2001). “Adding artificial feedback to a simple aquatic ecosystem: the
cybernetic nature of ecosystems revisited.” Oikos, 94: 533-547.
Pinchot, G. (1914). The training of a forester. Philadelphia, PA: J.B. Lippincott Company.
Plantinga, Alvin (1993). Warrant and Proper Function. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Pope, Carl (1998). "Reaching Beyond Ourselves: It's Time to Recognize Our Allies in the Faith
Community." Sierra (November/December): 14-15.
335
Pozzo, Ricardo (2006). "Immanuel Kant on Intellectual Property." Trans/Form/Ação, 29: 11-18.
Prenter, John, Robert W. Elwood and Ian Montgomery. (2003). "Mate-guarding, competition and
variation in size in male orb-web spiders, Metellina segmentata: a field experiment." Animal
Behaviour, 66: 1053-1058.
Preston, Christopher (2008). "Synthetic Biology: Drawing a Line in Darwin's Sand."
Environmental Values, 17: 23-39.
Preston, Christopher (2013). "Synthetic Bacteria, Natural Processes, and Intrinsic Value." In
Basic Bioethics: Synthetic Biology and Morality: Artificial Life and Bounds of Nature, edited
by G. E. Kaebnick and T. H. Murray (Cumberland, RI: The MIT Press): 107-128.
Rasmussen, S., et al. (2004). "Transitions from nonliving to living matter." Science, 303: 963-
965.
Rasmussen, S., M.A. Bedau, J.M. McCaskill, and N.H. Packard (2009). "Roadmap to
protocells." In Protocells: Bridging Nonliving and Living Matter (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press): 71-100.
Regan, Tom (1981). "The Nature and Possibility of an Environmental Ethic." Environmental
Ethics, 3: 19-34.
Rifkin, Lawrence (2013). “Is the Meaning of Your Life to Make Babies?” Scientific American
Blogs, http://blogs.scientificamerican.com/guest-blog/is-the-meaning-of-your-life-to-make-
babies/
Rolston, Holmes III (1979). "Can and Ought We to Follow Nature?" Environmental Ethics, 1: 7-
30.
Rolston, Holmes III (1981). “Values in Nature.” Environmental Ethics, 3: 113-128.
Rolston, Holmes III (1982). "Are Values in Nature Subjective or Objective?" Environmental
Ethics, 4: 125-151.
Rolston, Holmes III (1988). Environmental Ethics. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Rolston, Holmes III (2003). “Value in Nature and the Nature of Value.” In Environmental
Ethics: An Anthology, edited by A. Light and H. L. Rolston III (Malden, MA: Blackwell
Publishing): 143-153.
Rolston, Holmes III (2009). "Converging versus Reconstituting Environmental Ethics" In Nature
in Common? Environmental Ethics and the Contested Foundations of Environmental Policy,
edited by Ben A. Minteer (Philadelphia: Temple University Press): 97-117.
Rosenberg, Jay F. (2007). "Comments on Ruth Garrett Millikan's Varieties of Meaning."
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LXXV: 692-700.
336
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques (2007). Emilie. Teddington: The Echo Library.
Ruether, Rosemary Radford (1992). Gaia & God: An Ecofeminist Theology of Earth Healing.
San Franciso: HarperSanFransisco.
Salvi, Maurizio (2001). "Transforming Animal Species: the Case of 'Oncomouse'." Science and
Engineering Ethics, 7: 15-28.
Samuelson, Lars (2010). "Reasons and Values in Environmental Ethics." Environmental Values,
19: 517-535.
Sandler, Ronald (2012a). “Is artefactualness a value-relevant property of living things?”
Synthese, 185: 89-102.
Sandler, Ronald (2012b). “Intrinsic Value, Ecology, and Conservation.” Nature Education
Knowledge, 3: 4.
Sandler, Ronald (2012c). “Artifactual species.” In The Ethics of Species (New York: Cambridge
University Press).
Schmidt, Markus, Malcolm Dando and Anna Deplazes (2011) "Dealing with the Outer Reaches
of Synthetic Biology Biosafety, Biosecurity, IPR, and Ethical Challenges of Chemical
Synthetic Biology" in Chemical Synthetic Biology, edited by P. L. Luisi and C. Chiarabelli
(UK: John Wiley & Sons): 321-342.
