BYU Law Review BYU Law Review
Volume 1998 Issue 4 Article 2
11-1-1998
The Second Amendment in the Nineteenth Century The Second Amendment in the Nineteenth Century
David B. Kopel
Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.law.byu.edu/lawreview
Part of the Military, War, and Peace Commons, and the Second Amendment Commons
Recommended Citation Recommended Citation
David B. Kopel,
The Second Amendment in the Nineteenth Century
, 1998 BYU L. Rev. 1359 (1998).
Available at: https://digitalcommons.law.byu.edu/lawreview/vol1998/iss4/2
This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Brigham Young University Law Review at BYU Law
Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in BYU Law Review by an authorized editor of BYU Law Digital
Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected].
* Adju nct Professor of Law, New York Univer sit y La w Sch ool, 1998; Resea rch
Director, Independence Inst itute, Golden, Colorado. J.D., 1985, University of Michigan;
B.A. in Histor y 1982, Brown Univers ity. I would like to thank Jim Win chest er, J .D.,
for outstanding research assistance. Valuable aid wa s also pr ovided by Pa ul
Blackman, David Caplan, Clayton Cramer , Brannon Denning, Robert Dowlut, Mark
Fuller, Richard Gr iffith s, S tephen Ha lbr ook, Scott Ha tt ru p, Ch ar les B. Ka tes, Don
Kates, Jerry & Dolores Kopel, Nelson Lund, Joseph Olson, Daniel Polsby, Glenn
Harlan Reyn olds, Doug Spitt ler , William Van Alst yne, Eugene Volokh, and the
Cincinnati Law Lib ra ry Associa tion .
1359
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
The Second Amendment in the Nineteenth
Century
David B. Kopel
*
I. INTRODUCTION .................................1362
II. THE EARLY GIANTS: TUCKER, RAWLE, AND STORY ......1370
A. S t. George Tucker: The Am erican Blackstone ......1370
1. T ucker’s backgrou nd ......................1370
2. The central role of Tucker’s American Blackstone1371
3. Tucker on the right to arms in Bla ckst one .....1373
4. T ucker’s appen dix on the Am erican Con stitution 1375
5. T ucker’s exposition of the Second Am endment ..1377
B. Houston v. Moore ...........................1379
C. William Rawle ..............................1384
D. Joseph Story ...............................1388
1. The Second Amendment in Story’s Commentaries1389
2. The Second Amendment in Story’s Familiar
Exposition ...............................1393
3. The federal militia powers in Story’s
Commentaries ...........................1396
E. Other Pre-1850 Sources ......................1397
1. Henry St. George Tucker ...................1397
2. B enjam in Oliver ..........................1399
3. James Bayard ...........................1400
4. Francis Lieber ...........................1402
5. Elliot’s Debates ..........................1404
6. Webster’s Dictionary .......................1404
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1360 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
III. STATE CONSTITUTIONS AND CASE LAW .............1409
A. State Constitutions ..........................1409
B. S tate Case Law .............................1415
1. T ennessee ...............................1416
2. Arkansas ................................1422
3. Georgia .................................1425
4. Louisiana ...............................1427
5. North Carolina ...........................1428
6. Texas ...................................1429
7. Illinois .................................1431
8. West Virginia ............................1432
9. State case law sum mary ...................1432
IV. ANTEBELLUM YEARS AND THE CIVIL W AR ...........1433
A. Dr ed Scot t .................................1433
B. The Hum an Rights Advocates ..................1435
1. L ysan der S poon er .........................1436
2. Joel Tiffany .............................1440
C. Bloody Kansas ..............................1441
D. The Civil War ..............................1444
V. RECONSTRUCTION AND LABOR UNREST ..............1447
A. Congress, Civil Rights, and the Fourteenth
Amendment ................................1447
1. T he Freedmens B ureau ....................1447
2. Southern representation in Congress ..........1449
3. Civil Rights Bill ..........................1450
4. Anti-KKK Act ............................1451
5. Fourteenth Am endm ent ....................1451
6. Civil Rights Act of 1875 ....................1453
7. S um m ary of Con gressional policy ............1453
B. Cruishank .................................1454
C. Presser ....................................1459
VI. COMMENTARY FROM THE LATE 19TH CENTURY: COOLEY
AND OTHERS ..................................1461
A. Thomas Cooley ..............................1461
1. A Treatise on Constitutional Limitations ......1462
2. The General Principles of Constitutional Law ..1464
B. The Lesser Com mentators .....................1468
1. Joel Tiffany .............................1469
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1361
2. Timothy Farrar ..........................1470
3. George W . Pasch al ........................1472
4. J oel Bishop ..............................1474
5. J ohn Norton Pom eroy .....................1476
6. Oliver Wen dell Holm es, J r., an d J am es Kent ...1479
7. Editions of Bla ckst one .....................1482
8. T heoph ilus Parsons .......................1483
9. A foreigner’s vantage: von Holst .............1484
10. John Hare ..............................1485
11. George Ticknor Curtis ....................1486
12. John C. Ordronaux ......................1488
13. Sam uel Freeman Miller and J.C. Bancroft Davis1490
14. Henry Cam pbell Black ...................1493
15. George S. Boutwell .......................1494
16. J am es S chouler .........................1496
17. Home schooling .........................1498
18. Civics manuals for youth ..................1498
19. John Randolph Tucker ...................1501
C. L aw Review Articles .........................1503
D. Summary of the Late Nineteenth Century
Commentators ..............................1505
VII. FIN-DE-S IÈCLE AND BEYOND .....................1506
A. The Supreme Court ..........................1506
1. Miller v. Texas ...........................1506
2. Robertson v. Baldwin ......................1509
B. The Collective Right Establishes a Footing:
Salina v. Blaksley ...........................1510
C. Late Twentieth Century Commentators ..........1512
1. Some thoughts about David Williams .........1512
2. Some thoughts about Carl Bogus .............1515
D. Firearms Policy for the Twenty-first Century ......1530
1. W ho is protected by th e Second Am endm ent? ...1530
2. Does the Second Amendment limit the states? ..1530
3. What kind of “arms”? ......................1531
4. Can th e carrying of w eapons be controlled? ....1535
5. R epealing or ignoring the Second Am endment ..1536
6. T he First Am endm ent .....................1538
7. The illegality of most federal gun laws ........1541
VIII. CONCLUSION ................................1544
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1362 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
1. See SENATE SUBCOMMITTEE ON THE CONSTITUTION OF THE COMMITTEE ON THE
JUDICIARY, 97TH CONG., 2D SESS., THE RIGHT TO KEEP AND BEAR ARMS (Comm. Print
1982) [hereinafter SENATE SUBCOMM. ON THE CONST.]; Robert J. Cottrol, In trod uct ion
to 1 GUN CONTROL AND THE CONSTITUTION: SOURCES AND EXPLORATIONS ON THE
SECOND AMENDMENT at ix (Robert J . Cottrol ed., 1993); Robert J . Cottr ol & Ra ymond
T. Diam ond, Pu blic S afet y an d t he R ight to Bear Arms, in THE BILL OF RIGHTS IN
MODERN AMERICA: AFTER 200 YEARS 72 (David J. Bodenhamer & James W. Ely, J r.,
eds., 1993); Robert J. Cottrol, Second Amendment , in THE OXFORD COMPANION TO THE
SUPREME C OURT OF THE UNITED STATES 763 (Ker mit L . H all et al. ed s., 199 2);
CLAYTON CRAMER, FOR THE DEFENSE OF THEMSELVES AND THE STATE at xv (199 4); 4
ENCYCLOPEDIA OF THE AMERICAN CONSTITUTION 1639-40 (Leonar d W. Levy et a l. eds.,
1986); STEPHEN HALBROOK, A RIGHT TO BEAR ARMS: STATE AND FEDERAL BILLS OF
RIGHTS AND CONSTITUTIONAL GUARANTEES (1989) [hereinafter HALBROOK, RIGHT TO
BEAR ARMS ]; STEPHEN P. HALBROOK, THAT EVER Y MAN BE ARMED: THE EVOLUTION OF
A CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT (1984) [hereinafter HALBROOK, THAT EVER Y MAN BE ARMED];
I. INTRODUCTION
Despite the animosity that sometimes divides advocates and
opponents of gun control, they share one important characteris-
tic: almost unanimously, they are constitutional originalists.
Persons who believe that the Second Amendment guarantees a
right of individual Americans to own and carry guns claim that
the original intent of the Second Amendment was for an indi-
vidual right. Conver sely, person s who believe t hat the Second
Amendment only guarantees the right of state governments to
have National Guard (militia) units argue that the original
inten t su pports t heir own position.
Both sides of the debate cite mater ial from the period when
the Constitution and the Bill of Rights were ratified and de-
bated. Both sides also cite materials from E nglish legal history.
But su rpr isingly, neit her side has paid significa nt attention to
the interpretive community which first applied the Second
Amendment: the United States in the nineteenth century.
During that century, the Second Amendment’s right to keep
and bear arms was discussed in many legal treatises, in
Congressional debates, in six Suprem e Court cases, in
numerous state court cases, and in other legal materials. Yet,
except for two of the Supreme Court cases, the history of the
Second Amendment in the nineteenth century has been only
lightly touched by legal scholar ship.
In modern legal scholarsh ip, the “St anda rd Model” of the
Second Amendment maintains that individual Americans have
a right to own guns.
1
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1363
Edward F. Leddy, Guns an d G un Conrtol, in READERS COMPANION TO AME RICAN
HISTORY 477-78 (Eric Foner & John A. Garraty eds., 1991); LEONARD W. LEVY,
ORIGI NAL INTENT AND THE FRAMERS CONSTITUTION 341 (1988); J OYCE LEE MALCOLM,
TO KEEP AND BEAR ARMS: THE ORIGINS OF AN ANGLO-AMERICAN RIGHT (1994); Akhil
Reed Amar , The B ill of R igh ts an d t he F ourteen th Am end ment , 101 YALE L.J . 1193
(1992) [hereina fter Amar , Fou rteent h A m end m ent]; Akhil Reed Amar , Th e Bil l of
Rights as a Consti tution , 100 YALE L.J. 1131, 1164 (1991); Ra nd y E. Barn et t & Don
B. Kates, Under Fire: The N ew Consen sus on th e S econd Am end m ent , 45 EMORY L.J.
1139, 1141 (1996); Bernard J . Bordenet , The Right to Possess Arms: The Intent of the
Framers of th e S econd Am end m ent , 21 U. WEST L.A. L. REV. 1, 28 (1990); David I.
Caplan, The R igh t of t he I nd ivi du al t o Bea r A rm s: A R ecent J ud icial T ren d, 1982
DET. C.L. REV. 789, 790; Da vid I. Caplan , The Right to Have Arms and Use Deadly
Force Under the Second and Third Amendments, 2.1 J. ON FIREARMS & PUB. POLY
165 (1990); Robert J. Cottrol & Raymond T. Diamond, The Second Amendment:
Toward an Afro-Americanist Recon sid erat ion, 80 GEO. L.J . 309 (1991); Bra nn on P .
Denn ing, Can th e S im ple Cite Be Trus ted?: Low er Cou rt I nt erpretat ions of United
States v. Miller and the Second Amendment, 26 CUMB. L. REV. 961 (1995-96)
[hereinafter Denning, Sim ple Cite]; Bran non P. Denning, Gun Shy: The Second
Amendment as an “Und erenforced Constitutional N orm”, 21 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POLY
719 (1998) [hereina fter Denning, Gun Shy]; Anthon y J. Dennis, Clearing the Smoke
From th e Ri ght to Bear Arms and the Second Amendment, 29 AKRON L. REV. 57
(1995); Robert Dowlut , Federal and State Constitutional Guarantees to Arms, 15 U.
DAYTON L. REV. 59 (1989) [hereinafter Dowlut , Guarantees to Arms]; Robert Dowlut ,
The Current Relevancy of Keeping and Bearing Arms, 15 U. BALT. L.F. 32 (198 4);
Robert Dowlut, The R igh t to Arm s: Does t he C ons tit ut ion or the P redilect ion of J ud ges
Reign?, 36 OKLA. L. REV. 65 (1983) [her eina fter Dowlut , The Right to Arms]; Robert
Dowlut, The Right to Keep and Bear Arms: A Righ t to Self-Defense Against Crimin als
and Despots, 8 STAN. L. & POLY RE V. 25 (1997); Richar d E. Ga rdin er, To Preserve
Liberty—A Look at the Right to Keep and Bear Arms, 10 N. KY. L. REV. 63 (1982 );
Alan M. Gottlieb, Gun Ow nership: A Constitutional Right, 10 N. KY. L. REV. 113
(1982); Stephen P. Halbrook, Congress In terprets the S econd Am end m ent: Declara tion s
by a Co-Equal Branch on the Individual Right to Keep and Bear Arms, 62 TENN. L.
REV. 597 (1995); Stephen P . Ha lbrook, En croach m ents of the Crown on th e Liberty of
the Subject: Pre-R evolu tion ary Origin s of the S econd Amendment, 15 U. DAYTON L.
REV. 91 (1989); Stephen P. Halb rook , Personal Security, Personal Liberty, and “The
Constitutional Right to Bear Arms”: Visions of the Framers of the Fourteenth
Amendment, 5 SETON HALL CONST. L.J. 341 (1995) [herein after Halbrook, Personal
Security]; Stephen P. Halbr ook, S econd -Class C itizen sh ip a nd th e S econd Am end m ent
in the District of Columbia, 5 GEO. MASO N U. CIV. RTS. L.J . 105 (1995); Stephen P.
Halbrook, The Jurispru den ce of th e S econd and F our teen th Am end m ent s, 4 GEO.
MASON L. REV. 1 (19 81); Stephen P . Ha lbrook, The R igh t of t he P eople or th e Pow er
of th e S ta te: Bea rin g Ar m s, A rm in g Militia s, and th e S econd Am end m ent , 26 VAL. U.
L. REV. 131 (1991); Stephen P. H albrook, What the Framers Intended: A Linguistic
Analysis of the Right to “Bear Arms”, 49 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 151 (1986)
[hereinafter Halbrook, What the Framers Intended]; David G. Har dy, Armed Citizens,
Cit izen Arm ies: Towa rd a J ur ispru den ce of th e S econd Amendment, 9 HARV. J.L. &
P UB . POLY 559 (1986); David G. Hardy, The Second Amendment and the
Historiography of the Bill of Rights, 4 J.L. & POL. 1 (1987) [hereina fter Hardy, Second
Amend ment]; Nicholas J . Johnson, Principles and Passions: Th e Inters ection of
Abortion and Gun Rights, 50 RUTGERS L. REV. 97 (1997); Don B. Kat es, J r., Handgun
Prohibition and the O riginal M ean ing of t he S econd Am end m ent , 82 MICH. L. REV.
204 (1983) [hereina fter Kat es, Ha nd gun Proh ibit ion]; Don B. Kates, J r., Th e S econd
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1364 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
Amendm ent: A Dialogue, 49 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 143 (198 6); Don Ka tes, The
Second Am end m ent and t he Ideology of S elf-Protecti on, 9 CONST. COMMENTARY 87
(1992) [hereinafter Kates, S elf-Protection]; David B. Kopel & Christopher C. Little,
Communitarians, Neorepublicans, and Gu ns: Assessing the Case for Firearms
Proh ibit ion, 56 MD. L. REV. 438 (1997); Stephanie A. Levin, Grassroots Voices: Local
Action an d N ational M ilitary P olicy, 40 BUFF. L. REV. 321, 346-47 (1992); Sa nfor d
Levinson, The Embarrassing S econd Amendment, 99 YALE L.J . 637 (1989); N elson
Lund, The P ast an d F ut ure of the Individual’s Right to Arms, 31 GA. L. REV. 1 (1996)
[hereinafter Lund, Past and Fu ture]; Nelson Lund, The Second Amendment, Political
Liberty, and t he R igh t to S elf-Preservation, 39 ALA. L. REV. 103 (1987); Joyce Lee
Malcolm, T h e R ig h t of the P eop le to K eep an d B ea r A rm s: T he Common Law
Tr ad ition, 10 HASTINGS CONST. L.Q. 285 (1983); Thomas B. McAffee & Micha el J.
Quinlan, Bringin g Forw ard th e Ri ght to Keep and Bea r Arm s: Do Text, Histor y, or
Preced ent Stand in the Way?, 75 N.C. L. REV. 781 (1997); Thoma s M. Moncure, Jr.,
The Second Am endment Ain’t About Hunting, 34 HOW. L.J. 589 (1991); Thomas M.
Moncure, Jr., Who is the Militia— The Virginia Ratification Convention and the Right
to Bear Arms, 19 LINCOLN L. REV. 1 (1990); James Gray Pope, Republican Moments:
The Role of Direct Popular Pow er in th e Am erica n Cons tit ut ional O rder, 139 U. PA.
L. REV. 287 (1990); L.A. Powe, J r., Guns, Words, an d Constit ut ional Int erpretat ion,
38 WM. & MARY L. REV. 1311 (1997); Michael J . Quin lan, Is There a Neutral
Jus tif ication for R efu sin g to I m plem ent the S econd Am end m ent or is th e S up rem e
Court Just “Gun S hy”?, 22 CAP. U. L. REV. 641 (1993); Glenn Ha rlan Reynolds, A
Critical Guide to the S econd Am end m ent , 62 TENN. L. REV. 461 (1995); Glenn H arlan
Reynolds, The Right to Keep and Bear Arms Under the Tennessee Constitution: A Case
Study in Civic Republican Though t, 61 TENN. L. REV. 647 (1994) (discussing the
Secon d Amendment as r elated to t he Tenn essee Constitut ion) [hereinafter Reynolds,
Tennessee Constitu tion ]; Elain e Scar ry, War and the Social Contract: Nu clear Policy,
Distribution, and th e Right to Bear Arms, 139 U. PA. L. REV. 1257 (1991); J. Neil
Sch ulman, The Text of th e Second Am end m ent , 4 J. ON FIREARMS & P UB. POLY 159
(1992); Robert E. Sh alhope, The Armed Citizen in the Early Republic, 49 LAW &
CONTEMP. PROBS. 125 (1986); Robert E. Sha lhope, The Ideological Origins of the
Second Amendment, 69 J. AM. HIST. 599 (1982); William Van Alst yne, Th e S econd
Amendment and the Personal Right to Arms, 43 DUKE L.J. 1236 (1994); David E.
Vandercoy, The H istory of th e S econd Am end m ent , 28 VAL. U. L. REV. 1007 (1994);
Eugene Volokh, The Amazing Vanishing Second Amendment, 73 N.Y.U. L. REV. 831
(1998); Eugene Volokh, The Commonplace Second Amendment, 73 N.Y.U. L. REV . 793
(1998); Scott Bursor, Note, Toward a Fu nct ion al Fram ewor k for In terpret ing the
Second Amendment, 74 TEX. L. REV . 1125 (1996); Robert J. Cottrol & Raymond T.
Diamond, The Fifth Auxiliary Right, 104 YALE L.J. 995 (1995) (reviewing J OYCE LEE
MALCOLM, TO KEEP AND BEAR ARMS: THE ORIGINS OF AN ANGLO-AMERICAN RIGHT
(1994)); Bra nnon P. Denning, Professional Discourse, The Second Amendment, and the
Talking Head Constitutionalism” Counterrevolution: A Review Essay, 21 S. ILL. U. L.J .
227 (1997) (reviewing DENNIS A. HENIG AN ET AL ., GUNS AND THE CONSTITUTION: THE
MYTH OF SECOND AMENDME NT PROTECTION FOR FIREARMS IN AMERICA (1996)); T.
Markus Funk , Is t he T rue Meaning of th e Second Amend m ent Really S uch a R iddl e?
Tracing the Historical “Origins of an An glo-American Righ t”, 39 HOW. L.J. 411 (1995)
(reviewing JOYCE LEE MALCOM, TO KEEP AND BEAR ARMS: THE ORIGINS OF AN ANGLO-
AME RICAN RIGHT (1994)); David B. Kopel, It Isn’t About Duck Hun ting: The British
Origins of the Right to Arms, 93 MICH. L. REV. 1333 (1995) (reviewing JOYCE LEE
MALCOLM, TO KEEP AND BEAR ARMS: THE ORIGINS OF AN ANGLO-AMERICAN RIGHT
(1994)); F. Sm ith Fussn er, Book Review, 3 CONST. COMME NT ARY 582 (1986) (reviewing
STEPHEN P. HALBROOK, THAT EVER Y MAN BE ARMED: THE EVOLUTION OF A
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1365
CONS TITU TION AL R IGHT (1984)); Joyce Lee Ma lcolm, Book Review, 54 GEO. WASH. L.