Schmidt, Markus, et al., (2008). “SYNBIOSAFE e-conference: online community discussion on
the societal aspects of synthetic biology.” Systems and Synthetic Biology, 2: 7-17.
Schweitzer, Albert. (1969). Reverence for Life. Broadway, NY: Irvington Publishers.
Shellenberger, Michael and Ted Nordhaus (2004). “The Death of Environmentalism: Global
Warming Politics in a Post-Environmental World.” From: http://thebreakthrough.org
/archive/the_death_of_environmentalism
Sideris, Lisa (2003). Environmental Ethics, Ecological Theology and Natural Selection. New
York, NY: Columbia University Press.
Sideris, Lisa (2007). "Evolving Environmentalism: The Role of Ecotheology in
Creation/Evolution Controversies." Worldviews, 11: 58-82.
Simmons, Scott (2013). "How to Evolve a Good of Your Own." In Designer Biology: The Ethics
of Intensively Engineering Biological and Ecological Systems (Blue Summit Ridge, PA:
Lexington Books).
Simpson, Robert (2015). "Intrinsic Value and Intrinsic Valuation." Unpublished manuscript.
Singer, P. (1975). Animal liberation. New York: The New York Review.
Smith, Jane A. (1991). "A Question of Pain in Invertebrates." The ILAR Journal, 33: 25-31.
Smith, John Maynard (1999). “The Concept of Information in Biology.” Philosophy of Science,
67: 177-194.
337
Sober, Elliot (1980). “Evolution, Population Thinking, and Essentialism.” Philosophy of Science,
47: 350-383.
Sober, Elliot (1984). The Nature of Selection: Evolutionary Theory in Philosophical Focus,
Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Sober, Elliot (1986). “Philosophical Problems for Environmentalism.” In The Preservation of
Species: The Value of Biological Diversity, edited by Bryan G. Norton (Princeton: Princeton
University Press): 173-194.
Specter, Michael (2009). "A Life of Its Own: Where will synthetic biology lead us", Annals of
Science, September 28. The New Yorker. From: http://www.newyorker.com/magazine
/2009/09/28/a-life-of-its-own
Sperry, R.W. (1974), "Science and the Problem of Values", Zygon, 9: 7-21.
Steadman, Ian (2014). “Is a worm's brain in a Lego robot alive, or just creepy?”, The
NewStatesman, Future Proof blog, From: http://www.newstatesman.com/future-
proof/2014/12/worms-brain-lego-robot-alive-or-just-creepy.
Sterba, J. (1998). “A Biocentrist Strikes Back”, Environmental Ethics, 20:361-376.
Sterba, J. (2001). Three challenges to ethics: Environmentalism, feminism, and multiculturalism.
Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Sterelny, Kim and Paul E. Griffiths (1999). Sex and Death: An Introduction to Philosophy of
Biology, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Swinburne, Richard. (1993). The Coherence of Theism, Revised Edition. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Sylvan, Richard (2003). “Is There a Need for a New, an Environmental, Ethic?” In
Environmental Ethics: An Anthology, edited by A. Light and H. Rolston III (Malden, Mass.:
Blackwell Publishing): 47-52.
Tabaczek, Mariusz (2014). "An Aristotelian Account of Evolution and the Contemporary
Philosophy of Biology." in Proceedings of the Conferences on the Dialogue between Science
and Theology, Volume 1. (Ovidius University of Constanta, Romania: Research Center on
the Dialogue between Science and Theology): 57-69.
Taylor, Paul (1986). Respect for Nature: A Theory of Environmental Ethics. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
Tennyson, Alfred (1900). In Memoriam A.H.H. London: The Bankside Press.
Trojan, Przemysław (1983). Ecosystem homeostasis (The Hague: Dr. W. Junk Publishers).
338
Uhl, Christopher (2013). Developing Ecological Consciousness: The End of Separation, second
edition. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
van den Belt, Henk (2009). “Playing God in Frankenstein’s Footsteps: Synthetic Biology and the
Meaning of Life.” Nanoethics, 3: 257-268.