REV. 452 (198 6) (reviewing STEPHEN P. HALBROOK, THAT EVER Y MAN BE ARMED: THE
EVOLUTION OF A CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT (1984)); cf. Nicholas J. Johnson, Beyond the
Second Am end ment : An In di vid ua l R igh t to Arm s View ed t hrough the Ninth
Amendment, 24 RUTGERS L.J. 1 (1992) (arguing that the Ninth Amendment supports
an individu al righ t t o ar ms ).
2. See DENNIS A. HEN IGAN ET AL ., GUNS AND THE CONSTITUTION: THE MYTH OF
SECOND AMENDME NT PROTECTION FOR FIREARMS IN AMERICA (1995); Keith A. Ehrman
& Dennis A. Henigan, The S econd Am end ment in th e Twen tiet h Cent ur y: Ha ve Y ou
S een Your Militia Lately?, 15 U. DAYTON L. REV. 5, 30 (19 89) (“ The ‘right to bear
arms’ concerned the abilit y of th e st at es t o ma int ain an effect ive m ilit ia, not an
individual right to keep weapons for an y purpose whatsoever.”); Dennis A. Henigan,
Arms, Anarchy and the Second Amendment, 26 VAL. U. L. REV. 107 (1991) [hereinafter
Henigan, Arm s, An arch y]. Henigan’s status as premier writer of the anti-individual
school is based on the fact that he has authored two full length anti-individualist law
review articles in t he las t decade, an d h e is by far t he mos t a ctive sp okesm an for the
view that the individua l right t o keep and bea r a rm s is a frau d. S ee sources cited
infra not e 12; see also ROBERT J. SPITZER, THE POLITICS OF GUN CONTROL 42-43 (1995);
George Anastaplo, Amendments to the Constitution of the United States: A
Commentary, 23 LOY. U. CHI. L.J. 631, 687-93 (1992); Michael A. Bellesiles, The
Origins of Gun Culture in the United States, 1760-1865, 83 J. AM. HIST. 425 (1996);
Carl T. Bogus, Race, Riots, and Guns, 66 S. CAL. L. REV. 1365 (1993); Carl T. Bogus,
The Hidd en H ist ory of th e Second Am end m ent , 31 U.C. DAVIS L. REV. 309 (1998)
[hereinafter Bogus, Hidden History]; Lawrence Delbert Cr ess, An Arm ed Comm unity:
The Origins and Meaning of the Right to Bear Arms, 71 J. AM. HIST. 22 (1984);
Samuel Fields, Gu ns , Crim e an d t he N eglig ent Gun O wn er, 10 N. KY. L. REV. 141
(1982); Andrew D. H erz, Gun Crazy: Constitutional False Consciousness and
Derelict ion of Dialogic Responsibility, 75 B.U. L. REV . 57 (1995); Mich ael J . Pa lmiott o,
The Misconception of the American Citizen’s Right to Keep and Bear Arms, 4 J. ON
FIRE ARMS & PUB. POLY 85 (1992); War ren Spann aus, S tat e Firearm s R egul ati on and
the Second Amendment, 6 HAMLINE L. REV . 383 (198 3).
Standard Modelers differ among them selves over the types of
guns which may be kept, the breadth of purposes for which the
right to keep a gun is protected, and the permissible
restrictions on the “bearing” of arms.
Competing with the Standard Model in the late twentieth
century are what this article terms the “anti-individual”
theories. The name is appropriate because these theories are
linked by t heir common attempt to show that an individual
Amer ican citizen has no right to own a gun. The leading anti-
individual theorist is Handgun Control’s attorney Dennis
Henigan, who argues that the Second Amendment protects the
state governments’ right to be free from federal interference
with their militias.
2
According to this view, t he Secon d
Amendment limits the Congressional militia powers created by
Article I of the Constitution, although Henigan and other
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1366 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
3. For an analysis of the logical implicat ions of a states rights Second
Amendment theory as propounded by Henigan, see Glenn Har lan Reynolds & Don B.
Kates, The Second Amendment an d S tates Righ ts: A Thou ght E xper im ent , 36 WM. &
MARY L. REV. 1737 (1995). If the Second Am endment did guarantee state control over
the National Guard, then it would be ha rd to den y th e uncon stitu tion ali ty of
President Eisenhower’s federalization of the Arkansas National Guard—over the
vehement prote st of th e Gov ernor —du ri ng th e Litt le Rock school integration crisis in
1957. See Powe, supra note 1, at 1385-86.
4. Denn is Henigan, The Right to Be Arm ed: A Constit ut ional Illu sion , S.F.
BARRISTER, Dec. 1989, available online at ¶ 19 (visited Nov. 30, 1998)
<htt p://www.handguncontr ol.org/legalaction/C2/c2rtarms.htm>.
5. Garry Wills, Why We Have N o Right to Bear Arms, N .Y. REV. BOOKS, Sept.
21, 1995, at 62, 72.
6. Id. at 69.
7. See id. at 72.
states’ rights supporters have not specified what those
lim itations are.
3
But if states righ ts t heorists a re unclea r abou t
what the Second Amendment does, they a re emph atic abou t
what it does not do: “since privately-owned weapons are no
longer used to arm citizen militias, as they were in colonial
times, the regulation of such arms should face no Second
Amendment barrier.
4
Another major anti-individual theory might be called the
nihilist Second Amendment.” Offered by Garry Wills, this
theory argues that the Second Amendment “had no real
meaning.
5
According to Wills, only “wacky scholars” and their
dupes believe that the Second Am endm ent affirms a righ t of
individuals to own firearms for pr otection against tyranny.
6
Evid ently, J ames Ma dison played a clever trick on the entire
United States and wrote an Amendment which amounts to
nothing at all. In the period between Madison and Wills,
however, no one else seems to have discovered this shrewd
ploy.
7
The termcollective rights” is somet imes used in connect ion
with these anti-individual interpretations of the Second
Amendment to indicat e a right that belongs to the people
collectively (like “collective property” under a Communist
government), rather than to any individual, and therefore
belongs to the government. Some “collective rights” proponents
adhere to a states’ r ights version Second Amendment, while
other s propou nd t he nihilist app roach.
David Williams offers a third variant on the “anti-
individual” approach in a series of innovative articles. First, he
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1367
8. See David C. William s, Civic Republicanism and the Citizen Militia: The
Terrifying Second Amendment, 101 YALE L.J . 551 (1991) [her eina fter William s, Civic
Republicanism]; David C. William s, The M ilitia Mov em ent an d S econd Am end m ent
Revolution: Conjuring with the People, 81 CORNELL L. REV. 879 (1996) [hereinafter
Williams, Militia Movement]; David C. Willia ms, Th e Un ita ry S econd Amendment, 73
N.Y.U. L. REV. 822 (199 8).
9.
acknowledges that the Second Amendment was intended to
preser ve the ability of all “the people” to have guns a nd t o kn ow
how to use them to maintain order and resist tyranny.
8
But,
continues Williams, the Second Amendment is operative only as
long as the American people are like “the people” contemplated
in the r epublican theory of the Second Am endm en t: virtuous,
unified, homogenous, imbu ed wit h a shared vision of th e
common good, and trained by their state governments in the
use of firearms. Since the American people no longer fit the
description ofthe people implicit in the Second Amendment,
the argument goes, the Second Am endm ent is obsolet e and of
no legal effect. Because Willia ms’s theor y is an argument abou t
changed circumstances in the twentieth century, analysis of
nineteenth century sources cannot resolve all the issues he
raises. But the nineteenth century does provide a good test case
for Williams’s theory of the Second Amendment. During the
period before and after the Civil War, Americans were more
disunited, more distrustful of each other, and more thoroughly
polarized in their competing vis ions of the com mon good than at
any other time in American history. It is useful to examine
what became of t he Secon d Am endment during these decades
when the people of the United St ates fell far awa y from
Williams’s ideal.
The various fa ctions in the modern Second Amendment
debate share another t rait: they insist that their own
interpretation has a lways been the common underst anding of
the Second Amendment. The contra ry viewpoint, each insists,
is a modern fiction, invented by the other faction, and having no
support in American legal history. For example, the late
Warren Burger, after retiring from the Supreme Court,
participated in an advertising campaign for Handgun Control.
The former Just ice informed Americans that the notion of the
Second Amendment as an individual right is a “fr aud”
perpetrated by t he National Rifle Association.
9
The late Erwin
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1368 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
[O]n e of the frauds—and I use t ha t t er ms [sic] a dvisedly—on t he Ame rican
people, ha s been th e camp aign t o mislead th e pu blic a bout t he Secon d
Amendment. The Second Amendment doesn’t guarantee the r ight to ha ve
firearms at all. . . . [The People of this coun try] want ed th e Bill of Rights
to make sure tha t there was no standing army in this country, but that
there would be state armies. Every state during th e revolution had its own
army. There was no na tiona l army.
Warren Bur ger, Press Conference Concerning Introduction of the Public Health and
Safety Act of 1992, FED. NEWS SERVICE, June 26, 1992, available in LEXIS, Nexis
Library, ARCN WS F ile (su pporting pr opos al to confisca te ha nd guns ).
The United States, under the Constit ution, has always had a standing ar my. If
the Second Amendm ent were meant to prohibit standing armies, it is impossible to
explain why the very same Congress t hat approved the Second Amendment also voted
to crea te a sta ndin g ar my. Compare Military Establishment Act, H .R. 50a, with
Military Establishment Act, H.R. 126a, both in 5 DOCUMENTARY HISTORY OF THE FIRST
FED ERAL CONGRESS 1789-1791, at 1272-14 32 (L inda Gr an t D e P au w et a l. eds., 1972 ).
10. Erwin N. Gr iswold, Phantom Second Am endment ‘Rights’, WASH. POST, Nov.
4, 1990, at C7; see also Hen igan, supra note 4 (“That the 2nd Amendment poses no
threat to laws affecting the pr ivate possession of firearms m ay well be t he m ost well-
settled proposition in const itutional law.”). Considerin g how well-establish ed certain
other pr inciples of American law ar e (su ch a s ju dicia l re view, or t he prohib ition on
prior restr ain ts), Gr iswold and H eniga n m ake a very st rong claim.
11. Michael K. Beard & Kristin M. Ran d, The Handgun Battle, BILL OF RTS. J.,
Dec. 1987, at 13, 13.
12. 9 FIREARMS LITIG. REP. (Firearms Litig. Clear inghouse), Su mm er 1995, at
4 (recomm ending And rew D. Herz, Gun Crazy: Constitutional False Consciousness and
Dereliction of Dialogic Responsibility, 75 B.U. L. Re v. 57 (1995)); see also CENTER TO
PREVENT HANDGUN V IOLENCE, THE SECOND AMENDMENT: FRAUD AND FACT (undated
pamphlet) (on file with a uthor) (“Fraud[:] . . . each citizen of a state retains a
fundamentalrigh t to keep and bear a rms.’ Fact[:] . . . the Second Amendment does
not guarantee th e righ t of individuals to own an d to carry arm s.”); Denn is Hen igan,
Exploding the NRA’s Constitutional Myth, LEG AL TIMES, Apr. 22, 1991, at 22, 22
Griswold, former Solicitor General of the United States, former
Dean of Harvard Law School, and m em ber of the Board of
Handgun Control, wrote “that the Second Amendment poses no
barrier to strong gun laws is perhaps the most well-settled
proposition in American constitutional law.”
10
Similarly, the
Coalit ion to St op Gun Violence (t he n ations second largest
antigun group, next to Handgun Control) informs us that the
notion of the Secon d Amendment as a barrier to gun pr ohibition
is a “myth.
11
The Coalitions educational arm recommends a
recent law review article which, instead of the wordmyt h,”
uses words such as “deception,” “constitutional false
consciousness,fake,” “int entional deception,” “fictional,”
“bogus,” and “constitutional charade.” The article further
accuses law professors holding contrary views of deliberate
fraud.
12
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1369
(arguing that an individual right to arms is a “constitutional myth, an illusion created
by ma ss ad ver ti sin g to ad vance a p olit ica l object ive ,” th at th e N RA should “no longer
pretend th at th er e is some fund am en ta l cons tit ut ional liberty at stake, and that
“[i]t’s time to stop the Second Amendment nonsense”) [hereinafter Henigan,
Constitutional Myth]; Dennis He nigan, Faulty Interpretation, WASH. TIMES, Jan. 11,
1998, at B4 (“Th e con st itut ional debate is p hony .”).
13. See generally DUNCAN KENNEDY, LEGAL EDUCATION AND THE REPRODUCTION
OF HIERA RCHY: A POLEMIC AGAINST THE SYSTEM (198 3).
If Chief Justice Burger and the rest are right, then we
should expect that legal materials of the nineteenth century
would clearly support their claim. In the period before the
founding of the National Rifle Association in 1871, we should
not expect to find assertions that the Second Amendment is an
individual right.
This article lets the nineteenth century legal community
speak for itself by dealing with the treatises and cases—what
Duncan Kennedy calls “the mandarin materials”
13
—of th e
nineteenth century, as well a s Congressional and polit ical
debates. Newspaper articles, novels, and other mass
entertainment materials are not discussed. There is a great
deal to learn from what the nineteenth century had to say
about the Second Amendment. Most importantly, we can
resolve whether the Second Amendment has historically been
considered to protect an individual right. Additionally, an
examination of the Second Amendment in the nineteenth
century provides useful guidance about what types of gun
control are constitutionally permissible.
Part II of this article analyzes the Second Amendment
scholarship of the three great constitutional treatises of early
nineteenth century—St. George Tucker’s American Blackstone,
William Rawle’s A View of the Constitution of the United States
of America, and Joseph Story’s Commentaries on the
Constitution of the United States—as well as some lesser
commentators from the 1830s, 1840s, and 1850s. Part II also
includes a study of Justice Story’s dicta about the Second
Amendment in the 1820 case Houston v. Moore.
Part III addresses nineteenth century state constitutions
and state case law regarding the right to arms. These
constitutional texts and their judicial interpretation offer
valuable insights into the meaning of the Second Amendment.
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1370 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
The Civil War is the subject of Pa rt IV, which discusses
Dred S cott, the writin gs of anti-slavery human rights activists,
and the confiscations of arms before and during the War. Part
V deals wit h the aftermath of the Civil War, including
Congressional debates about the infringements by
unreconstructed Southern states of the freedmens right to
arms; the Fourteenth Amendment; and the Supreme Court’s
Cruikshank decision. Part V concludes with a discu ssion of th e
growth in labor unrest, restrictive gun laws aimed at labor
agitators, and the Supreme Courts Presser decision.
Scholarly commentators of the later nineteenth century are
the subject of Part VI. Thomas Cooley is the giant of this
period, but there were also more than a dozen other
constitutional treatises from the period, as well as the first law
review articles on the right to arms.
Part VII brings the article to the fin-de-siècle, by looking at
two Su pr em e Court cases m en tioning the Secon d Am endment
in dicta; it also peeks ahead into the early twentieth century at
the most important Second Amendment “states’ right”
ruling—the Kansas case of S alin a v. Blaksley. Part VII also
examines the implications that the nineteenth century records
have for moder n firea rms policy, and for the scholarsh ip of
David Williams and Carl Bogus.
The Conclusion discu ss es wh ich modes of t he Secon d
Amendment analysis are plausible and which modes are
implausible in light of the nineteenth centurys Second
Amendment interpretation.
II. THE EARL Y GIANTS: TUCKER, RAWLE, AND STORY
Part II of this article examines the treatment of the Second
Amendment in the fir st third of the nineteenth century by the
three major legal commentators of the era: St. George Tucker,
William Rawle, and Joseph Story. This Part also discusses the
Supreme Court’s first Second Amendment case, the virtually
unknown 1820 Houston v. Moore. The Part concludes with
discussion of other commentators from the 1830s through the
1850s.
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1371
A. St. George T ucker: The Am erican Blackstone
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1372 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
14. WILLI AM BLAC KSTO NE, COMMENTARIES (St. George Tucker ed., Lawbook
Exchange, Ltd. 1996) (1803).
15. See Hon. Armistead M. Dobie, Fed eral District J ud ges in V irginia B efore t he
Civil War, 12 F.R.D . 451, 459 (1 952); WILLIAM S. PRINCE , THE POEMS OF HEN RY ST.
GEORGE TUCKER OF WILLIAMSBURG, VIRGINIA 1752-1827, at 1 (1977). Like many
educated me n of his day , Tu cker fr equently wr ote poet ry. Alth ough his poem s a re not
particula rly memorable, neither is most American poetry from t he E arly Repu blic. See
id. at x.
16. Don Riddick, The Second Most Powerful Pen in Early Virginia: St. George
Tucker, 4 J. S. LEG. HIST. 71, 71 (1 997).
17. See JAMES MADISON, JOURNAL OF THE FEDERAL CONVENTION 35-36 (E.H .
Scott ed., Alb er t, Scot t & Co. 1 893 ) (1840).
18. LAWRENCE M. FRIE DMAN , A HISTORY OF AMERICAN LAW 193 (1973). Tucker
was also known to be “as kindhearted a ma n as ever lived.” HENRY ADAMS, JOHN
RANDOLPH 166 (M.E. Shar pe 1996) (188 2).
19. See PRINCE, supra note 15, at 5; Paul D. Car rin gton, The Twenty-First
Wis dom , 52 WASH. & LEE L. REV. 333, 33 3 n.1 (1 995); Dowlut, The Right to Arms,
supra note 1, at 83-84; Stephen P . Halbrook, Rationing Firearms Purchases and the
Righ t to Keep Arms: Reflections on the Bills of Rights of Virginia, West Virginia, and
the Un ited S tates, 96 W. VA. L. REV. 1, 2 0 (19 93).
20. Carrington, supra note 19, at 336.
21. RICHARD B. DAVIS, INTELLECTUAL LIFE IN JEFFE RSONS VIRGI NIA 1790-1843,
at 413 (1964), cited in Car rin gton, supra note 19, at 336 n.18. H is abolition proposal
The first scholar ly analysis of the Second Amendment is
found in St . George Tuckers American edition of Blackstone’s
Com m entaries, published in 1803.
14
1. Tucker’s backgrou nd
The law practice of this young Virginia attorney was
interrupted by the American Revolution. St. George Tucker
threw himself into the cause enthusiastically, heading up a
gun-running operation in which his four small ships sent indigo
to the West Indies and Bermuda in exchange for firearms for
the Patriots.
15
Acclaimed as “one of the great war heroes of
Virginia,” Tucker was chosen as h ea d of Vir gin ias delegation to
the Annapolis Convention (the precursor to the Philadelphia
Conven tion).
16
Ther e, h e ser ved on a commission with James
Madison to meet with state officials and determine to what
degree the federal government should have the authority to
create uniform rules to facilitate interstate commerce.
17
“[O]ne of the most eminent of Virgin ia lawyers,
18
Tucker
taught law at William and Mary from 1790 until 1804, when he
was appointed a judge of Vir ginias H igh Court of Appeals.
19
He
was alsoperhaps the most ardent advocate of emancipation in
Virginia in the 1790s,”
20
calling it his “dear est wish.”
21
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1373
was detailed in ST. GEORGE TUCKER, A DISSERTATION ON SLAVERY: WITH A PROP OSAL
FOR THE GRADUAL ABOLITION OF IT IN THE STATE OF VIRGINIA (179 6). Tucker ensured
the wide circulat ion of his proposa l by ma king it an appen dix to h is 1803 t rea tise. See
2 BLACKSTONE, supra note 14, app. at 31. Tucker described the disarmed status of
free Negroes in Virginia as amounting to civil slavery. But he urged that the law
against ownersh ip of arm s by freedm en be le ft in pla ce upon th e abolition of slavery,
so as to encourage the ex-slaves to settle outside Virginia. See id. app. at 57, 68, 78-
79.
22. See PRINCE, supra note 15, at 5.
23. See Pau l Finkelman & David Cobin, In trod uction to 1 BLACKSTONE, supra
note 14 at i.
24. Carrington, supra note 19, at 334.
25. See Pa ul D. Ca rr ington, Law as “The Comm on Thoughts of Men”: The Law-
Teaching an d J ud gin g of T hom as M cIn tyre Cooley, 49 STAN. L. REV. 495, 516 (19 97).