Varner, Gary (1990). “Biological Functions and Biological Interests.” The Southern Journal of
Philosophy, XXVIII: 251-270.
Varner, Gary (1998). In Nature's Interests? New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Veitch Gemma E., et al. (2007). "Synthesis of Azadirachtin: A Long but Successful Journey."
Angewandte Chemie International Edition, 46: 7629-7632.
Vesterby, Vincent (2008). “Are Ecosystems Alive?” In The Proceedings of the 52nd Annual
Meeting of the ISSS.
Viegas, Jennifer (2013). "Blobfish Wins Ugliest Animal Mascot Contest: Photos."
Discovery.com. From: http://news.discovery.com/animals/endangered-species/ugly-animals-
need-saving- 130618.htm
Vogel, Steven (2002). "Environmental Philosophy after the End of Nature." Environmental
Ethics, 24: 23-39.
Wallace, Mark I. (2005). Finding God in the Singing River: Christianity, Spirit, Nature.
Minneapolis: Fortress Press.
Walsh, Denis (2008). "Teleology" in The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Biology, edited by
Michael Ruse (New York: Oxford University Press): 113-137.
Weston, Anthony (1987). “Forms of Gaian Ethics.” Environmental Ethics, 9:217-230.
Weston, Anthony (1996) “Beyond Intrinsic Value: Pragmatism in Environmental Ethics.” In
Environmental Pragmatism, edited by Andrew Light and Eric Katz (London: Routledge):
285-306.
Wheeler, Michael (2005). “Under Darwin’s Cosh? Neo-Aristotelian Thinking in Environmental
Ethics.” In Philosophy, Biology and Life: Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, edited
by Anthony O’Hear (Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press).
White Jr., Lynn (1967). "The Historical Roots of Our Ecologic Crisis." Science, 155: 1203-1207.
Williams, Evan (2016). "Preferences' Significance Does Not Depend on Their Content." Journal
of Moral Philosophy, 13: 211-234.
Wright, Larry (1976). Teleological Explanations: An Etiological Analysis of Goals and
Function. Berkeley, Calif: University of California Press.
339
Yong, Ed (2009). "The suicide plasterers aphids that repair their homes with their own bodily
fluids." Not Exactly Rocket Science blog (Ed Yong, 02/25/09) From:
http://blogs.discovermagazine.com/notrocketscience/2009/02/25/the-suicide-plasterers-
aphids-that-repair-their-homes-with-their-own-bodily-fluids/#.U-pubvldWSo
Zagzebski, Linda (1996). Virtues of the Mind: An Inquiry into the Nature of Virtue and the
Ethical Foundations of Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zaleha, Bernard Daley. (2008a). "'The Paradise We Ever Need': An Investigation into
Pantheism's Sacred Geography in the Writings of Edward Abbey, Thomas Berry, and
Matthew Fox, and a Preliminary Survey of Signs of Emerging Pantheism in American
Culture." (MA diss., University of Florida).
Zaleha, Bernard Daley (2008b). "Review of John Hart's "Sacramental Commons: Christian
Ecological Ethics." Environmental Ethics, 30: 217-220.
Zaleha, Bernard Daley (2013). "'Our Only Heaven': Nature Veneration, Quest Religion, and Pro-
Environment Behavior." Journal for the Study of Religion, Nature and Culture, 7: 131-153.
340
VITAE
David Lewis Rice III
AOS: Ethics, Environmental Ethics, Philosophy of Biology
AOC: Philosophy of Science, Philosophy of Religion
EDUCATION:
University of Arkansas, PhD, Philosophy, ABD
Dissertation: "Biocentrism in Environmental Ethics: Questions of Inherent Worth, Etiology
and Teleofunctional Interests." Dissertation Director: Dr. Richard Lee.
University of Mississippi, M.A., Philosophy, 2009
Master’s Paper: “Where Biocentrism meets Darwin: Intrinsic Value, Teleology and Moral
Considerability.”
Delta State University, M.S.N.S., Biology, 1999
Master’s thesis: “Determinants of Diel Territorial Activity in Male Hackberry Butterflies,
Asterocampa celtis, (Lepidoptera: Nymphalidae) at a Perch Site used in Mate Location.”