26. See Elizabeth Gaspar Brown , A Jeffersonian’s Recommendations for a
Lawyer’s Education: 1802, 13 AM. J. LEGAL HIST. 139, 141 (1969). Two decades later,
Tucker’s Blackstone was still “necessary to every student and practitioner of law in
Virginia.” Daniel Call, Biographical Sketch of the Judges of the Court of Appeals, 8
Va. (4 Call) xxvi, xxviii (1827), reprinted in JEFFERSON, VIRGI NIA REPORTS, 1730-1880,
at 627 (Th omas J ohns on Mich ie e d., Th e Michi e Co. 1902).
27. Finkelman & Cobin, supra note 23, at xiii.
President Madison appointed Tucker to the federal bench for
Virginia in 1813, where he served until his death in 1827.
22
2. The central role of Tucker’s American Blackstone
Tucker’s annotated edition of Blackstone quickly became
known as the American Blackstone.
23
It was the first treatise on
common law written for t he needs and conditions of t he
Amer ican legal profession. The treatise consisted of
Bla ckst one’s four original volumes, annotated by Tucker, plus
numerous appen dices on Amer ican law a nd t he Const itution.
Thefive-volume [work] was the standard work on American
law for a generation.”
24
Almost every prospective lawyer began
his studies by reading Tucker’s Blackstone, and some lawyers
may never have read anything else.
25
Thomas Jefferson
recommended Tucker’s Blackstone as part of the course of study
for aspiring law students, since the Tucker book was the best
source for overall mastery of American law.
26
Before the
publication of Chancellor Kent’s Com m entaries in the late
1820s,Tucker’s [Blackstone] was the only trea tise on
Amer ican law available in the nation. Until 1827, Tucker was
the most frequently cited American legal scholar . . . .”
27
In
short, Tucker’s Blackstone is “generally considered the single
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1374 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
28. Riddick, supra note 16, at 73; see also Hon. Armistead M. Dobie, Federal
District Jud ges in V irgin ia B efore t he C ivil War, 12 F.R.D. 451, 460 (1 952 ) (“[T]he
Ame ri can Blackstone was unquestiona bly one of the most important law-books of its
da y.”).
29. Alfred L. Brophy, Ingenium Est Fateri Per Quos Profeceri s:” Fra ncis Da niel
Pastorius’ Young Country Clerk’s Collection an d A nglo-Am erica n L egal Li terature,
1682-1716, U. CHI. SCH. ROUNDTABLE 637, 671 n.121 (1996) (citing Robert M. Cover,
Tucker’s Blackstone, 70 COLUM. L. REV. 1475, 1475 (1970); John H. Langbein,
Chancellor Kent and the History of Legal Literature, 93 COLUM. L. REV . 547 (199 3)).
30. See Finkelm an & Cobin, supra note 23, at ii.
31. 2 BLACKSTONE, supra note 14, at 140-42.
32. See id. The primary rights were personal secur ity, person al liber ty, and
proper ty. See id. at 121-38.
33. Id. at 143 (footnote s a dded by T uck er ).
most important ea rly lega l text crea ted by a n Amer ican
scholar.”
28
Alfred Brophy observes: “When Americans set out to remold
law books for use in America, as Henry [sic] St. George Tucker
did in 1803 with Blackstone’s Com m entaries, their results are
extraordinarily illuminating about bot h the mind of Am ericans
and the state of American law.”
29
Tucker did not intend merely
to reprint Blackstone; he wanted to show how Blackstone’s
ver sion of the common law had been changed —in the direct ion
of significantly greater civil liberty—by developments in
Amer ica, especially the ratifica tion of the Constitution and Bill
of Rights.
30
3. Tucker on the right to arms in Bla ckst one
The second volume of Tucker’s American Blackstone
contains Blackstone’s commentary on what Blackstone called
the five “auxiliary rights of the subject.”
31
These were rights
(such as the right to seek legal redress in court, and the right to
petition) whose main purpose was to safeguard primary
rights.
32
Blackstone had written:
The fifth and last auxiliary right of the subject, that I shall at
present mention , is th at of having arm s for their defence[fn40]
su ita ble to their cond ition and degr ee, and such as are allowed
by law[fn 41]. Which is also declared by the same statute 1 W.
& M. st. 2 c. 2, and it is indeed, a public allowance under due
restrictions, of the natural rights of resistance and self-
preservation, when the sanctions of society and laws are found
insu fficient t o re stra in th e viole nce of opp re ssion.
33
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1375
34. 1 W. & M., Sess. 2, ch. 2 (1688). Th e Parliament ena cting the Bill of Rights
had reject ed a n a rm s gu ar an tee lim iting th e r ight on ly to ar ms kept “for their
comm on defence.” MALCOLM, supra note 1, at 117. Although Catholics were excluded,
they were allowed by statute to keep guns on their own property for persona l de fense.
See 1 W. & M. Sess. 2, ch. 15 (1 688 ); MALCOLM, supra note 1, at 122-23.
35. 2 BLACKSTONE, supra not e 14, at 143 n .40. Th e cit at ion to “Ar t. 4” reflect s
the fact that the Second Amendment was originally the Fourth Amendment and
gained its current numbering only when the original first two amendments
(controlling House of Representatives apportionment and Congressional pay raises)
failed to win speedy ra tificat ion by the states. Tucker’s numbering system followed
the numbering of the amendments as proposed to the S ta tes by Congr ess. S ee 1 id.
app. at 300.
36. 2 id . a t 143 n .41 (qu ota tion ma rk s m odifi ed to r efle ct m odern us age).
37. They [the proposed Bill of Right s] rela te 1s t. to private rights — . . . fa lla cy
on both s ide s—espec[iall]y a s t o En glis h D ecln . of Rt s—1. mere act of parl[iamen]t.
2. no freedom of press—Conscience . . . attainders—arms to Protest[an]ts.” James
Madison, N otes for S peech in Con gress S up port in g Am end m ent s (June 8, 1789), in 12
THE PAPERS OF JAMES MADISON 193-94 (Charles F. H obson et . al. eds., 1979); see also
THE ORIGIN OF THE SECOND AMENDMENT 645 (David E. Young ed., 1991) [hereinafter
Bla ckst one was explaining the English Bill of Rights, wh ich
provided:That the subjects which are protesta nt s, may have
arms for their defence suitable to their conditions, and as
allowed by law.”
34
Tucker added his own analysis in two footnotes:
[fn40] The right of the people to keep an d bea r a rm s shall not
be infringed. Am endm en ts to C. U. S. Ar t. 4, an d this with out
any qualification as to their condition or degree, as is the case
in the British government.
35
[fn41] Wh oever examines the forest, a nd game laws in t he
British code , will r ea dily p er ceive that t he r igh t of keeping
arms is effectu ally ta ken a way from th e people of E nglan d.
The commentator himself informs us, Vol. II, p. 412,that the
pr eve ntion of popular insurrections and resistence to
government by disarming the bulk of the people, is a reason
oftener meant than avowed by the makers of the forest and
gam e la ws .”
36
Tucker’s footnote 40 echoed the language of t he Secon d
Amendment. He distinguished the American right to arms from
its British antecedent by noting that the American right had
none of the limitations that were contained in the British right.
Tucker’s criticism of the English Bill of Rights paralleled
Madison’s criticisms in a speech to Congress introducing the
Bill of Rights.
37
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1376 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
ORIGIN].
38. 3 BLACKSTONE, supra note 14, at 414 n.3.
39. See MALCOLM, supra note 1, at 126-30.
40. 3 BLACKSTONE, supra note 14, at 414 n.3.
Tucker’s footnote 41 qu oted Bla ckstone’s description of th e
English game la ws, with their restriction on the ownership of
hunting weapons as having the covert intent of disarming the
non-aristocratic population. In his commentary on the game
laws section of Blackstone, Tucker added his own condemnation
of British pr actice, contrast ing it wit h the robust righ t to arms
in Amer ica:
The bill of rights, 1 W. a nd M, sa ys Mr. Blackstone, (Vol. 1
p. 143,) secures to the subjects of England the right of having
arms for their defen ce, suitable to their con dition an d degree.
In the construction of these game laws it seems to be held, that
no person who is not qualified according to law to kill game,
hath any right to keep a gun in his house. Now, as no person,
(except th e gam e-k eepe r of a lord or lady of a m anor) is
admitted to be qualified to kill game, unless he has 100l. per
annum, &c. it follows th at no others can keep a gun for th eir
defence; so that the wh ole n at ion ar e com pletely disa rm ed, an d
left at the mercy of the government, under the prete xt of
preserving the breed of hares and pa rt rid ges, for the exclusive
use of th e in dependent cou ntr y gentle men . In Am er ica we may
re as ona bly hope that the people will never cease to regard the
right of keepin g and bearing arms as the surest pled ge of th eir
liberty.
38
In fact, Tucker was wrong in his dire description of
England; after the overthrow of the Stuarts in 1689, the game
laws were no longer used to disarm the common people. The
law presumed that a comm oners gu n was intended for self-
defense (a right guaranteed by the 1689 Bill of Rights), unless
the circumstances showed that the gun was used for u nlawful
hunting.
39
But more important than whether Tucker accurately
understood English circumstances is what his widely read
treatise shows about the state of American law. Tucker’s
remarks unambiguously described “the right of keeping and
bearing arms as the surest pledge of . . . liberty.”
40
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1377
41. St. George Tucker, The Judges Tucker of the Court of Appeals of Virginia,
1 VA. L. REG. 789, 794 (1896); see also Fin kelm an & Cobin, supra note 23, at i.
42. See Tucker, supra note 41, at 793.
43. See Finkelm an & Cobin, supra note 23, at ii.
44. New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254, 286, 296 (1964) (Black, J.,
concurring) (J us tice Dougla s joine d t his con cur re nce ).
45. Finkelman & Cobin, supra note 23, at v.
46. Cohens v. Vir gin ia, 19 U.S. (6 Wh ea t.) 264 , 418 (18 21).
4. Tucker’s appen dix on th e Am erican Constitution
Tucker’s American Blackstone contained several appendices,
including a lengthy appendix analyzing the new American
Const itution. This appendix was “the first disquisition upon the
character and interpretation of the Federal Constitution, as
well as upon its origin and true na tu re,”
41
and was used as a
legal textbook for many decades throughout the United
States.
42
Tucker’s constitutional analysis remains powerful in
modern times. For example, Tucker was the first scholar to
argue that the First Amendment advanced far beyond English
common law freedom of pr ess. While freedom of press in
England meant only freedom from prior restraints, Tucker
argued that the First Amendment left Congress with no power
at all to punish newspapers, even after the fact.
43
Justice Hugo
Bla ck later obser ved that Tuckers a ppendix set forth “the
general view held when the First Amendment was adopted and
ever since.”
44
Justice Black was right to cite Tucker as the definitive
source for original intent. “While Tucker published his
[Amer ican] edition of Blackstone in 1803, he began writing it in
1790, as h e prepared lect ures for his courses at William and
Mary. The ideas and arguments in his volumes are thus
perhaps as contemporaneous to the Founding as it is possible to
find.”
45
Because “[g]reat weight has always been attached, and very
rightly attached, to contemporaneous exposition,”
46
the
Supreme Court has cited Tucker in over forty cases. On e ca n
find Tucker in th e major cases of virtually every Supr em e Court
era. In the early nineteenth century Tucker is cited in Fletch er
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1378 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
47. 10 U.S. (4 Cr an ch) 8 7, 121 (1 810).
48. Dartmouth College v. Woodwar d, 1 7 U .S. (4 Wh ea t.) 518 , 607 (18 19).
49. 22 U.S. (9 Whea t. ) 1, 86, 113, 179 (1824).
50. Charles River Bridg e v. Warr en Br idge, 36 U .S. (11 P et .) 420, 4 72 (1837 ).
51. Scot t v. San dfor d, 60 U .S. (19 H ow.) 3 93, 578 (1856).
52. 83 U.S. (1 6 Wa ll.) 36, 1 27-2 8 (18 72).
53. 123 U.S. 1 31, 152 (1887).
54. 157 U.S. 4 29, 629 (1895) (Wh it e, J ., diss en ti ng).
55. 341 U.S. 4 94, 522 -23 n .4 (1951 ) (Fr an kfu rt er , J ., con cur ring ).
56. 376 U.S. 2 54, 286 , 296-97 (196 4) (Black , J ., con cur ri ng).
57. 501 U.S. 9 57, 977 (1991).
58. U.S. Ter m L imits, Inc. v. Thornt on, 514 U.S. 779 (1995). The Court used
Judge Tucker’s “two primary argum ents” in its holding against t he power to add ter m
limits qualifications:
First, that in a representative government, the people have an
undoubted right to judge for them selves of the qua lification of their
delegate, and if their opinion of the integrity of their representative will
supply th e wa nt of est at e, t here can be n o reas on for the government to
interfere, by saying, that the latter must and sha ll overbalance the former.
Secondly; by requiring a qu alification in estate it m ay often happen , that
men the best qualified in oth er r espects might be in capacitated from servin g
their country.
Id. at 824 n.34.
59. Som e other cites: Pacific Mut. Life Ins. Co. v. Haslip, 499 U.S. 1, 29 (1991)
(Scalia, J., concur ring in jud gment) (“It was t hu s a s a su ppos ed a ffirm at ion of Magn a
Charta according to Coke that the First Congress . . . included in the proposed F ifth
Amendment to t he Fe dera l Con st it ut ion th e provision th at ‘[n]o person shall be . . .
deprived of life, liberty, or p roperty, without due process of law.’ Early commen taries
confirm this. S ee, e.g., 2 W. BLACKSTONE, COMMENTARIES 133 nn.11, 12 (S. Tucker
ed., 1803 ).”); U.S. S te el Cor p. v. Multistate Tax Comm’n, 434 U.S. 452, 463 n.13
(1978) (“St. George Tucker, wh o along with Madison and Edmund Randolph was a
Virginia commissioner to the Annapolis Convention of 1786, drew a distin ction
betweentreaties, alliances, and confederations’ on the one hand, and ‘agreem ents or
compacts’ on th e oth er: . . . 1 W. BLACKSTONE, COMMENTARIES, Appendix 310 (S.
Tucker ed. 1803).”); Apoda ca v. Or egon , 406 U.S. 404, 408 n .3 (1972 ) (“[T]he
unquestioning acceptance of the unanimity rule by text writ ers such as St. George
Tucker indicate th at [jury] unanimity became th e accepted ru le dur ing the 18th
cen tu ry .”); Smith v. California, 361 U.S. 147, 157 n .2 (1959) (Black, J ., concurr ing)
(“For another early discussion of the scope of the First Amendment as a complete bar
to all feder al abridgm en t of s pee ch a nd press see S t. Geor ge T uck ers comment s on
the adequ acy of state forum s and state laws to grant a ll the protection needed
v. Peck ,
47
Dartmouth College,
48
Gibbons v. Ogden,
49
Charles
River Bridge,
50
and Dred Scott;
51
later in the nineteenth century
Tucker appears in the Slaughter-house Cases,
52
Spies v.
Illinois
53
(the Haymarket case), and Pollock v. Farmers’ Loan
and Trust Co.
54
(income tax). Tucker also appears in Dennis v.
United States,
55
New York Times v. Sullivan,
56
Harmelin v.
Michigan,
57
and U.S. Term Limits v. Thornton ,
58
in the
twentieth century.
59
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1379
against defamation and libel.”); Barenblatt v. United States, 360 U.S. 109, 151 n.23
(1959) (Black, J ., dissen ting) (“Cf. St. George Tu cker, Appendix, 1 Blackstone
Commentaries (Tucker ed. 1803) 299. ‘[T]he judicial courts of the respective states a re
open to all persons a like, for the redress of injuries of this natur e [libel] . . . . But
the genius of our government will not permit the federal legislature to inter fere with
the su bject; an d t he federal courts are, I presume, equally restr ained by the pr inciples
of the constitution, and the amendment s which have since been a dopted.’” (omiss ion
and alt er at ions in or igin al)); id at 150 n. 20 (“Cf. St. George Tucker, Appendix, 1
Blackstone [Tucker ed. 1803] 315, discussing English laws ‘for suppressing assemblies
of free-mas ons an d pointing out th at sim ila r laws ca nn ot be en act ed under our
Con st itut ion.”).
60. William Rawle’s and Justice Story’s treatises closely followed this language.
See infra text accompanying notes 96, 112.
61. 1 BLACKSTONE, supra note 14, app. at 300.
5. Tucker’s exposition of the Second Amendment
Although Tucker had addressed the Second Amendment in
his footnotes to Blackstone, the constitutional appendix gave
Tucker the oppor tunity for a fuller exposition:
This may be con sidered as th e tru e palladiu m of
liberty
60
. . . . The right of self defence is the first law of nature:
in most governments it has been th e st ud y of ru lers to confine
this right within the narrowest limits possible. Wherever
standing armies are kept up, and the right of the people to
keep and bear arm s is, under any colour or pretext
whatsoever, pr ohibited, liberty, if not alr eady a nn ihila ted, is
on the brink of destruction. In England, the people have been
disarmed, generally, un der th e specious pretext of preser ving
the game: a never failing lure to bring over the landed
aristocracy to support any measure, under that mask, though
calculated for very differen t p urp oses. Tru e it is, their bill of
rights seem s a t fir st view to cou ntera ct t his policy: but the
right of bearing arms is confined to protestants, and the words
suitable to their condition an d degree, have been interpreted
to authorise the prohibition of keeping a gun or other engine
for the destruction of gam e, to an y farm er, or in ferior
tradesman, or other person not qualified to kill game. So that
not one man in five hundred can keep a gun in his house
without being subject to a pen alty.
61
Besides asserting that the Second Amendment upholds an
individual right essential for liberty, Tucker also argued that
even wit hout the Second Am en dm en t, Con gress cou ld not
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1380 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
62. U.S. CONST. art. I, § 8, cl. 18.
63. 1 BLACKSTONE, supra note 14, app. at 289. For furt her analysis of th is
passage, see Gary Lawson & Patricia B. Gr anger, The “Proper” Scope of Federal
Power: A Jurisdictional Interpretation of the Sweeping Clause, 43 DUKE L.J. 267, 302-
03 (1993) (arguing that prior to adopt ion of Bill of Rights, all natural
rights—including the right to arms—were protected by the Necessary and Proper
claus e).
64. See 1 BLACKSTONE, supra note 14, app. at 289.
But if congress may use any means, which they choose to adopt, the
provision in the constit ution which secures to the pe ople th e right of bearing
arms, is a m ere n ullity; and a ny man impri son ed for bearing arms under
such an act, m ight be with out r elief; because in tha t case, no court could
have any power to pronounce on the necessity or propriety of the means
adopted by con gress t o car ry an y sp ecifie d power into com plete effect .
Id.
65. S ee, e.g., CRAMER, supra note 1, at 69; HALBROOK, THAT EVER Y MAN BE
ARMED, supra note 1, at 53, 90, 99; Dowlut, The Right to Arms, supra note 1, at 83-
84; Gottlieb, supra note 1, at 130-31; Ha lbrook, supra note 19, at 20-26; Kates,
Handgun Proh ibit ion, supra note 1, at 241-43; McAffee & Quinlan, supra note 1, at
867-68; Powe, supra note 1, at 1369-70.
disarmany person” because disarmament could never be
necessary and proper”:
62
If, for example, congress wer e to pass a law prohibiting any
person from bea rin g arms, as a means of preventing
insurrections, the judicial courts, under the construction of the
words necessa ry an d proper, here conten ded for, wou ld be able
to pronounce decidedly upon the constitutionality of these
means.
63
Tucker continued his reasoning, using the example of
Congressional disarmament as an illustration for the necessity
of judicial power to declare laws unconstitutional.
64
St. George Tucker appears regularly in Standard Model
articles discussing the Second Amendment.
65
It is perhaps
significa nt that none of the anti-individual writers even admit
Tucker’s existence, let alone attempt to address the meaning of
the m ost impor tant law book of t he E arly Republic.
Suppose that the gun prohibition lobbies’ claims were
correct and the Second Amendment plainly guara nteed only a
state’s right to raise a militia. If such were the case, it is indeed
strange that not one of th e architects of t he Constitution offered
any objection to St. George Tucker . Mos t of the framers of the
Const itution, including Madison, were alive in 1803 and
actively engaged in public affairs. Many were lawyers, and it
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1381
66. Tucker’s Bla ckstone was a five-volume tr eatise, in pa rallel with the original
Blackstone. Only Tu cker’s additions, not the origina l Blackstone, were new, and
therefore potentially controver sial. Tu cker’s writin gs on constitutiona l subjects would
have been especially like ly to dra w the at tention of the lawyers, including Madison,
who ha d wr itt en th e Con st itu tion .
67. See Hous ton v. Moore, 18 U .S. (5 Wh ea t.) 1 (18 20).
68. Id. at 2-3.
would have been difficult for them to fail to notice the leading
lawyer’s book in the United States. Tucker presents an
interpretation of the Second Amendment that the anti-
individualists would find wrong in every respect: the right is
individual, not a states right; it belongs to everyone, not ju st
militia members; its purposes include defense against tyranny
and hunting. And yet, not one of the framers stepped forward to
correct Tucker’s flagitious misunderst anding of the Second
Amendment. Is it reasonable t o infer that Tucker—far from
grossly misunderstanding the Second Amendmen t—was merely
restating a universal understanding?
66
Might Madison s opinion
of Tucker’s legal scholarship be inferred from Ma dison s
appointment of Tucker to the Federal bench in 1813?
B. Houston v. Moore
The War of 1812 was unpopular in the Northeast, and many
people resisted orders to muster for milit ia service. Houston v.
Moore grew out of a prosecution under Pen nsylva nia law for
failure to perform federal militia duty.
67
In 1814, the Pen nsylvania legislature enacted a bill
providing that “ever y non-commissioned officer and priva te of
the militia who shall have neglected or refused to serve when
called into actual service” by the President should be punished
according to the terms of th e federal militia law of 1795. The
Pennsylvania law specified that persons accused of violating
the law would be tried by a state court-martial.
68
On July 4, 1814, President Madison, acting through the
Secretary of War, told the Governor of Pennsylvania to supply
militiamen for service in the war against Great Britain. The
Pennsylvania militia wa s t o be sent to guard Baltimore and the
Delaware River against expected British attack. (Napoleon s
recent defeats in Europe had freed the main force of the British
army for war against t he United States.)
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1382 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
69. U.S. CONST. art. I, § 8, cl. 15.
70. Id. at cl. 16.
71. See U.S. CONST. amend. X.
72. See Hou ston , 18 U.S. at 7-12.
73. See id. at 21-24.
Houston refused to serve, was eventually tried by a state
court-martial, and fined. He sued in state court to have his fine
overturned, lost, and eventually brought the case to the United
States Supreme Court.
Houston argued that the Pennsylvan ia law was
unconstitutional because Article I, Section 8, Clauses 15 and 16
of the Constitution make Congress the authority over the
militia. Clause 15 gives Congress the power “To provide for
calling forth the Militia to execute the Laws of the Union,
suppr ess Insurrections and repel Invasions.”
69
Clause 16 gives Congress the power “To provide for
organizing, arming, a nd disciplin ing, t he Militia, and for
governing such Part of them as may be employed in the Service
of the United States, reserving to the States respectively, the
Appointment of the Officers, and the Authority of training the
Militia accordin g to the discipline prescribed by Congress.”
70
Houston’s lawyer reasoned that the Congressional power over
the national militia is plenary and, therefore, states could not
legislate on the subject.
Pennsylvania’s lawyers r espon ded t hat Congressional power
over the militia was concurrent with state power, not exclusive.
They point ed to the Tenth Amendment, which reserves to
states all powers not granted to the federal government.
71
Further, they said, the Pennsylvania statute punishing militia
resisters was consistent with the similar federal statute
punishing resisters.
72
The Supreme Court’s opinion was delivered by J ustice
Bushrod Wash ington, a nephew of George Wash ington. J ust ice
Washington concluded that, as a general principle, federal
legislation regarding the militia was exclusive. Since Congress
had enacted a law punishing militia resisters, the states cou ld
not enact their own laws about militia resisters.
73
But, continued J ustice Washington, the instant case was
different. Here, the question was whether a Pennsylvania
court-martial could enforce the federal law. Yes, answered
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1383
74. See id. at 24-31.
75. See id. at 32.
76. “It is not very easy,” Justice Johnson began , “to form a distinct idea of what
the question in this ca se really is.” Id. at 32. In deed, Houston v. Moore could
supplant Pennoyer v. Neff, 95 U.S. 714 (1877), as the ideal case law professors could
use to baffle first-day law students—if law professors consider ed th e milit ia as
interesting as in rem jur isdiction.
77. See Hou ston , 18 U.S. a t 42-45 (J ohns on, J ., con cur ri ng ).
78. 32 U.S. (7 P et.) 243 (1833).
79. This was the only time that Justice Story dissented from a constitutional
decis ion in which Chief Justice Marshall was in the majority. S ee JAMES MCCLEL LAN,
JOSEPH STORY AND THE AMERICAN CONSTITUTION 311 n. 161 (197 1).
80. See Hou ston , 18 U.S. at 53-54.
81. See id. at 60-65.
Justice Washington, since the Congressional law creating
federal court-martials for militia resisters did not forbid states
from enforcing the federal law. And the Pennsylvania statute
did not create a new law, but merely enforced the federal one.
74
Thus, the Pennsylvania conviction was upheld.
75
Justice William Johnson agreed with the result, but wrote a
separate opinion explaining his reasoning.
76
Analyzing bot h the
federal militia law and the particular militia order to which
Houston had been subject, Justice Johnson concluded that
Houston could not be prosecuted by the federal governmen t for
violating the federal militia law. Accor dingly, Houst ons
prosecution by Pennsylvania did not interfere with any federal
powers.
77
Justice Johnson’s opinion treated the Fifth
Amendment double jeopardy clause as enforceable against the
state of Pennsylvan ia; his opinion was the foundation of
nineteenth century argument that, Barron v. Baltimore
78
notwithstanding, the Bill of Rights did apply to the states.
Justice Joseph Story dissented.
79
Because Congress had
enacted exten sive m ilitia legislation, in cluding legislation
punishing militia resisters, its authority was exclusive.
80
A
state could not legislate with regard to militia resisters. Federal
militia control began wh en the Presiden t called for th the
militia, not wh en the militiamen must ered at the rendezvous
spot.
81
Part of Justice Story’s dissenting opinion addressed a
hypothetical: What if Congress, instead of exercising its
constitutional power over the militia, neglected the militia? In
case of Congressional inaction, wrote Justice Story, the states
could act:
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1384 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
82. Id. at 52-53.
83. In regard to int er st at e com merce, J us tice St ory took a d ifferent posit ion: t he
mere existence of a federal power over interstate commerce preempted any state
regulat ion of inter sta te commer ce. S ee New York v. Miln, 36 U.S. (11 Pet.) 102, 157-
61 (1837). The Miln opinion was quoted, for a different point, in another Suprem e
Court gun case, United States v. Cruikshank, 92 U.S. 542, 553 (1876). See infra text
accompanying note 365.
84. See Hou ston , 18 U.S. at 7-12. Others were concerned that the federal power
to arm and discipline the militia would entirely displace th e st at e pow er to do so.
See Pa tr ick He nr y, Vir gin ia Con ven ti on Deba te of J un e 5, 1788, reprinted in ORIGIN,
supra note 37, at 373-74; Patrick Henr y, Virginia Convention Deba te of June 9, 1788,
repr inted in ORIGIN, supra not e 37, at 380-8 1; George Ma son , Virginia Conve nt ion
Debate of June 14, 1788, reprinted in ORIGIN, supra note 37, at 401-02; Patrick
Hen ry, Virginia Conven tion Debate of J une 14, 1788, reprinted in ORIGIN, supra note
37, at 406, 410.
If, th er efore, the pre sent ca se tu rn ed upon th e qu estion ,
wheth er a State might organize, a rm , an d discipline it s own
militia in the absence of, or su bordin at e to, th e r egu lation s of
Congress, I am certainly not prepared to deny the legitimacy
of such an exercise of authority. It does not seem repu gnan t in
its nature to the grant of a like paramount authority to
Congress; and if not, then it is retained by the States. The fifth
[sic] am en dm en t t o th e constitu tion , declaring that “a well
regulated militia being necessary to the security of a free
State, th e righ t of the people to keep an d bea r a rm s shall not
be infrin ged ,” ma y not, perhaps, be thought to have any
important bearing on this point. If it have, it confirms an d
illustrates, rather than impugns the reasoning already
suggested.
82
Justice Story’s hypothetical, fifty-two pages into the case,
marks the first appearance of the Second Amendmen t in
Supreme Court jurisprudence. Justice Story’s main point was
that the state exercise of militia power would not be
inconsistent with Congressional militia power, since
(hypothetically) Congress would be ignoring the militia.
83
After
conceding that the Second Amendment (dubbed the “fifth”
amendment in a typo) was probably irrelevant, Justice Story
suggested that to the extent the Second Amendment was
relevant, it supported his position. J ust ice Story’s point was n ot
unreasonable. The entire Bill of Rights, after all, was animated
by fear of feder al abuse, and several of the Anti-Federalists
raised concerns that the federal government might totally
neglect the militia and thereby render it useless.
84
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1385
For federa list re assu ra nces t ha t t he st at es r etain ed con cur re nt power t o ar m and
discipline the militia, which could be used in case of federal neglect, see An Im partial
Cit izen , VA. GAZ., Mar . 13, 1788, reprinted in ORIGIN, supra note 37, at 299 ; Rich ard
Henry Lee, Virginia Convent ion Deba te of J une 9, 1788, reprinted in ORIGIN, supra
note 37, at 382-83; John Marsh all, Virginia Convention Debate of Jun e 16, 1788,
repr inted in ORIGIN, supra note 37, at 426.
85. See Hen igan , supra note 12, at 22 (“[Ame rican colonists] sough t in the Bill
of Rights a r ea ffirm at ion of t he rig ht of th e st at es t o ha ve t he ir own armed militia,
composed of ordinary citizens, as a check on th e power of th e sta nd in g arm y.”);
Henigan, Arms, Anarchy, supra note 2, at 116 (“[T]h e Secon d Amen dm en t d id a ffect
some change in the Constitutional scheme; presuma bly the Framers did not adopt the
Bill of Right s in 179 1 with th e in te nt to l ea ve t hing s a s t he y we re in 178 7.”).
86. The reporter s text sum marizes t he argumen ts pr esented by each side. See
id. at 4-12.
87. Hou ston , 18 U.S. at 53. The Supreme Court decided one other militia case
during this period. Writing for a unanimous Court, Justice Story held that the
President’s determination of the need for a m ilitia call-out was not subject t o judicial
review. S ee Ma rt in v. Mott , 25 U.S. (1 2 Wh ea t.) 19, 28-3 9 (18 27).
The lea ding scholar of anti-individual Second Amendment
interpretation, Dennis Hen igan, argues that the Second
Amendment, rather than guaranteeing an individual right,
limits some of the federal powers over the militia granted by
Article I, Section 8.
85
If Heniga ns t heory were true—if t he
Second Amendment were a guarantee of state control over the
militia—then the Second Amendment should have been at the
center of Houston v. Moore. The precise issue in the case was
Pennsylvania’s assertion of authority over the militia. Under
the state power theory of the Second Amendment, the strongest
argument that Pennsylvania’s attorneys could have made
would have been to point to the Second Amendment. But the
Second Amendment never entered their arguments.
86
If the
Second Amendment were understood as a right of state
governments against federal control of the militia, then the
total absence of the Second Amendm ent in the rea son ing of the
state’s attorneys and the pro-state Justices is inexplicable.
Justice Story’s dissent is incongruen t wit h Heniga ns t heory
that the Second Amendment somehow reduces Congress’s
militia powers. In the paragraph following the Second
Amendment hypothetical, Justice Story affirmed that whenever
Congress is actually exercising its Article I powers over the
militia, the power of Congress is exclusive, and there is no room
for any state control,however small.
87
Like the writings of St. George Tucker, the Houston v.
Moore decision is absent from the anti-individual articles.
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1386 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
88. WILLI AM RAWLE, A VIEW OF THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STAT ES OF
AMERICA (1825).
89. See The R aw le R ead ing R oom at Temple University Law Library (visited
Nov. 8, 1998) <http://www.tem ple.edu/departm ent s/lawschool/II-ra wlecollection.h tm >
[herein-after Rawle R ead ing Room ]. Rawle also served as a trustee of the University
of Pennsylvania. See Trustees of the University of Pennsylvania (visited Nov. 23, 1998)
<htt p://www.upenn.edu/AR/1830/trustees.ht ml>.
90. See Cha rles Sum ner Lobinger, William Rawle, in THE DICTIONARY OF
AME RICAN BIOG RAP HY (CD-ROM ed. 1997) [hereinafter DICT. AM. BIO.].
91. Michael G. Collins, Article III Cases, State Court Duties, and the Madisonian
Compromise, 1995 WIS. L. REV. 39, 75. Like Tucker, Rawle was also a friend and
correspondent of Thoma s Jefferson . See Kates, Hand gun Prohibit ion, supra note 1,
at 241 n.159.
92. See D. BROWN, EULOGIUM UPON WILLIAM RAWLE 15 (1837), cited in Kates,
Handgun Proh ibit ion, supra note 1, at 242 n.161.
93. In that capacity, he prosecuted the leaders of the Wh iskey Insur rections. See
Lobinger, supra note 90.
94. Joel Fish ma n, Th e Reports of th e S uprem e Court of Pennsylvania, 87 L.
LIBR. J. 643 , 653 (19 95).
Unlike the Amer ican Blackstone, the 1820 Houston case is not
contemporaneous with the creation of the Second Amendment,
but neither is it far removed from the founding era. And the
implications of the case are just as inconsistent with the anti-
individual theories of the Second Amendment as are the direct
statements made by St. George Tucker.
C. William Rawle
Supplanting Tucker’s Blackstone as the leading American
constitution al treatise was William Rawle’s 1825 A View of the
Constitution of the United States of America.
88
A View of the
Constitution was used, among other places, at the United
States Military Academy at West Point.
89
The treatise enjoyed
sufficient popularity for there to be a second edition, and there
would have been a third had Rawle not passed away in 1836.
90
Like Tucker, Rawle was a distinguished attorney long
before he became aninfluential treatise writer.”
91
Elected to
the Pennsylvania legislature in 1789, Rawle declined George
Washington’s repeated offers to serve as the first Attorney
General.
92
Rawle accepted Washington’s appointment as United
States Attorney for Pennsylvania, however, and held the post
from 1792 to 1800.
93
A pr odigiou s scholar, Rawle authored
many law books in addition to his constitutional treatise,
although the tr eat ise is the only one that rema ins in print
today.[O]ne of the most respected lawyers of the day,”
94
he
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1387
95. See Th e Ra wle Rea di ng Room , supra note 89.
also founded Rawle & Henderson, which is now the oldest law
firm in the United States.
95
Rawle described the Second Amendment at length:
In th e se cond ar ticle, it is declar ed, th at a well regulated
militia is n ecessa ry to th e secu rit y of a free state; a proposition
from which few will dissent. Although in actual war, the
services of regu lar t roop s are confessedly m ore valuable; yet,
while peace prevails, and in the commencement of a war
befor e a r egu lar for ce can be r aised, the m ilitia form the
palladium of the country. They are ready to repel invasion , to
suppress insurrection , and preserve the good or der a nd p ea ce
of government. That they shou ld be well r egu lat ed, is
judiciously add ed . A disor de rly m ilit ia is d isgracefu l to itself,
and dangerous not to the enemy, but to its own country. The
duty of the stat e govern ment is, to adopt such regulation s as
will tend to make good soldiers wit h th e least in te rr upt ions of
the ordinar y and u seful occu pa tion s of civil life. In this all the
Union has a strong and visible interest.
The corolla ry, from th e first position , is, that th e righ t of
th e peop le to k eep a nd bear arm s sh all n ot be in fringed .
The pr ohibit ion is ge ner al. No clau se in th e Constitu tion
could by any rule of construction be conceived to give to
congress a power to disarm th e people. Such a flagitiou s
attempt could only be made under some gener al preten ce by a
state legislatu re. B ut if by a ny blin d p ursu it of inordinate
power, either should attempt it, this am endm ent m ay be
appealed to as a restraint on both.
In most of the countries of Europe, this right does not seem
to be den ied , alth ough it is allowed more or less sparingly,
according to cir cum stan ces. In England, a country which
boasts so much of its freedom, the right was secured to
protestant su bject s on ly, on the revolut ion of 1688; and it is
cau tiou sly described to be that of bear ing ar ms for t heir
defence, “suita ble to t heir cond ition s, and a s allowed by law.”
An ar bitra ry code for the preservat ion of game in th at coun tr y
has long disgra ced t hem. A very sm all pr oportion of the pe ople
bein g pe rm itted to kill it, though for their own su bsisten ce; a
gun or other instrument, used for that purpose by an
unqualified person, m ay be seized or forfeite d. B lacks tone, in
whom we regret that we cannot always trace the expanded
principles of ra tion al libert y, observes however , on this subject,
that the prevention of popular insurrections and resistance to
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1388 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
96. WILLI AM RAWLE, A VIEW OF THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES OF
AMERICA (Leon ar d W. Levy ed., Da Cap o Pre ss 197 0) (2d ed. 1829) (citations and
footnotes omitt ed). N ot a ll of Ra wle’s constitu tion al ana lysis was vindicated by
his tor y. His fin al ch ap ter m ain ta ine d t ha t s ta tes h ave a r ight t o secede fr om t he
Union—a reasonable position in 1825, but one which was dealt a serious blow by
Joseph Story in the next decade and which, whether r ightly or wrongly, was
decisively sett led by th e Union victory in the Civil War. Even when not vindicated
by subsequ ent decades, however, Ra wle is st ill u sefu l for u nder stan din g th e st at e of
Ame ri can legal thinking in the 1820s.
The last sentence in t he quote cited to 3 EDWARD COKE, THE FIRST PART OF THE
INSTITUTES OF THE LAWS OF ENGLAND 160 (Garland Publ. 1979) (1628); 1 WILLI AM
HAWKINS, A TREATISE OF THE PLEAS OF THE CROWN 126 (Garland Publ. 1978) (1716)
(explaining th at th e J ustice of the Peace may requ ire su ret y from per sons wh o “go
about with unusu al Wea pons or Attendan ts, t o the Terror of the P eople”). See RAWLE,
supra note 96, at 126 n .‡. Haw kin s elsew here explained tha t t he 1328 St at ut e of
Northampton (against wearing arms in public) was limited in its construction, so
[t]hat no wearing of Arms is within the mea ning of this Sta tute, unless it
be accompan ied with such Circumstances as are apt to terrify the People;
from when ce it seem s clear ly to follow, That P ersons of Quality ar e in no
Danger of Offendin g ag ain st th is Sta tu te by we ar ing comm on Weapon s, or
having their usual Number of Attendants with them, for t heir Orna ment or
Defence, in su ch Places, a nd upon such Occasions, in which it is the
comm on Fa sh ion t o ma ke us e of them, withou t ca us ing th e leas t Sus picion
of an In te nt ion to com mit a ny Act of Violen ce or Distu rban ce of the Peace.
And from the same Ground it also follows, Tha t P ersons arm ed with privy
Coats of Mail to the Int ent to defend themselves against th eir Adversaries,
are not within the Meaning of the Sta tute, because they do noth ing in
terrorem populi.
S ect. 10. VI. That no Person is with in th e Intention of said Statute, who
arms himself to suppress Rioters, Rebels, or Enemies, and endeavours to
suppress or r esist su ch Dist ur ber s of the Pe ace or Quie t of th e Realm ; for
Persons who so arm themselves, seem to be exempted out of the general
Words of the said Statute, by that Part of the Exception in the beginning
th er eof, which s eem s t o allow all Pe rs ons to arm themselves upon a Cry
made for Arms to keep the Peace, in such Places where such Acts happen.
1 HAWKINS, supra, at 136. It was not surprising that Rawle used Hawkins as an
authority. The Hawkins treatise went through seven editions in the eighteenth
century, and one m ore in the nin eteent h. See A.W.B. Simpson, The Rise and Fall of
the Legal Treatise: Legal Principles and the Forms of Legal Literature, 48 U. CHI. L.
government by disarming the people, is oftener meant than
avowed, by makers of forest an d game laws.
This right ought not, however, in an y governm ent, to be
abused to the disturbance of the pu blic peace.
An assem blage of persons with a rms, for an unlawful
purpose, is an indict ab le offen se, an d even th e carr ying of
arms abroa d by a single individ ua l, attend ed w ith
circumstances giving just reason to fear that he purposes to
make an unlawful use of t hem, would be sufficient cause to
require him to give su rety of the pea ce. If he refused he would
be liable for imprisonment.
96
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1389
REV. 632, 653 (1 981) (n oting that Hawkins sought to interpret the criminal laws
based on pr incipl es of just ice a nd re as onab len ess).