Delta State University, B.S., Biology, 1994
TEACHING EXPERIENCE:
Instructor/Adjunct Lecturer: Introduction to Ethics, Introduction to Philosophy, Logic, Human
Nature and the Meaning of Life, Reasoning and Discovery, Ethics and the Professions
University of Arkansas, Department of Philosophy (January 2010 present)
Adjunct Instructor: Introduction to Philosophy, Critical Thinking
Northwest Arkansas Community College (January 2015 present)
Teaching Assistant: Introduction to Religion, History of Philosophy, Logic
University of Mississippi, Department of Philosophy and Religion (January 2005 December
2008)
Laboratory Instructor: Invertebrate Zoology, Introductory Biology, Physiology
University of Mississippi, Department of Biology (June 2002 May 2004)
Laboratory Teaching Assistant: Zoology, Introductory Biology
Delta State University, Department of Biological Sciences (August 1996 May 1997)
Graduate Teaching Assistant: Marine Science
University of Southern Mississippi, Gulf Coast Research Laboratory (Summer 1996)
341
PRESENTATIONS:
The Epistemic Significance of Scientific Disagreement: The Hierarchical Model and the Equal
Weight View
2011 Three Rivers Philosophy Conference “Science, Knowledge, and Democracy”, University
of South Carolina, Columbia, SC, April 1-3, 2011.
An Assessment and Criticism of the Fourth Item of Paul Taylor’s ‘Biocentric Outlook’
The 47th Meeting of the North Texas Philosophical Association, University of North Texas,
Denton, TX, April 3-5, 2014.
Commentary on Borland and Hillman’s “The Nature of Philosophy is…What Exactly?”
Mid-South Philosophy Conference, April 21-22, 2014.
PUBLICATION:
Porter, M. D. and Rice, D. 2001. “Application of Geographic Resource Analysis Support System
(GRASS) in analyses of dissolved oxygen declination in commercial catfish ponds.”
Proceedings of the First International Symposium on Geographic Information Systems (GIS) in
Fishery Science, 295-301.
OTHER ACHIEVEMENTS:
Beta Beta Beta (National Biological Honors Society)
Twice-recipient of the R.L. Caylor Science Scholarship and Award (1993/1995)
Dean’s List: 1993/1994
American Philosophical Association
EMPLOYMENT HISTORY:
Summer Research Assistant in Nitrogen and Air Pollutant Emissions from Poultry
Operations
U.S. Department of Agriculture, Poultry Production and Products Safety Research, University of
Arkansas, Dr. Philip Moore (May 2015 July 2015)
Summer Research Assistant in Entomology
University of Arkansas, Department of Entomology, Dr. Don Steinkraus (May 2012 July 2013)
Biological Aid in Surface Water Chemistry
U.S. Dept. of Agriculture, National Sedimentation Lab, Oxford, MS (May 2009 - December
2009)
342
Medicinal Plant Garden Assistant
University of Mississippi, National Center for Natural Products Research (January 2008 -
December 2008)
Sport Fish Restoration and Invasive Species Coordinator
Gulf States Marine Fisheries Commission (May 2007 - December 2007)
Coastal Resource Management Specialist
Mississippi Department of Marine Resources (September 2006 April 2007)
Environmental Scientist II, Nonpoint Source Pollution
Mississippi Department of Environmental Quality, Nonpoint Source Section (May 2000 May
2002)
Student Conservation Association Intern in Endangered Species and Coastal Wetlands
AmeriCorps, Marine Corps Base Camp Lejeune, Environmental Management Department (June
1999 May 2000)
Summer Agricultural Research Assistant in Entomology and Weed Control
US Dept. of Agriculture/Miss Ag. and Forestry Experiment Station (1995 2003)
REFERENCES:
Richard Lee, Associate Professor
Department of Philosophy
University of Arkansas
(479)-575-5826
Neil A. Manson, Associate Professor
Department of Philosophy and Religion
University of Mississippi
(662)-915-6713
Ed Minar, Professor and Chair
Department of Philosophy
University of Arkansas
(479) 575-8712
Tom Senor, Professor
Department of Philosophy
University of Arkansas
(479)-575-5827