Coke’s treatise was written to defend civil liberties and the common law against
monarchial absolutism. Paraphr asing Ovid, Coke noted that “the laws permit the
taking up of ar ms against ar med persons.” 3 COKE, supra, at 162; see also
HALBROOK, THAT EVER Y MAN BE ARMED, supra note 1, at 19 (citing Ovid, Artis
Amatoriae III (line 492), in 2 OVID 118, 152-53 (J . Mozley transl., 1969) (“The laws
allow ar ms to b e t ak en agai ns t a n a rm ed foe.”)).
97. RAWLE, supra note 96, at 153-54.
98. See id. at 155-61.
99. Id. at 125.
Rawle’s analysis of federal powers over the militia noted the
value of widespread arms ownership to a good militia:
In a people perm itt ed and a ccustomed to bear arms, we
have th e rud iments of a m ilitia, wh ich pr operly cons ist s of
arm ed citizen s, divided int o military bands, and instructed at
least in part in the use of arm s for the purposes of war. The ir
civil occupa tions a re not r elin qu ish ed, except while they are
actually in t he field, and th e inconvenience of with dr aw ing
them from their accustomed labors, abridges the time required
for military instruction. [Rawle then explicated how standing
arm ies, with th eir stronger habits of obedience, usually prove
su perior to m ilitias in th e field .]
. . . .
But notwithstanding their inferiority to soldiers schooled
and practised in the field, gallant actions have been performed
by our militia collectively. T he ca pt ure of a n entire army under
General Burgoyne in 1777, and the celebrated defence of New
Orleans in 1814, wer e chiefly effected by militia.
But however inferior in military estimate to armies
regular ly trained, the militia constitutes one of the great
bulwarks of the nation, and nothing which ten ds to improve
and support it should be neglected.
97
Rawle discussed Houston v. Moore and argued strongly against
thestates’ rights” position on this issue; he suggested that
federal deter mination of the necessit y of a militia call-up was
unreviewable by state governmen ts or by t he courts.
98
Rawle’s high regard for the militia was typical of his time.
He clearly explained that the Second Amendment does not
protect only potential militia members, for “[t]he prohibition is
general.”
99
(Thomas Cooleys treatise, half a century later,
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1390 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
100. THO MAS M. COOLEY, GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW IN THE
UNITED STATES OF AMERICA 298 (Andr ew C. McLa ughlin e d., Litt le, Brown, & Co.
1898) (1880); see also infra note 403 and accompanying text.
101. See Ba rr on v. Baltimore , 32 U.S. (7 Pe t.) 243 , 248-49 (1833).
102. See generally David B. Kopel & Glenn H. Reynolds, Taking Federalism
Seriously: Lopez and the Partial-Birth Abortion Ban Act, 30 CONN. L. REV . 59 (1 997 ).
103. See RAWLE, supra note 96, at 125.
104. See CRAMER, supra note 1, at 69-70; Amar, Fou rteent h A m end m ent , supra
note 1, at 1203-04; Dowlut, The Right to Arms, supra note 1, at 84-85; Gottlieb, supra
note 1, at 131; Kat es, Ha nd gun Prohibit ion, supra note 1, at 242-43; McAffee &
Quinlan, supra note 1, at 869-70.
105. The sole an ti-individua l au th or t o address Rawle is George Anasta plo. See
George Anastaplo, Am end m ent s to th e Con stitu tion of th e United States: A
Commentary, 23 LOY. U. CHI. L.J. 631 (1992). Ana st aplo cha ra cterizes Rawle a s pr o-
regulation, based on Rawles statement: This r ight ought not, h owever, in any
government, to be abused in the distur bance of public peace.” Id. at 691. Anastaplo
then asserts that the modern “proliferation of weapons” disturbs the public peace. Id.
Anastaplo thereby confuses concern about t he a buse of a right into opposition to the
right its elf—as if be ing oppos ed t o spe eding wer e the sa me as bein g opposed to t he
ownership of autom obiles. An asta plo does n ot a ddr ess th e fact t ha t Rawle’s position
on th e Secon d Am en dm en t is e xplicit ly in consis te nt wit h An astopolos claim that the
early repu blic understood the Second Amendment as guaranteeing no individual right.
106. JOSEPH S TORY, COMMENTARIES ON THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES
(Fred B. Rothman & Co. 1991) (1833).
would echo Rawle on the Second Amendment, sta ting “The
Right is General.”
100
)
Writ ing long before Barron v. Baltimore refused to enforce
the Bill of Rights against the states,
101
Rawle considered the
Second Amendment a limit on state and feder al disarmament of
the people. And writing a century and a half before the
Congressional power “to regulate commerce . . . among the
several States” was construed as a power to ban the simple
intrastate possession of firearms,
102
Rawle stated that, even
putting the Second Amendment aside, Congress would have no
power to disarm the people.
103
Like Tucker’s Blackstone, Rawle’s A View of the
Constitution is cited by the Standard Modelers,
104
but is
conspicuously absent from law review articles asserting that
the Second Amendment is not an individual right.
105
D. Joseph Story
The American Republics next major constitutional treatise
was the 1833 Com m entaries on th e Constitution of the Un ited
States,
106
written by Joseph Story while teaching at the
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1391
107. ROBERT COVER, JUSTICE ACCUSED: ANT ISL AVER Y AND THE JUDICIAL PROCESS
238 (1975).
108. See MCCLEL LAN, supra note 79, at 40-41.
109. See RAWLE, supra note 96, at 295-310.
110. MCCLEL LAN , supra note 79, at 42. The treatises, which grew out of lectures
at Harvard, are PROMISSORY NOTES (1845), BILLS OF EXCHANGE (184 3), P ARTNERSHIP
(1841), AGENCY (1839), EQU ITY PLEADINGS (1838), EQUITY JURISPRUDEN CE, 2 vol.
(1836), THE CONFLICT OF LAWS (1834), ON THE CONSTITUTION, 3 vol. (1833), and
BAILMENTS (1832). In th e 1997 m ovie Amistad, retired Justice Harry Blackm un plays
the role of Joseph St ory.
Harvard Law School. Story was the dominant legal figure of
pr e-Civil War Amer ica.
No man eve r w as m ore ste eped in th e la w, in tellect ually and
interpersonally. Professional study, th e com m on elemen t for
bench an d ba r, a tt ain ed n ew levels with Story. He wr ote n ine
important treatises, taught at—virtually created—the
Har vard Law School . . . .
107
President Madison appointed Joseph Story to the Supreme
Court in 1811; at age 32, he was the youngest man ever
nominated.
108
He served on the United States Supreme Court
until 1845. After John Mar shall, no Justice of the early Court is
considered more influential on Supreme Court jurisprudence.
In 1840, Story authored an expanded version of th e
Com m entaries, and also wrote a popularized version, entitled
Familiar Exposition of the Constitution of the Un ited States.
Story’s constitutional treatises differed in important ways from
their predecessors; he was far more enthusiastic about broad
federal powers. Rawle had explicated the authority of states to
secede from the Union.
109
But Story alm ost single-handedly
created the doctrine of an indissoluble Union, a doct rine which
would carry the day intellectually in the North . Each of Story’s
treatises was “a major success” and some were still in use in
the twentieth centur y.
110
1. The Second Amendm ent in S tory’s Commentaries
Story’s commentary on the Second Amendment would later
be quoted in numerous Standard Model law review articles. For
example, the following Story quotation appeared in Sanford
Levinson’s 1989 article The Embarrassing Second Amendment:
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1392 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
111. Compare this language to Tucker’s statement that t he militia “may be
considered as the true palladium of liberty.” 1 BLACKSTONE, supra note 14, app. at
300. Justice Thomas quoted Story’s language in h is concurring opinion in Printz v.
United States, 117 S. Ct . 2365, 238 6 (1997) (T homa s, J ., con cur ri ng).
112. 3 STORY, supra note 106, a t 746, § 1890, quoted in Hen igan , Arms, Anarchy,
supra note 2, at 119, and in Levinson, supra note 1, at 649.
113. See Hen igan, Arms, Anarchy, supra note 2, at 119.
114. 3 STORY, supra note 106, at 746-47, quoted in Henigan, Arms, Anarchy,
supra note 2, at 119-20.
The right of th e citizens to keep an d bear ar ms h as justly been
cons idered as the p alladiu m of th e libertie s of a re pu blic;
111
sin ce it offers a stron g m ora l check against the usurpation and
arbitrary power of rulers; and will generally, even if these are
successful in the first instan ce, enable the people to resist and
triumph over them.
112
In response to Levinson’s quotation of Story in his article,
Dennis Henigan accuses Levinson of purposely omitting the
remainder of Story’s passage, which states:
113
And yet , th ough th is t ru th wou ld seem so clear, and the
im por ta nce of a well regulated militia would seem so
undeniable, it cannot be disguised t hat, a mong the Am erican
people, there is a growing indifference to an y system of militia
discipline, and a strong disposit ion, from a sen se of its
burdens, to be r id of a ll regu lations. H ow it is p ra ctica ble to
keep th e people duly ar med, with out some organization, it is
difficult to see. There is certainly no small danger that
indifference may lead to disgust, and disgust to contempt; and
thus gradu ally un der mine all the protect ion in tend ed b y th is
clause of our national bill of rights.
114
However, nothing in the second part of the passage (quoted
by Henigan) changes the meaning in the first part (quoted by
Levinson). In both parts, Story sought to maintain militias as a
counterweight to a standing army. He bemoaned the declining
interest of the people and their state government s in militia
training. Nothing Story said in the second through fourth
sentences changes the mea ning of Story’s first senten ce, which
asserts that the right to bear arms belongs not to state
governments but tothe citizens.” The purpose of this right is to
deter tyran ny and allow popular revolution to unseat a tyr ant.
Henigan does some selective quoting of his own. While he
chastises Levinson for not quoting a footnote in which Story
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1393
115.
It would be well for American s to reflect upon the passage in Tacitu s, (Hist .
IV. ch. 74): “Nam neque quies sine armis, neque arma sine stipendiis,
neque stipendia sine t ributis, haberi queunt.” Is t here an y escape from a
large standing army, but in a well disciplined militia? Th er e is mu ch
wholesome inst ruction on th is subject in 1 Black. Comm. ch. 13, p. 408 to
417.
3 STORY, supra not e 106, at 747 n .1; see also Hen igan , Arms, Anarchy, supra note 2,
at 120. Henigan mistakenly asserts that the pen ult imat e sent ence is a t ra ns lat ion of
the Tacit us quote. S ee Hen igan, Arms, Anarchy, supra note 2, at 120. Actually, t he
sentence is Story’s own. The Tacitu s quote, t ran sla ted, is : “For th e tra nquillity of
nations cannot be preserved without armies; armies cannot exist without pay; pay
cannot be furnish ed without tribu te; all else is common between us.”
116. See Hen igan, Arms, Anarchy, supra note 2, at 119-20.
117. See supra text accompanying note 96.
118. The footnotes appear in su pport of the t ext quoted by Le vinson . See 3
STORY, supra note 106, at 746, nn .1-2 (citing “I T u ck er ’s B la ck . C om m . App . 2 99 ” a nd
“1 Tucker’s Black Comm . App. 300; Rawle on Const. ch. 10, p. 125; 2 Lloyd’s Debates
219, 220”). The last cited sou rce, Lloyd’s Debates, was a record of discussion in
Congress. Justice Story’s citation is to the First Congress’s debate of August 17, 1789,
regarding the Second Amendment. On the cited pages, the House has gone int o a
Committee of the Whole. The text of t he am endm ent u nder considera tion re ads: “A
well regulated milit ia, composed of th e body of th e pe ople, being th e best secu rity of
a free st at e; the right of th e people to keep and bear a rms shall not be infringed, but
no pers on, being r eligiously scrupulous, shall be compelled to bear arm s.” 2 THOMAS
LLOYD , THE CONGRESSION AL REGIST ER; OR, HISTORY OF THE PROCEEDINGS AND DEBATES
OF THE FIRST HOUSE OF REPRESENTATIVES OF THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA 219-21
(N.Y., Hodge , Alle n, & Ca mp bel l 1789).
Massachusetts Representative Elbridge Gerry began:
This declaration of rights, I t ake it, is intended to secure the people
against the mal-administrat ion of the government; if we could suppose that
in all cases the right s of the people wou ld be at te nd ed t o, th e occasion for
guards of this k ind would be rem oved. Now I am appreh ens ive, sir, that
this clause would give an oppor tunity to the people in power to dest roy the
constit ut ion itself. They can declare who are those religiously scrupulous,
and prevent them from bearing arms.
What, sir, is the use of a m ilitia? I t is to pre ven t t he est ablish me nt of
a sta nding army, the ba ne of liberty. Now it must be evident, that under
this provision , togethe r w ith t he ir oth er powe rs , congress cou ld t ak e such
measures with respect to a militia, as make a sta nding army necessary.
Whenever governm ent mea n to invade the rights and liberties of the people,
they always attem pt to destr oy the m ilitia, in order to r ais e an a rm y upon
their ruins. This was actually done by Great Br itain at the commencement
of the lat e revolution. Th ey used every means in their power to prevent the
establishment of an effective militia t o th e ea st ward. Th e asse mb ly of
Massachusetts, seeing the rapid pr ogress th at administ ration were makin g,
denounced standing armies,
115
Henigan omits two other Story
footnotes
116
citing passages from Tucker and Rawle
117
enthusiastically praising the wide scope of the in dividu al right
to keep and bear arms.
118
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1394 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
to divest them of their inherent privileges, endeavored to counteract th em
by the organization of the militia, but they were always defeated by the
influence of the crown.
Id. at 220. Rep. Seney then asked whether there was an issue before the committee
of the whole. Rep. Gerry
[r]eplied, that he meant to make a motion, as he disapproved of th e words
as they stood. He then proceeded, No attempts that they made, were
successful, until they engaged in th e struggle which emancipated th em at
once from their thraldom. Now, if we give a discretionary power to exclude
those from militia duty who have religious scruples, we may as well make
no provision on this head; for this reason he wished the words to be altered
so as to b e con fined to persons belon gin g to a re ligiou s se ct, s cru pu lous of
bearing arms.
Id. Rep. J ackson moved that an exemption from militia duty be gra nted “upon pa ying
an equivalent to be est ablished by law.” Id. at 221 (Lloy d’s use of “f” for “s” changed
to reflect modern usage). The same material is also in House of Representatives
Debates of August 17, 1789, reprinted in ORIGIN, supra note 37, at 695-96. Lloyd’s
records of Congressiona l debates were not full transcripts, but rather his embellished
reconstructions of th e spee ches h e t hou ght m ost inte re sting; m an y pers ons accu sed
Lloyd of inaccur at e r epre sent at ions of t he debates. S ee Mar ion Tin ling, Thomas
Lloyd’s Reports of the First Federal Congress, 18 WM. & MARY Q. 3D 519, 531-33
(1961).
In following pages (not cite d by S tor y), the Hou se n ar rowly r eject ed a mot ion t o
delete the ent ire exempt ion for th e religiously scr up ulou s a nd lea ve exem ptions for
pacifists dependent on the beneficence of the legislatur e.
Rep. Gerry then moved to amend the first clause to read “a well regulated militia,
trained to arms,” in order to ensure that the governmen t would not neglect militia
training. The motion failed for lack of a second. Rep. Burke moved for an additional
amendment, denouncing st an din g ar mies, an d requ iring two-th irds vote from both
houses for a standing army to be raised. The motion was defeated. The House spent
the remainder of the day debating the proposals which beca me th e Th ird, F our th ,
Fifth, an d Sixth Amendmen ts. See 2 LLOYD , supra, at 221-29.
As we shall see below, Gerry’s view that the Second Amendments overarching
purpose was to guarantee the survival of the state militia was widely sha red by
nineteenth century courts and commentators. Like Justice Story, most of the courts
and comm en ta tor s saw not hing incons ist en t in t he Ame nd me nt s pur pose t o pr otect
the militia (e xtolled by Gerr y, Tu cker, a nd Rawle, all of whom were cited by St ory)
and the Amendments protection of firearms ownership for personal uses (specifically
mentioned by Tuck er an d Ra wle , and cited by S tor y).
119. See Andrews v. State, 50 Tenn. (3 Heisk.) 165, 183-84 (1871), discussed infra
in text a ccompanying notes 210-227.
The above passages from Justice Story were quoted by an
1871 Tennessee Supr em e Court opinion as authority for the
exact point that the Second Amendment, in order to secure a
militia, guarantees a general right of individuals to have
weapons.
119
Story concluded by contrasting the strong right in America
with the weak one in England:
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1395
120. 3 STORY, supra note 106 , a t 747 (footn ote s om itte d).
121. See Madison, supra note 37.
§ 189 1. A similar p rovision in favour of prot esta nts (for to
them it is con fined) is to be found in the bill of rights of 1688, it
bein g declare d, “that t he subjects , wh ich are protestants, may
have ar ms for th eir defence su ita ble to t heir cond ition , an d a s
allowed by la w.” But under various pretences the effect of th is
pr ovision has been greatly n ar rowed; a nd it is a t presen t in
England more nominal than real, as a defensive privilege.
120
Here, Story closely t racked Madison s n otes on the Second
Amendment, in wh ich Madison contrasted the Second
Amendment with the narrower English right, the latter being
unsatisfactory because it was confined to Protestants.
121
2. The Second Amendm ent in S tory’s Familiar Exposition
Story’s 1840 const itutional la w book intended for a popular
audience, Fam iliar Exposition of the Con stitution of the Un ited
States, contains some Second Amendment material not found in
the Com m entaries. The Familiar Exposition removes any
possible doubt that Story saw the Second Amendment as
guaranteeing an important individual right:
The next amendment is, “A well-regula ted m ilitia bein g
necess ary to the secu rity of a free state, the right of the people
to keep an d bea r a rm s shall not be in frin ged .” One of t he
ord inary modes, by which tyrants accomplish their purposes
without re sista nce, is, by disa rm ing the people, and m aking it
an offence to keep arms, and by substituting a regular ar my in
the stead of a resort to the militia. The friends of a free
government cannot be too watchful, to overcome the dangerous
tendency of th e public m ind t o sacrifice, for the sake of mere
private conven ien ce, this powerfu l check upon th e design s of
ambitious men.
The importance of this article will scarcely be doubted by
any persons, who have duly reflect ed upon the subject. The
militia is the natural defence of a free country against sudden
foreign invasions, dom est ic insur rections, and dom estic
usurpations of power by rulers. It is against sou nd p olicy for a
free people to keep up large military esta blishments and
standing ar mies in tim e of pe ace, both from th e en orm ous
expenses, with which they are attended, and the facile means,
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1396 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
122. JOSEPH STORY, A FAMILIAR EXPOSITION OF THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED
STA TES 264-65 (1842) (quotin g U.S CONST. am en d. I I).
123. Henigan, Arms, Anarchy, supra note 2, at 120.
124. Id.
How can the militia be a collection of citizens wit h the const itutionally
guaranteed right to engage in armed resistance against t heir government
if the Constitution itself grants Congress the power t o call out the m ilitia
“to execute the laws of the Union [and] suppress insurrections . . . .”? The
Constitu tion cann ot view th e militia both as a means by which government
can suppress insurrection and as an instrument for insurrection against the
which th ey a fford to a mbitious a nd u npr incipled r uler s, to
subvert th e governmen t, or tr am ple u pon th e r igh ts of the
people. The right of the citizens to keep and bear arms has
justly been considered, as t he p alla dium of th e lib er ties of a
re pu blic; sin ce it offers a strong moral check against the
usurpation and arbitrary power of rulers; and it will generally,
even if these are successful in the first instance, enable the
people to r esist an d t riu mph over th em . And yet, though t his
truth wou ld seem so clear, and th e im portance of a well-
regulated militia would seem so unden iable, it cannot be
disguised, th at am ong th e Am erican people th ere is a grow ing
indifference to any system of m ilitia disciplin e, a nd a stron g
disposition , from a sense of its bur den s, to be rid of all
regu lation s. How it is pr act icable to keep th e pe ople duly
arm ed withou t some organizat ion, it is difficult to see. There is
certainly no small danger, that indifference may lead to
disgust, and disgust to contempt; and thu s gr ad ua lly
undermine all the protection intended by this clause of our
National Bill of Rights.
122
Can any fair-minded r eading of J ust ice Story support
Henigan’s position that the federal government has the
unquestioned constitutional authority to outlaw the possession
of firearms in the United St ates? Or would Story bemoan
Henigan’s organization—whose members were never required
by their state governments to possess arms and to learn how to
use them in militia dr ill—as fulfilling Story’s fears “that
indifference may lead to disgust, and disgust to contempt”?
One of Henigan’s central errors is hiseither/or” view of the
militia. Story saw the militia as a defense “against . . . domestic
insurrections.”
123
Henigan finds t his insu rrection-su ppression
view to be “itself inconsistent with the notion that the militia is
the armed citizenry poised to engage in domestic
insurrection.”
124
But Story also exulted that when “citizens” are
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1397
government . It must be one or the other.
Id. at 115. Henigan ignores the fact that his sta tes r ight t he ory implie s a rig ht of
state governments to revolt against t he federal gover nm en t. He ni gan’s t he ory (if h e
actu ally believed it as a matter of constit utional interpretat ion, rather than as a
defense against the Standard Model) would thereby repr esent post hoc justificat ion
for th e Confederate t heor y of secession in the Civil War. S ee Lun d, Past and Future,
supra note 1, at 31-32 n.72.
125.
In the next place, the actual m oral and intellectual power, and even
ph ysical power, of the state in its present organization, may be so combined
in the st ructure of the government, that they ma y present insu pera ble
barriers to an y chan ge. If, for instance, the whole of the privileged classes
should happen to be the only edu cated persons in the na tion; if th e whole
priesth ood should depen d upon the governmen t for its influence and
support, and its exclusive patronage and privileges; if th e wh ole we alt h of
the comm un ity sh ould be lod ged in a few h an ds, an d thos e few should be
the ver y hea ds of the government; if the military power should be so
organ ized, th at it could scar cely find th e m eans , or possess th e power , to act
except under the existing arrangements;—in any, and in all of these cases,
it is easy to perceive, that there would be immen se difficulties in
introducing any fundamental and salutary change. It could scarcely take
pla ce but u pon som e genera l convuls ion, which could break asunder all the
comm on ties of society.
Joseph Stor y, Natural Law (1836), reprinted in MCCLEL LAN, supra note 79, at 318-19.
126. See MCCL ELL AN, supra note 79, at 6. Like many other legal analysts of his
era, Story believed in a n atural-law right to self-defense since “self-preservation” was
one of th e du ties th at ea ch m an na tu ra lly h ad to h im self. “[A] man h as a p er fect
right to his life, to his personal libe rt y, a nd to h is p rop er ty; an d h e m ay by for ce
assert and vindicate those rights against ever y aggressor .” Story, supra note 125, at
314-15.
127. As Alexander Hamilton wrote:
If the federal government should overpass the just bounds of its authority
and make a tyrannical us e of it s powers , the people , wh ose cre at ur e it [th e
Constitution] is, must appeal to the standard they have formed, and take
such measur es to redress the in jury don e to the Constitution as the
exigen cy may suggest and pr uden ce justify.
THE FEDERALIST NO. 33 (Alexan der H am ilt on). H am ilt on also p re dict ed th at if the
armed, they can resist usurpation; the right to bear arms
allows the “people to resist and triumph over” their oppressors.
Indeed, J ust ice Story explicit ly promoted the dispersion of
armed force in a society as facilitating needed changes in
government.
125
Nor was violent resistance to tyranny an
abstract notion to Story; his father had been one of the Indians
in the Boston Tea Party.
126
The notion that the American people
could be trusted both to suppress illegitimate insurrections and
to overthrow tyranny may seem self-contradictory to late
twentieth-century American antigun lobbyists. But it was an
obvious truth to J ustice Story.
127
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1398 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
federal government attempted to use th e militia to impose tyranny on reca lcitrant
states,whither would the militia” march itself “but to the seat of the tyrants, who
had meditat ed so foolish as well as so wicked a project; to cru sh t hem in their
imagined intrenchments of power and to make them an example of the just
ven gea nce of a n abu sed a n d i nce n sed pe op le ?” T HE FEDERALIST NO. 35 (Alexander
Ha mi lton).
128. See 3 STORY, supra note 106, at 81-95, §§ 1194-1210.
129. See id. at 81, § 1196.
130. Id. at 82, § 119 7 (foot note omitte d).
131. See Eh rm an & Hen igan , supra note 2, at 7.
132. 3 STORY, supra note 106, at 85, § 1202.
133. See id. at 85 n.5 & 86 nn.1-2, § 1202.
3. The federal militia powers in Story’s Commentaries
Story’s treatise also contained an extensive section on the
militia powers in Articles I and II of the Const itution.
128
Story
extolled the militia and explained that while the posse
comitatus (the able-bodied males of the county subject to the
sheriff’s call to enforce the law) would suffice for maintaining
law and order in most situations, there were some
circumstances in which either a militia or a standing army
would be necessary.
129
Story disparaged anti-federalist fears about granting federal
power over the militia. He noted that these fears “produced
some propositions of amendment in the state conventions,
which, however, were never du ly r atified, and h ave long since
ceased to be felt, as matters of general concern.”
130
Here, Story
directly undermined Henigan’s theory of the Second
Amendment. Henigan claims that the Second Amendment was
a restraint on the federal government’s militia powers.
131
Story
claims that none of the proposals for restrictions on federal
militia powers were ever ratified.
Story then discussed in great detail the division of federal
and state powers over the militia. He suggested, “If congress
did not choose to arm, organize, or discipline the militia, there
would be an inherent right in the states to do it.”
132
In support
of this proposition, Story cited Houston v. Moore, Rawles
treatise, Tucker’s Blackstone, and various portions of E lliots
Debates.
133
While Story’s dissent in Houston v. Moore had
suggested that the Second Amendment, if relevant at all, would
also support this proposition, Story did not in his Com m entaries
cite the Second Amendment for support of state militia powers.
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1399
134. Id. at 87, § 1202.
135. See id. at 87 n.1, § 1202.
136. See David Cobin & P aul Fin kelm an, Introduction to 1 HENRY S T . G EORGE
TUCKER , COMMENTARIES ON THE LAW OF VIRGINIA: COMPRISING THE SUBSTANCE OF A
COURSE OF LECTURES DELIVERED TO THE WINCHEST ER LAW SCHOOL, at i (The Lawbook
Exchange, Ltd. 1998) (3d ed. 1846). He nr y St . Geor ge Tuck er wa s n ot the literal “son”
of St. George Tucker. Henry was actually the child of a distant Bermuda re lative. At
an early age, however, H enry went to live with St. George Tucker, who raised him,
but never form ally a dopted him . See Armistead M. Dobie, Hen ry S t. George T uck er,
in DICT. AM. BIO., supra note 90.
137. Under Tuckers leadership, the Virginia Court–in great contrast to other
Southern cour ts of th e time–often ru led in fa vor of slaves whose manumission had
been legally challen ged. See Cobin & Fink elma n, supra note 136, at xxviii-xxix.
138. See Car rin gton, supra note 19, at 333 n.1.
Story went on to define other state/federal militia
boundaries; he noted that when the militias were not in federal
service, Congress had no power to discipline and train them,
such power being “exclusively vested in the stat es.”
134
For this
proposition, Story cited Federalist 29 and the Tucker and
Rawle treatises (again, not parts dealin g with the Second
Amendment).
135
The treatise continued for eight more sections
to discuss various state/federal militia issues, such as the power
to call th e militia into service, to govern the m ilitia, to court-
martial, and to command the militia. Never once did St ory hint
that the Second Amendment had any relevance to these issues.
If, as Henigan claims, Story read the Second Amendment
the way Henigan does, it is inexplicable how Story’s treatise
could minutely dissect the boundaries of state/federal militia
powers wit hout once m en tioning the Second Amendment. The
only plausible interpretation of Story’s trea tment of the militia
in his Com m entaries is that proposed by t he Standa rd Model of
the Second Amendment, in which the Second Amendment does
not reduce the scope of the Congressional militia powers in
Article I, or the Presidential militia powers in Article II.
E. Other Pre-1850 S ources
1. Henry S t. George Tucker
Henry St. George Tucker was the son of St. George Tucker,
author of Tucker’s Blackstone.
136
The younger Tucker served as
U.S. Representative from Virginia (1815-19), as President of
the Virgin ia Su pr em e Court,
137
and as law professor at the
University of Virginia (1841-45).
138
He declined President
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1400 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
139. See Dobie, supra note 136.
140. TUCKER, supra note 136.
141. Warren M. Billings , Seventeenth-Century Virginia Law and Its Historians,
With an Accom pany ing Gu ide to S our ces, 87 L. LIBR. J. 556, 55 8 (1995).
142. Cobin & Finkelm an, supra note 136, a t v.
143. A small book or m anua l carr ied as a r eference book. See 2 THE NEW
SHORTER OXFORD ENGLISH DICTIONARY 3538 (3d ed. 1993).
144. 1 TUCKER, supra note 41, at 807.
145. Cobin & Finkelm an, supra note 136.
146. 1 TUCKER, supra not e 136, at 42-43. In oth er wr iti ngs, the youn ger Tucker
extolled the na tura l right t o reform or abolish t he gover nm ent , and the natural right
to self-defens e. See HENRY ST. GEORGE TUCKER, A FEW LECTURES ON NATURAL LAW
10-11, 95-99 (1844); HENRY ST. GEORGE TUCKER, LECTURES ON GOVERNMENT 37 (1 844 ).
Jackson’s offer to serve as United States Attorney Genera l.
139
In
1831, he wrote a three volume treatise Comm entaries on the
Law of Virginia.
140
Although he followed Blackstone’s
organization, the tr eat ise was entirely Tucker’s own, and it
represented an important step forward in the development of
distinctly Amer ican law. This treatise “was standa rd fa re for
aspiring lawyers”
141
and was “the primary referen ce source for
the bar of Virginia” until the Virginia Code was adopted in
1850.
142
Tucker had created the “vade mecum
143
of the bar of
Virginia. . . . It was recognized by the bar of Virginia, and in
many of the Souther n St ates, as t he m ost valuable text -book for
students and lawyers then in existence.”
144
Tucker’s work
established the standard for American treatise writing, helped
organize American law, and provided access to it for attorneys
distant from law librar ies.”
145
Explainingthe principal absolute rights of individuals,
Tucker wrote:
[C]ertain protections or barriers have been er ected wh ich serve
to mainta in inviola te th e three prim ar y rights of per son al
security, personal liberty, an d priva te proper ty. These m ay in
America may be said to be:
1. Th e Bill of Rights an d w rit ten Con stitu tion s . . . .
2. Th e righ t of bea rin g arm s—w hich wit h us is not limited
and restrained by an ar bitr ar y system of gam e laws, as in
England; but is practically en joyed by every citizen, a nd is
among his most valuable privileges, since it furnishes the
means of resisting, as a freeman ought, the inroads of
usurpation.
3. The right of ap plying to th e court s of just ice for re dr ess
of injuries.
146
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1401
147. 1 TUCKER, supra note 136, at 43.
148. Id.
149. Id.
150. Philip A. Hamburger, Natural Rights, Natural Law, and American
Constitutions, 102 YALE L.J. 907, 953 n .124 (1993); see also BENJ AMIN L. OLIVER, THE
LAW SUMMARY: A COLLECTION OF LEGAL TRACTS ON SUBJECTS OF GEN ERAL
APPLICATION IN BUSINESS (2d e d., Fr ed B. Roth ma n & Co. 1995 ) (183 1).
151. BENJ AMIN L. OLIVER, THE RIGHTS OF AN AMERICAN CITIZEN; WITH A
COMMENTARY ON STATE RIGHTS, AND ON THE CONSTITUTION AND POLICY OF THE UNITED
STATES 174 (1832). The book was cited by the dissent in Harmelin v. Michigan, 501
U.S. 957, 1009-10 (1991) (White, J., dissenting) for the proposit ion that the Eighth
Amendment forbids punish ment s disproportionate to the underlying offense.
152. See Bliss v. Commonw ea lt h, 12 K y. (2 Lit t. ) 90 (1822 ).
If, therefore, the act in question imposes any restraint on the right,
immaterial what appellation may be given to t he act , wh ethe r it be a n a ct
Tucker cont inued, quoting Blackstone’s form ulation of the
English right to arms. Tucker added that this rightis secured
with us by Am. C. U. S. art. 4.”
147
(Lik e some other writers of
the period, Tucker numbered the amendments as they were
when sent to the states for ratification by the first Congress.)
When human right s wer e violated, Tucker concluded, the
citizen was entitled first to justice in the courts, “next to the
right of petitioning for redress of grievances; and, last ly, to the
right of having and using arms for self-preservation and
defence.”
148
While all of the r igh ts Tucker descr ibed were “our
birthright to enjoy entire,” they could be subject to “necessary
restraints” which were “gentle and moderate.”
149
2. Benjamin Oliver
Benjamin L. Oliver was “a writer of law books, a noted
chess player, and son of a former Governor of
Massachusetts.”
150
His 1832 The Rights of an American Citizen
contained a cha pter entitled “Of the righ ts r eserved to the
people of the United St ates; not being gr anted eit her to the
general government, or the state governments.” This chapter
explained the Second Amendment “right of the citizens to bear
arms” as making it possible for a militia to comba t invasion,
insurrection, or usurpation.
151
An 1822 Kentu cky decision, Bliss v. Commonwealth,
interpreted the state’s constitution to find a law against
carrying concealed weapon s (t he fir st Amer ican weapon s
control law of general applicability) to be unconstitutional.
152
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1402 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
regulating the ma nner of bear ing arms or any oth er, the consequen ce, in
re fer en ce to the constitution, is precisely the same, and its collision with
that instrument equally obvious.
Id. at 92. “For, in principle, the re is n o difference between a law prohibiting the
wearing concealed arms [sic], and a law forbidding the wearing such as are exposed;
and if the former be unconstitutional, the latter mu st be so likewise.” Id. “[I]f an y
portion of that right be impaired, immaterial how small the part may be, and
immaterial the order of time at which it be done, it is equa lly forbidden by the
constitution.” Id. at 93.
153. OLIVER, supra note 151, at 176-78.
154. Id. at 178. Anoth er pa ssage described self-defense as a natural right :
There are some other rights, which are reserved to th e people, though
not mentioned in the genera l con st itut ion. Am ong the se is t he ri ght of s elf-
defence, in cases where the dan ger is so imminent, that the person in
jeopardy, may suffer irre pa ra ble injury , if h e waits for th e prote ction of th e
laws. . . . as the compact between him and society is mutual, if society is
unable to p rote ct h im, his n at ur al righ t r evives to p rote ct h im se lf.
Id. at 186. Also, “Of those rights wh ich are u su ally ret ain ed in or gan ized societ y, . . .
[t]h e first an d m os t im po r t a n t of t hes e r ig h t s, i s t ha t of s el f-d ef en ce .” Id. at 40.
155. JAMES BAYARD, A BRIEF EXPOSITION OF THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED
STATES 4 (Fr ed B. R oth ma n & Co. 1 992) (2d e d. 1845 ).
156. Id. at 3.
157. Id. at 147.
Oliver thought that carrying concealed weapons, “if it is really
unconstitutional to restrain it by law, ought to be
discountenanced,” since concealment allowed an antagonist to
surprise a victim.
153
Still, [t]here are without doubt
circumstances, which may justify a man for going armed; as, if
he has valuable property in his custody; or, if he is traveling in
a dangerous part of the country; or, if his life has been
threatened.”
154
3. James Bayard
James Bayard’s A Brief Exposition of the Constitution of the
United States was inten ded a s “a text -book for the in st ruction of
youth.”
155
The book was adopted by some colleges and
seminaries and was praised by Chief Justice John Marshall,
Justice Joseph Story, Chancellor James Kent, “and other
distinguished jurists,” accor ding to the author.
156
The small
book took the reader through the Constitution clause by clause,
offering short explanations of the meaning and background of
each provision.
Bayard wrote that the Second Amendment “secures the
right of the people to provide for their own defence.”
157
This
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1403
158. See U.S. CONST. amend. III: “No Soldier shall, in time of peace be quartered
in an y house, with out th e consen t of t he Own er , nor in time of war, but in a manner
to be pr escribed by law.”
159. BAYARD, supra note 155, at 148.
160. See LOIS G. SCHWOERER, “N O STANDING ARMIES!” THE ANTIMILITARY
IDEOLOGY IN SEVENTEEN TH-C EN TU RY ENGLAND (1974); William S. Fields & David T.
Hardy, The Third Amendm ent and the Issue of the Maint enance of Standing Arm ies:
A Legal History, 35 AM. J. LEGAL HIST. 393 , 402-13 (1991); MALCOLM, supra note 1,
at 6-15.
short statement is not, in isolation, necessarily inconsistent
with the Standa rd Model or wit h the anti-individual theories.
One could read the language, Standard Model-style, as “the
Amendment guarantees the pre-existing right of people to
protect them selves with arms.” Or one could, with a little more
effort, read Bayard’s language Henigan style: “the Amendment
protects state governments from federal interference, so that
the people may be defended by state militias.”
Any confusion arising from Bayard’s ter seness on the
Second Amendment is clarified by his discussion of the Third
Amendment, which prohibits quartering troops in private
homes under most circumstances.
158
Bayard detailed its
historical background: “The people of this country, while under
the dominion of England, had felt too sensibly the evils arising
from the want of arm s . . . not to take every precaution against
their recurrence.”
159
Formally, Bayard’s reference to “the evils arising from the
want of arms” makes no sense in a Third Amendment
discussion. The Third Amendment keeps soldiers out of homes,
but does n othing to pr event “the want of ar ms.Historically,
however, the Second a nd Third Amendments were closely
linked, and they a re placed next to each other because both
were intended as checks against the dangers of militaristic
tyranny on the part of the central government. The
disarmament of individual citizens, the replacement of th e
militia by a standing arm y, and the abuses of a standing army
(including the forced quartering of soldiers in private homes)
were closely linked to the abuses of King Ch arles I, which
precipitated the English Civil War,
160
whose history the
Americans knew well—especially since similar abuses helped
precipitate the American Revolution. As the Founders also
knew from reading Mon tesquieu and ot her s, the quartering of
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1404 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
161. See Kat es, Self-Protecti on, supra note 1, at 100 (“As Englishmen a nd
Ame ri can s were well aware from their reading of Bodin, Beccaria and Montesquieu,
the Huguenots had been rendered incapable of resisting either individually or as a
group by t he Con tine nt al policy of di sa rm ing all but th e Ca th olic n obilit y.”).
[T]h e most at rocious–and effective–were the dr agon na des , or billet ing of
dragoons on Hu guen ot families with encouragem ent to behave a s viciously
as they wished. Notoriously rough a nd u ndisciplined, the en list ed t roop s of
the dragoons spread carnage, bea ting and robbing the householders, r apin g
the women , sma shin g and wrecking an d leaving filth . . . .
BARBARA W. TUCH MAN , THE MARCH OF FOLL Y 21 (198 4).
162. See Steven Alan Sa mson, Francis Lieber on the Sources of Civil Liberty, 9
HUMANIT AS 1-2 (1996) (visited Mar. 16, 1998) <http://www.nh umanities.org/
samson.ht m>.
163. See id.; FRANCIS LIEBER, ON CIVIL LIBERTY AND SELF-GOVERNMENT 5
(Theodor e D. Woolsey ed., Da Ca po Pr ess 1972) (3d ed. 1877).
soldiers was one of the major abuses perpetrated against the
disarmed French Huguenots by Louis XIV in the 1690s.
161
Thus, it was not unreasonable for Bayard to address the
problems of centralized militarism in one u nified discussion.
Knowingthe evils arising from the want of arms, the
Americans took “every precaution against their recurrence,”
and it is therefore impossible to read Bayard as supporting
Henigan’s theory tha t the federal government may
constitutionally disarm the American people.
4. Fran cis Lieber
One of the most important of America’s early political
scientists was Francis Lieber, a German immigrant. He taught
history, political science, and public law at South Carolina
College, Columbia College, and Columbia Law School. H is code
of military conduct for land warfare, written for the Union
Army during the Civil War, later became part of the Geneva
and Hague Conventions.
162
Lieber’s main contribution, however,
was his analysis of how a society could create complex
institutional structures to promote civil liberty; the fullest
exposition of his political thought is found in his book On Civil
Liberty and Self-Govern m ent, first published in 1853.
163
In the penultimate paragraph of a chapter discussing
control of standing armies and the Third Amendment, Lieber
wrote:
Akin to the last-m en tioned gu ara nte e, is th at w hich
secures to every citizen the right of possessing and bearing
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1405
164. LIEBER, supra note 163, at 120 (quoting U.S. CONST. amend. II). Lieber’s
Secon d Amendment quotation wa s, of cour se, slight ly in er ror . Th e wor d “upon” is n ot
part of the Am endmen t. See also Fr ancis Lieber , Anglican and Gallican Liberty, in
2 THE MISCELLANEOUS WRITINGS OF FRANCIS LIEBER 373-75 (David C. Gilman ed.,
1880); Samson, supra note 162 (discussing the fact that Lieber listed the righ t to
arms and the right t o resist un la wfu l a ut hority as am ong the es sent ial r igh ts of a
society in wh ich civil liber ty is s ecu re ).
A sout her n reviewer of another Lieber book, Ma nu al of Politica l E th ics (1839),
used the review to defend slavery under t he Constitution; the reviewer included the
right to arms in a litany of individual rights that the Constitution guar anteed to free
men:
To the people, the habeas corpus act, th e trial b y jury, th e exemption fr om
excessive bail, and the quartering of soldiers, and the right t o keep and
bear arms, was secured; but these privileges only applied to free pe ople, and
not to per sons held to ser vice or labor in one State, wh o might escape into
another . . . .
Lieber’s Politica l E th ics, 24 S. Q. REV. 464, 481 (Oct. 1847).
165. For the sak e of complet enes s, two oth er t rea tises written before th e Civil
arm s. Our constitution says: The right of the people to keep
and bear arms shall not be infringed upon; and the [English]
Bill of Rights secured th is right to every protestant. It extends
now to every English subject. It will hardly be necessary to
add, that laws prohibiting se cre t w ea pon s, or th ose wh ich
necessarily endanger th e lives of the citizens, are no
infringement of libert y; on t he contra ry, liberty r est ing
necessa rily on law, and lawful, that is, peaceful state of t he
citizens, libert y itself requ ire s t he su ppression of a re turn to
force an d violence among the citizens—a fact by no means
su fficien tly weigh ed in recen t t im es in Am er ica.
164
Lieber recognized the individual right ofevery citizen” to
bear arms; he did not even quote the m ilit ia clause of th e
Second Amendment. Unlike Tucker, Rawle, and Story, who
distinguished the br oad American righ t to ar ms from its feeble
English ancestor, Lieber saw the English right as robust and
identical to the American right. (Lieber’s general theme was to
contrast the strong rights in Anglo-American law with the weak
or non-existent rights in France and the rest of Europe.) The
endorsement of concealed weapon s control laws, followed by the
complaint about American attitudes, might reflect the fact that
outside the Southeast and the state of Indiana, there were no
concealed weapons laws or any other sort of gun control at all.
And, as Lieber ruefu lly recogn ized, Amer icans were often too
quick to resort to private revenge, rather than to the judicial
system.
165
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1406 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
War should be ment ioned. Maurice Richter s 1859 The Municipalist examined the
relationship between local and feder al power . H e a rgue d t ha t m an y pr ovision s of t he
Bill of Rights would make sense in Eu rope as restraint s on central power, but that
these provisions were of no use in the United Sta tes, since the national governmen t
had no affirmative power to violate those rights. Thus, for the Second Amendment,
Richter wrote, “Good for Europe. We have read t he dispositions of the const itution [in
Article I] about the militia. Congress has no power to legislate on the keeping and
bearing of a r m s, e xcep t in th e D is tr ict of C ol u m bi a.” M AURICE A. RICHTER, INTE RNAL
RELATIONS OF THE CITIES, TOWNS, VILLAGES, COUNTIES, AND STATES OF THE UNION; OR
THE MUNICIPALIST : A HIGHLY USEFUL BOOK FOR VOTERS, TAX-P AYERS, STATESMEN,
POLITICIANS AND FAMILIES 133 (N.Y., Ross & Tousey, 2d ed. 1859), availabl e online
<htt p://moa.umdl.umich.edu/cgi-bin/moa/sgml/moa-idx?notisid=AEW4742)>.
William Duer’s lectures on the Constitution at Columbia College in the 1830s
were published as WILLI AM ALEXANDER DUER, A COURSE OF LECTURES ON THE
CONS TITU TION AL JURISPRUDENCE OF THE UNITED STATES (Burt F ranklin Pr ess 1971)
(1856). Duer’s lengthy analysis of federal militia powers and sta ndin g armies said
nothing about the Second Amendmen t. S ee id. at 196-210. H is discu ssion of
constitutional amendments amounted to summary qu ota tion s of Amendm ents four
through eight , with no ment ion of Amendments one t hrough th ree, nine, or ten. Id.
at 39-40. His discussion of natur al rights par aph rased Blackstone’s th ree primary
rights (personal security, personal liberty, an d priva te pr opert y) and five auxiliary
rights (legislative authorit y; limits on the king’s prerogat ive; the right to apply to
cour t for redress of injury, and the associated rights of trial by jury and habeas
corpus; the righ t to petit ion; an d “of keep ing arm s for defen ce; which was, in deed, a
public allowan ce, under certain restr ictions, of the natural right of resistance and self-
pre serv at ion”). Id. at 36-37. Duer’s list of Blackstone’s auxiliary rights contained a
footn ote to the Seventh Amendment for “ Trial by J ur y.” There wa s no cita tion to
Article I for ha bea s cor pus, t o th e F irst Amend ment for t he right to petition, nor to
the Second Am endmen t for the r ight to ar ms. See id.
A footnote concerning the auxiliary right to arms discussed a Kentucky case
holding a law against wear ing concealed arms void under th e Kent uck y Const itu tion
and likewise voiding a law against free blacks defending themselves against white
aggressors. See id. at 37 n .1; see also infra text accompanying notes 394-95.
Regarding the self-defen se issue, a contr ary case was a lso cited. See id.
166. 1 JONAT HAN ELLIOT, THE DEBATES IN THE SEVERAL STATE CONVENTIONS ON
THE ADOPTION OF THE FEDERAL CONSTITUTION, at xv (2d ed., 2d pr tg . 19 37).
5. Elliot’s Debates
Jonathan Elliots 1836 compilation, The Debates in the
Several State Conventions on the Adoption of the Federal
Constitution, is still the major documentary source for its
subject. ElliotsDigest of the Constitution” indexed the various
Constitutional provisions. Under the index heading “Rights of
the citizen declared to be—,” th ere is a listing forTo keep and
bear arms, and other rights from the first nine amendments.
In contrast, the Tenth Amendment, unquestionably astates’
right, was not included in the heading “Rights of the
Citizen.”
166
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1407
167. Kemp Mallone, Noah Webster, in DICT. AM. BIO., supra note 90.
168. See MARSHALL SMELSER, THE DEMOCRATIC REPUBLIC: 1801-1815, at 32 n.27
(1968).
169. NOAH WEBSTER, A N AMERICAN DICTIONARY OF THE ENGLISH LANGUAGE (182 8).
170. 2 Id. at 54. Similarly, George Cabot—a Federa list and one of the richest
men in New England—wrote that society should function like a “well regulated
family” with “each one learning his proper place and keeping to it.” Robert E.
Shalhope, Individualism in the Early R epublic, in AMERICAN CHAMELEON:
INDIVIDULAISM IN TRANS-NATIONAL CONTE XT 66, 67 (Richard O. Cur ry & Lawrence B.
Goodheart eds., 1991) (citing DAVID H. FISCHER, THE REVOLUTION OF AME RICAN
CONSERVATIVISM (1965)). Thus, in “a well regulated milit ia,” the milit ia-men would
be able t o ma rch an d de ploy for combat in p roper form ations, with each militia-man
knowing his place.
171. See Ran dy E. Ba rn ett , N ecessa ry a nd Prop er, 44 UCLA L. REV. 745, 775
(1997 ). Or as Congressman Daniel Webster explained, regar ding federal power to
“regulate” intern ational commerce, “To regulate . . . could never m ean to destroy.”
ROBERT V. REMINI, DANIEL WEBSTER: THE MAN AND HIS TIME 94 (199 7).
6. Webster’s Dictionary
The legitimacy of the American version of the English
language found its truest champion in Noah Webster. Websters
father served as a captain on the “alarm list” of the militia near
his Hartford farm,
167
and the family strongly supported the
Revolution. Noah Webster’s first major work was the American
Spelling Book (1783), of which millions of copies were
eventually printed. He published his first dictionary in 1806,
the Compendious Dictionary of the English Language.
168
But his
revered classic came in 1828, the two-volume American
Dictionary of the English Language.
169
By examining the Second
Amendment word-by-word, as defined by Webster, we see the
meaning of the Amendment’s words in the nineteenth century.
Regulated” meant[a]djusted by rule, met hod or form s; put
in good order; subjected to rules or restrictions.”
170
As Randy
Barnett has observed in rela tion to the Congressional power to
regulate” interstate commerce, to regulate something means to
make it more regular—not to prohibit it.
171
Militia” was
The body of soldiers in a state en rolled for d iscipline, bu t n ot
engaged in actual service excep t in em er ge ncies; a s
distinguished from regular troops, whose sole occupat ion is
war or milita ry ser vice. Th e m ilitia of a coun try are th e able
bodied men organized into companies, regiments and brigades,
with officers of all grades, and required by law to attend
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1408 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
172. 2 WEBSTER, supra note 169, at 15.
173. 2 id. at 21.
174. 2 id. at 66.
175. 1 id. at 87.
176. 2 id. at 80.
177. 2 id. at 59.
178. 2 id. at 32.
179. 2 id. at 2.
180. 1 id. at 19.
military exer cise s on cer ta in da ys only, but a t oth er tim es left
to pursue their usual occupations.
172
“Necessary” meantindispensibly requisite . . . .”
173
“Security” was “[p]rotection; effectual defense or sa fety from
danger of any kind.”
174
Free” meant “[i]n governm ent, not enslaved; not in a state
of vassalage or dependence; subject only to fixed laws, made by
consent, and to a regular administration of such laws; not
subject to the arbitrary will of a sovereign or lord; as a free
stat e, na tion, or people.”
175
State meant
A polit ical bod y, or bod y politic; th e w hole b ody of people
united under one government, whatever may be the form of
government. . . . More usually the word sign ifies a politica l
body govern ed by r epre senta tives . . . . In th is sen se, state has
sometimes more immediate reference to government,
sometimes t o the people or commun ity.
176
Thus,state is not just thegovernment. The Second
Amendment aims to protect the security of a free Amer ican
people, not just to protect their government.
“Right” was a “[j]ust claim; immunity; privilege. All men
have a right to secure enjoyment of life, liberty, personal safety,
liberty, and property. . . . Rights are natural, civil, political,
religious, personal, and public.”
177
People” meant[t]he body of persons who compose a
community, town, city or nation. We say, the people of a town;
the people of London or Paris; the English people.”
178
Keep” was “[t]o hold; to retain in one’s power or
possession.”
179
Bear meant firstly, “[t]o support; to sustain; as, to bear a
weight or burden”
180
—a meaning that does not fit with the
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1409
181. Id.
182. S ee, e.g., Aym et te v. Sta te , 21 Tenn . (2 H um .) 15 4, 161 (1840 ).
183. The Address and Reasons of Dissent of the Min orit y of th e Con ven tion of
the Stat e of Pennsylvania to their Constituent s (Dec. 18, 1787), reprinted in ORIGIN,
supra note 37, at 154, 160.
184. See discussion infra note 190.
context of the Second Amendment. The second and third
meanings ofbear are much more congruent, however: “To
carry; to convey; to support and remove from place to place” and
“[t]o wear; to bear as a mark of authority or distinction; as, to
bear a sword, a ba dge, a name; t o bear arms in a coat.
181
It is sometimes argued that “bear” has an exclusively
military connotation, so that the right tobear” arms refers
only to bearing them in militia service.
182
But none of Websters
definitions for bear contain such a narrow construction. And
rather significantly, we know t hat “bear” was u sed with a broad
meaning in one of the key documen ts t hat gave birth to the
Second Amendment: the minority report from the Pennsylvania
ra tifying convention. The minority demanded constitutional
protection for the right of the people “to bear arms for the
defense of themselves and their own state, or the United States,
or for the purpose of killing game.”
183
Hunting—“killing
game”—is obviously a personal, non-militia purpose for which
one couldbear arms.”
Further, the state constitutions of Missouri (1820), Indiana
(1816), Ohio (1802), Kentucky (1792), and Pennsylvania (1776)
all recognized a right of citizens to “bear arms” in the “defense
of themselves and the state.”
184
While arms-bea ring for defense
ofthe state” would be in a militia context, citizens bearing
arms merely for “defense of themselves” would merely be
defending themselves against criminal attack. Hence, the
phrasebear arms” did not connote that arms-bearing could
only occur while in active militia service.
In a 1998 ca se, the Supr em e Court wa s ca lled u pon to
construe the meaning of the phrase “carries a firearm in a
mandatory sentencing statute. While the majority opinion did
not refer to the Second Amendment, Justice Ginsburg, writing
for four dissen ters, used t he Second Amendment to help explain
the phrase:
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1410 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
185. Muscarello v. United Sta tes, 118 S. Ct . 1911, 1921 (1998) (Ginsbu rg, J .,
dissen ting) (omiss ions in origin al).
186. 1 WEBSTER, supra note 169, at 13.
187. 1 id. at 110.
Surely a most familiar mea ning is, a s the Constitu tion s
Second Amendment (“keep and bear Arms”) (emphasis added)
and Black’s Law D iction ar y, at 214, in dica te: “wear , bea r, or
carry . . . upon the person or in the clothing or in a pocket, for
the purpose . . . of being armed a nd r ea dy for offen sive or
defen sive act ion in a ca se of conflict wit h an oth er pers on.”
185
Justice Gin sburg’s r eading of the Second Amendment is thus
consistent with the reading suggested by Websters Dictionary.
Arms” meant [w]eapons of offense, or armor for defense
and protection of the body . . . . A stand of arms consists of a
musket, bayonet, cartr idge-box and belt , with a sword. But for
common soldiers a sword is not necessary.”
186
Websters
definition offers two useful insights. First, the distinction
sometimes dr awn between “offensive” and “defensive” weapon s
is of little value. All weapons are made for offense, although
they may be used for defensive pu rposes (i.e., shooting someon e
who is a ttempt ing to perpetrate a murder).
Second, Websters dictionary suggests that the “arms”
protected by the Second Amendment may include more than
just weapons. The Amendm ent may en compa ss “armor for
defense and pr otection of the body.” The defensive a sp ect of
arms would be relevant to legislative pr oposals to pr ohibit non-
government possession of bullet-resistant vests.
Finally,infringed” meant[b]roken, violated,
transgressed.”
187
How would the Second Amendment read if rephrased
according to Webster’s dictiona ry?
The good order of able-bodied men required to attend military
exercises on certa in da ys b ein g in dispensibly requ isite to th e
pr otection of a not-en slaved body politic, the just claim of th e
body of per son s who compose the United States to retain and
wear weapons and armor shall not be violated.
While hardly as elegant as the Second Amendment, Websters
dictionary does point us in the same direction as do the legal
commentators wh o ar gue that the milit ia (an essential
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1411
188. Noah Webst er, An Exam ination into the Leading Principles of the Federal
Constitution , in PAMPHLETS ON THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES 55, 56 (P aul
Leicester Ford ed., Br ooklyn 1888).
Often confused with Noah Webster, but having no relation, was Massach usetts
Senator Daniel Webster, perh aps the greatest orator of the ninet eenth century.
Amon g the most fam ous of all Webster’s public speeches was “The Plymouth
Ora tion,” which he delivered at Plymouth Rock on December 22, 1820—the
bicentennial of the P ilgrim lan ding. Webster, who was an avid hunter all his life,
traced the connection between the social conditions created by the Pilgrims and the
current condition of American freedom; he emphasized that the social condit ions, and
not just the forma l Constitution, wer e es sen tia l ingredients of free dom : “The practical
character of governm ent d epend s often on a variety of considerations, besides the
abstract fram e of its constitutiona l organ ization. Among th ese are the condition and
tenure of proper ty . . . an a rm ed or un ar me d yeoma nr y.” Further,[e]ducation,
wealth, talent s, are all parts and elements of the general aggregate of power; but
numbers, never theless, const itute ordinarily th e most importa nt considera tion , unless,
indeed, there be a m ilitary force in t he h ands of th e few, by which t he y can cont rol
the ma ny.” Dan iel Webster, Th e Plym out h Orat ion, Dec. 22, 1820, available in part
at <http://www.dartmouth.edu/~dwebster/speeches/
plymouth~ora tion.ht ml>.
institution of a free society) will only be effective as long as the
people are gu aranteed t he ownersh ip of arms. In fact, Noah
Webster himself, during the ratification debates, provided a
concise summary of why the entire population should be armed:
Before a standing arm y can rule, the people must be disarmed;
as they ar e in almost every kingdom in Europe. The suprem e
power in Am er ica ca nnot enforce unjust laws by the sword;
because the whole body of the people a re ar med, an d
constitute a force superior to any band of regular troops that
can be, on any pretence, raised in the United States.
188
In sum, all of the pre-1850 sources analyzed
aboveincluding the leading treatises, the lesser treatises,
other books, and the Supreme Court’s Houston casesupport
the St anda rd Model approach to the Secon d Am endment: the
Amendment grants an individual right to bear arms.
III. STATE CONSTITUTIONS AND CASE LAW
The nineteenth century was a fertile period for th e right to
bear arms in state courts and in state constitutions. Many of
these st ate sources pr ovide a good deal of useful information
about how the Second Amendment was understood. This Part
discusses state constitutional texts first and then discusses
state case law. The purpose is not to comprehensively survey
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1412 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
189. Cla yton Cramer s book provides a super b sur vey of state firearms
constitutional case la w in t he n inet eenth cent ury. See CRAMER, supra note 1. The
works of other scholars offer useful stu dies of particular states in the n ineteenth
centur y. See STEPHEN HALBROOK, A RIGHT TO BEAR ARMS: STATE AND FEDERAL BILLS
OF RIGHTS AND CONSTITUTIONAL GUARANTEES (1989); Robert Dowlut, Federal and
State Constitutional Guarantees to Arms, 15 U. DAYTON L. REV. 59 (1989); Robert
Dowlut, The Right to Arms, supra note 1; Robert Dowlut & Janet A. Knoop, State
Constitutions and th e Right to Keep and Bear Arms, 7 OKLA. CITY U. L. REV. 177
(1982); Stephen P. Halbrook, Rationin g Firearm s Pu rch ases an d t he R igh t to Keep
Arms: Reflect ions on th e Bills of R igh ts of Virginia, West V irginia, an d t he U ni ted
States, 96 W. VA. L. REV . 1 (1993); St eph en P. H alb rook , The Right to Bear Arm s in
Texas: The Intent of the Framers of the Bills of Rights, 41 BAYLOR L. REV. 629 (1989);
Glenn Harlan Reynolds, The Right to Keep and B ear Arms under the Tenn essee
Constitution: A Case S tud y in Civ ic Republican Though t, 61 TENN. L. REV. 647 (1994).
190. Many thanks t o Eugene Volokh, who compiled th ese provisions , an d wh o ha s
made them a vailable at
<htt p://www.l aw.ucla.edu/faculty/volokh/beararm s/stat econ.htm >, to which all following
cites are made.
Alabama:That every citizen has a right to bear arms in d efens e of himself and the
sta te.” Art. I, § 26 (enacted 1819, art. I, § 23, with “defence” in place of “defense,”
spelling cha ng ed 190 1).
Arkansas: “The citizens of this State shall have the right to keep and bear arm s for
their common defense.” Art. II, § 5 (1868). This replaced the 1836 p rovision : “That
the free white m en of this Sta te sh all ha ve a right to keep and to bea r arms for th eir
comm on defense.” Art. II, § 21.
California: No provision.
Colorado:The right of no person to keep and bear arms in defense of his home,
per son an d prop er ty, or in aid of the civil power when thereto legally summoned,
sha ll be called in qu estion; bu t n oth ing h er ein conta ined sh all be const ru ed to jus tify
the pr act ice of ca rr yin g con cea led weap ons.” Ar t. II , § 13 (1876).
Connect icu t: Although C onne cticut ha d been one of th e origina l thirteen states, it
added a right to ar ms provision to its constitution in 1818: “Every citizen has a r ight
to bear arms in defense of himself and the state.” Art. I, § 15 (enacted 1818, art. I,
§ 17). The original 1818 text came from the Mississippi Constitu tion of 1817.
Florida: Upon a dmission to the Union in 1838, the Florida const itution provided:
That free white men of this Sta te shall have a right to keep and to bear arms, for
the nineteenth century arms rights cases,
189
but rather to
survey state mater ials solely as t hey m ay shed light on the
federal Second Amendment.
A. State Constitutions
The texts of nineteenth century state constitutions are
worth reviewing for several reasons. First, the large number of
state provisions suggests that the right to arms was considered
an important human right. Of the thirty-six states that were
admitted or readmit ted to the Union in the nineteenth century,
twenty-eight provided a right to arms provision in their state
constitution.
190
Several states adopted right to arms
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1413
their common defence.” Art. I, § 21. The 1865 Constitution, a white supremacist
document, made no mention of a right to arms. The 1868 Constit ution, a
Recons tr uct ion document , provided, “The people shall have the right to bear arms in
defe nce of themselves and of the lawful authority of the State.” Art. I, § 22. This was
modified in 1 885 t o allow rest riction s on th e carr ying of ar ms : “The right of the
people to bear ar ms in defence of themselves, and the lawful authority of the State,
sha ll not be infringed, but the Legislature may prescribe the m anner in which they
may be born e.” Art. I, § 20.
Georgia: The state’s original constitution ha d no right to ar ms, wh ich impelled an
1845 Geor gia Supr eme Cou rt decis ion striking down gun con tr ol to r ely on th e Se cond
Amendment and natural law. The 1865 and 1868 Georgia Constitutions did include
an arms right. 1865: “A well-regulat ed militia, being necessa ry to the secur ity of a
free State, the right of the people to keep and bear ar ms sha ll not be infringed.” Art.
I, § 4. 1868: “A well-regula ted m ilitia bein g necessary to the secur ity of a free people,
the right of the people to keep and bear arms shall not be infringed; but the general
assembly sha ll have power to prescribe by law the man ner in which arms may be
borne.” Art. I, § 14. The provision took its fina l form in t he 1877 Const itu tion : “The
right of the people to keep and bear arms shall not be in fringed, but the General
Assembly shall have power to prescribe the manner in which arms may be born e.”
Art. I, § I, ¶ VIII.
Idaho: The 1889 statehood Const itu tion st at ed: “ The people have the right to bear
arms for th eir security an d defense; but the Legislature sha ll regulate the exercise
of this righ t by la w.” Art. I, § 11.
Illinois: The state had n o right to ar ms u ntil the adopt ion of a new constitution in
1970.
Indiana: The right to arms in th e 18 16 s ta te hood con st itut ion (“That the people have
a right to bear arms for the defense of themselves and the State, and that the
military shall be kept in st rict subordina tion to the civil power.” Art. I, § 20) was
revised in 1 851 t o stat e: “Th e people sh all ha ve a right to bear a rm s, for th e defense
of themselves and t he State.” Art. I, § 32.
Iowa: No provision.
Kansas:The people have the right to bear arm s for their defense and security; but
standing armies, in time of peace, are dangerous to liberty, and shall not be tolerated,
and th e m ilit ar y sh all be in st rict subordination to the civil power.” Bill of Rights,
art. I, § 4 (185 9).
Kentucky: Th e Kent uck y Con stitu tion of 1792 provided: “The right of the citizens to
bear arms in defense of themselves and the Stat e shall not be questioned.” Art. XII,
§ 23. It was changed slightly in 1799 : “That the rights of the citizens to bear arm s
in defense of themselves and the State shall not be questioned.” Art. X, § 23. An 1850
revision addressed a court case from several decades before and specifically authorized
restrictions on con cealed ar ms : “That the rights of the citizens to bear a rm s in
defense of themselves and the State shall not be questioned; but the General
Assembly ma y pa ss laws to p re ven t p er son s fr om car ry ing con cea led ar ms .” Art. XIII,
§ 25. The provision took its modern form in 1891:
All men are, by natur e, free and equal, and have certain inherent and
inalienable rights, among which may be reckoned:
First: The right of enjoying and defending their lives and liberties.
. . . .
Seventh: The right to bear arms in defense of themselves and of the State,
su bject to the power of the General Assembly to enact laws to prevent
persons from carrying concealed weapons. Bill of Rights § 1.
Louisiana: The 1879 Const itution stated: “A well regula ted m ilitia being necessary to
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1414 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
the se cur it y of a free State, the right of th e pe ople to keep an d be ar ar ms sh all not
be abridged. This sh all not pr event th e pa ssa ge of laws t o punis h t hos e who carry
weapons concealed.” Art. 3.
Maine: The 1819 Constitution stated “Every citizen has a right to keep and bear arms
for the common defense; and this right shall never be questioned.” Art. I, § 16. In
1987, aft er a s ta te cour t decision w hich int erpret ed t he Maine provision a s
recognizing no individual right , the Constitution was amended to provide: “Every
citizen has a right to keep and bear arms and this right sha ll never be questioned.”
Art. I, § 16.
Michigan:Every person has a right to bear arm s for the defence of himself and the
sta te.” Art . I, § 6 (18 35).
Minnesota: No provision.
Mississippi: The state’s first Constitution, in 1817, provided: “Ever y citizen has a right
to bear a rms, in defence of himself and the Stat e.” Art. I, § 23. The comma was
removed in 1832. Th e 1868 Reconstruction Constitution changed th e wordin g to: “All
persons shall have a right to keep and bear arms for their defence.” Art. I, § 15. In
1890, the provision was rewritten to copy a formulat ion common in late-19th century
rights to a rm s, m ak in g explicit th e m an y pu rp ose s of t he right to arms, and also the
authority of th e legislat ur e t o cont rol con cealed wea pon s: “The r ight of every citizen
to keep a nd bear arms in defen se of hi s h ome, p er son , or pr opert y, or in aid of t he
civil powe r when t here to legally summoned, shall not be called in question, but the
legislature may r egulate or forbid carrying concealed weapons.” Art. III, § 12.
Missouri: The form used in Mississippi, Colorado, and Mon tana first a ppeared in the
1875 Missou ri Constitu tion : “That the r ight of no citizen to keep and bear arms in
defense of hi s h ome, p er son an d propert y, or in ai d of t he civil power, when thereto
legally summoned, shall not be called into question; but nothing herein cont ained is
intended to justify the practice of wearing concealed weapons.” Art. II, § 17. The
provision re pla ced la ngua ge from 1 820: “That the people have the right peaceably to
assemble for the ir comm on good , an d to apply t o thos e vested with th e power s of
government for redr ess of grievances by petition or remonstr ance; and t hat their right
to bear arms in defen ce of t he ms elv es an d of t he St at e ca nn ot b e qu estioned.” Art .
XIII, § 3. The 1865 Constitut ion had copied the 1820 lan guage, except to subst itute
the lawful authority of the State” for “the State.” Art. I, § 8.
Montana:The right of a ny per son to k eep or bear arms in defense of his own home,
person, and property, or in aid of the civil power when thereto legally summoned,
sha ll not be called in question, bu t nothing her ein contained shall be h eld to per mit
the carrying of concealed weapons.” Art. III, § 13.
Nebraska: No arm s right provision until 1988.
Nevada: No provision until 1982.
North Carolina: The 1868 Con st itu tion substantially followed the arms provision in
the 177 6 Con st itut ion (“That the people have a right t o bea r a rm s, for th e de fen ce
of the State; and, as standing armies, in time of peace, are dangerous to liberty, they
ought not to be kept up; and that the military should be kept under str ict
subordin at ion to, a nd governed by, the civil power.” Bill of Rights, § XVII) and stated:
“A well regulated militia b ein g necessary to t he secu rity of a free St at e, t he right of
the people to keep and bear a rms sh all not be infringed; and, as standing armies in
time of peace are dangerous to liberty, they shall not be maintained, and the milita ry
sha ll be kept under str ict subordination to, an d governed by, th e civil p ower.” Art .
I, § 24. In 1875, concealed we ap ons cont rol w as added : “Noth ing herein contained
sha ll justify the practice of carr ying concealed weapons, or prevent t he General
Assembly from enacting penal statutes against that practice.
North Dakota: No right to ar ms until 1984.
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1415
Ohio: The original 1802 provision stated “That the people have a right to bear arms
for th e defence of themselves and th e state; and as standing armies in time of peace,
are dangerous to liberty, they shall not be kept up, and t hat the m ilitary sh all be
kept under strict subordination to the civil power.” Art. VIII, § 20. The language was
modernized in 1 851: “The people have the right to bear arms for their defense and
security; but sta ndin g ar mies, in time of pea ce, ar e dangerous to libert y, and shall
not be kept u p; an d th e milit ar y sha ll be in s trict su bordin ation to the civil power.”
Art. I, § 4.
Oregon :The people shall have the r ight to bear arms for the defence of themselves,
and the State, but the Military shall be kept in strict subordination to the civil
power.” Art . I, § 27 (e na cte d 1857, as a rt . I, § 28).
Rhode Island: The state had no constitution until 1842. The 1842 constitution stated:
The right of the people to keep and bear arms shall not be infringed.” Art. I, § 22.
South Carolina: The origina l cons tit ut ion h ad no r ight t o ar ms . Th e 1868 Con st itu tion
added one : “The people ha ve a rig ht to k eep an d bear ar ms for t he common defence.
As, in times of peace . . . .” Art. I, § 28. This was revised in 1895 to more closely
parallel the Second Amendment:A well regulated militia being necessary to the
security of a free S ta te, th e r ight of t he peop le to keep and bear a rms shall not be
infringed. As, in times of peace, armies are dangerous to liberty, they shall not be
maintained without t he consent of the Gen era l Ass em bly. Th e m ilit ar y pow er of th e
State sha ll always be held in subordina tion to the civil aut hority and be governed by
it.” Art. 1, § 20.
South Dakota: “The right of the citizens to bear arms in defense of themselves and
the st at e sha ll n ot b e den ied .” Art . VI, § 24 (1 889).
Tennessee: The 1834 sta te constitution’s right to arm s exactly matched the lan guage
of the origina l 1796 const itu tion : “That the freemen of this State have a right to keep
and to bear a rm s for th eir comm on d efen ce.” Art . XI, § 26. Th e Reconstr uct ion
Constitu tion added legislative power to control the carrying of ar ms : “That the
citizens of th is State have a rig ht to k eep an d to bea r a rm s for th eir comm on
defense; but the Legislature shall have power, by law, to regulate the wearing of
arms wit h a view t o pr eve nt cri me .” Art . I, § 26 (1 870).
Texas: When the Texan nation gained independence in 1836, the Declaration of Rights
provided:Every citizen shall have the right to bear arms in defence of hi ms elf a nd
the repu blic. The militar y sha ll at a ll times an d in all cases be subordinate to the
civil power.” Declaration of Right s, cl. 14. When Texas joined th e Union in 1845, the
new Constitution stated:Every citizen shall have the right to keep and bear arms
in law ful d efen ce of hims elf or th e St at e.” Art . I, § 13. Th e Reconstr uction
Constitu tion of 1868 decla re d: “Every person shall have the right to keep and bear
arms in the lawful defence of h imself or the State, under such regulations as the
legislature ma y pres cribe.” Art. I, § 13. The final version appeared in 1876:Every
citizen shall have the right to keep and bear arms in the lawful defense of him self
or th e St at e; bu t t he Legisla tu re sh all ha ve power, by law, to regulate the wearing
of arms, with a view to prevent crime. Art. I, § 23.
Utah:The people h ave t he r ight to bea r a rm s for their secur ity a nd defense, but the
legislature ma y regu late th e exer cise of th is r igh t b y la w.” Art. I, § 6 (189 6).
Washington : The state’s 1889 provision was typical of its tim e, except for it s explicit
statement about armed groups, including company goon squa ds: “ The right of the
individual citizen t o bear ar ms in defen se of hims elf, or th e state, shall not be
impaired, but noth ing in t his section sh all be const rued as authorizing individua ls or
corpora tion s to organize, maintain or employ an arm ed body of men.” Art. I, § 24.
West Virginia: No provision un til 1986.
Wisconsin: No provision until 1998.
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1416 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
Wyoming:The right of citizens to bear ar ms in defen se of th em selves a nd of th e
state sh all not b e den ied .” Art . I, § 24 (1 889 ).
191. See CONSTITUTION FOR THE PROVISIONAL GOVERNMENT OF THE CONFED ERAT E
STATES OF AMERICA, ar t. I , § 7, cl. 10; CONSTITUTION OF THE CONFEDERATE STATES OF
AMERICA, art. I, § 9, cl. 13, reprinted in CHARLES ROBERT LEE, JR., THE CONFE DERATE
CONSTITUTIONS apps. B & C (1963). The Confederate Constitution adopted t he United
States Const itu tions Bill of Right s word for word. See id.
192. LA. CONST. art. 3.
193. GA. CONST. art. I, § 1 4 (1868).
provisions repeatedlyfirst upon admission to the Union, then
upon readmission shortly after the Civil War, and a gain upon
creation of a new Constitution under Reconstruction. The
Confederate States of America also put a right to arms in their
national Constitution.
191
Second, states often thought it necessary to specifically
enumerate the exceptions to the right to arms. Many
constitutions contain a specific except ion allowing restrictions
on concealed carry. Open carry was considered honorable, but
concealed carry was seen useful only to people who wanted to
surprise a victim. Louisiana’s constitution, for example, closely
tracked the Second Amendment, but added an except ion
against concea led ca rry: “A well regulated militia being
necessary to the security of a free State, the right of the people
to keep and bear arms shall not be abridged. This shall not
prevent the passa ge of laws to pu nish those who carry weapon s
concealed.”
192
This concealed carry exception, which was aimed
at individuals, shows that the Louisiana right was an
individual one. The close r eliance on the language of the Second
Amendment further suggests that, at least to those who drafted
and ratified the Louisiana Constitution, the Second
Amendment was seen as protecting an individual right.
Similar ly, Georgia during Reconstruction adopted a Bill of
Rights copied nearly verbatim from the federal Bill of Rights.
The arms provision stated: “A well-regulated militia being
necessary to the security of a free people, the right of the people
to keep and bear arms shall not be infringed; but the general
assembly shall have power to prescribe by law the manner in
which arms may be born e.”
193
The Georgia Su pr em e Court has
had no difficulty in upholding this provision as pr otecting the
right of individual Geor gia ns t o own and ca rry gu ns. At the
same time, the court relied on th e Const itutions express grant
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1417
194. See Hill v. St at e, 53 Ga . 472, 473-8 3 (1874).
195. S ee, e.g., Eh rman & Hen igan , supra note 2, at 14-32.
196. OHIO CONST. ar t. I , § 4. Th is la ngua ge r evis ed t he 1802 lan guage : “That the
people have a r ight to bear arm s for the defence of th emselves and the state; and as
standing ar mies in t ime of peace, ar e da ngerous to liber ty, th ey sha ll n ot be kept up;
and that the military shall be kept under s trict subordinat ion t o the civil power.”
OHIO CONST. art. VIII, § 2 0 (1802).
197. S ee, e.g., Arnold v. City of Clevela nd, 616 N.E .2d 163, 169-71 (O hio 199 3);
In re Rei lly, 31 O hio Dec. 36 4 (C.P. 191 9).
of authority to regulate the conditions of ca rryin g as r ea son for
upholding a state law prohibiting dea dly weapon s a t election
grounds, courts, churches, and other public gatherings.
194
Third, state constitutional arms provisions that address the
issue of the military and standing armies were not seen as
inconsistent with individual rights. Opponents of the individual
rights view of the Second Amendment normally point out that
the Founders were gra vely concerned about standing armies
(true), that they saw state militias a s a counterpoise to a
federal standing army (also true), and that during the
ratifica tion deba tes over the proposed federal Con st itution,
many anti-federalists worried that the new federal government
would destroy the state militias (also true). The anti-individual
theorists then claim that because the Founders saw militias as
a pr otection against st anding armies , the Second Amendment,
therefore, guaranteed only the right of state governments to
have militias.
195
But st ate const itutions show us t hat an anti-standing army
arms right provision can also be an individual right provision.
For example, the Ohio Constitution of 1851 st at ed, “The people
have the right to bear arms for their defense and security; but
st anding armies , in time of peace, a re danger ous to liberty, and
shall not be kept up; and the military shall be in strict
subordination to the civil power.”
196
Ohio courts have always
treated this provision as guaranteeing an individual right.
197
Likewise, t he 1868 Nor th Carolina Const itution pr ovided:
A well regulated militia being necessa ry to the secu rity of a
free Stat e, th e right of th e pe ople t o keep and bea r a rm s sh all
not be infringed; and, as standing arm ies in time of peace are
dangerous to liberty, they ought not to be kept up, and the
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1418 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
198. N.C. CONST. ar t. I, § 2 4 (1868).
199. Id. § 30 (1 875 ).
200. S ee, e.g., Stat e v. Kerner, 107 S.E. 222 (N.C. 1921); State v. Speller, 86 N.C.
697, 699-701 (1882); Stat e v. Newsom, 27 N.C. (5 Ired.) 250, 253-54 (1844); State v.
Huntly, 25 N .C. (3 Ir ed.) 418, 422-2 3 (1843).
201. For an excellent survey of the r acial implications of nineteenth century arms
control in the Sout h, see Robert J. Cottrol & Raymond T. Diam ond, Never In ten ded
to be Applied to the White Population”: Firearm s R egulation and Racial
Disparity—The Redeem ed S out h’s L egacy to a Nation al J ur ispru den ce?, 70 CHI.-KENT
L. REV . 1307 (1995), Cla yton E. Cram er, The Racist Roots of Gun Control, 4 KAN. J.L.
& PUB. POLY 17 (1995), and Stefan B. Tah massebi, Gun Control and Racism, 2 GEO.
MASON U. CIV. RTS. L.J . 67 (1991 ).
military should be kept under strict su bordin at ion to, a nd
governed by, the civil power.
198
This language quoted the Second Amendment but added
additional language denouncing st anding armies. Su rely if the
anti-individual view of t he Secon d Am endment were correct,
then the North Carolina language (even more heavily weighted
with anti-army language) could not be construed as an
individual right.
But the North Car olina language was indeed so construed.
In 1875, the North Carolina legislature added concealed
weapons control to the state constitution:Nothing herein shall
justify the practice of carrying concealed weapons, or prevent
the General Assembly from enacting penal statutes against
that pract ice.”
199
The anti-concealed weapons language was
obviously aimed at individual arms carriers, not at the state
militia. And North Carolina courts consistently interpreted the
provision as guaranteeing an individual right.
200
B. State Case Law
Except for some statutes late in the century banning arms
from public parades, gun control in the nineteenth century was
almost exclusively a Sou ther n ph enomenon. In the post-Civil
War period, the Southern gun laws were clearly aimed at
controlling the Freedmen; although written in racially neutral
terms, the laws were meant for, and applied almost exclusively
to, blacks.
201
As for the antebellum period, scholars have speculated that
the Southern controls were aimed at free bla cks. But Cla yton
Cramer has shown that the antebellum laws, wh ich were
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1419
202. See generally Clayton Cramer, Concealed Weapons Laws in the Early
Republic (1998) (unpublished Master’s thesis in History, Sonoma State Un iver sit y) (on
file wit h a ut hor).
203. See Aymette v. Sta te, 21 Ten n. (2 H um .) 154 (18 40). For t he hi st ory of the
right to ar ms in Tenn essee, see Glenn Harlan Reynolds, The Right to Keep and Bear
Arms Under the Tennessee Constitution: A Case Study in Civic Republican Th ought,
61 TENN. L. REV. 647 (199 4).
204. Aymette, 21 Tenn. at 157.
205. Id.
written in facially neutral terms in a period when there was no
Fourteenth Amendment to require racial neutrality, had a
different purpose. Dueling had been widely practiced in the
Southeast; legislative efforts t o outlaw dueling had been
undermined by the courts and by juries. In the absence of
regulated dueling, Southerners whose honor had been offended
sim ply killed the offender. The concealed weapons laws were an
ext en sion of the antidueling laws and were intended to prevent
the victims of insults from killing the insulter. Legislatures
accurately expected massive resistance to the laws, and
therefore included many special enforcement mechanisms, such
as allowing private citizens to bring criminal prosecutions and
forbidding juries to consider the defendant’s motives.
202
The solid majority of courts that reviewed the gun control
laws, which were often challenged under the Second
Amendment and its state analogues, would uphold the
particular control, while affirming an individual righ t to own
and carry guns.
1. T ennessee
One of the most important state gun cases in the nineteenth
century was Aymette v. State, an 1840 decision upholding
restrictions on carrying concealed weapons.
203
The decision was
based on the Tennessee Constitution’s right to arms, but the
court stated that the Tennessee provision was intended “[i]n
the same view” as the Second Amendment.
204
The Aymette
court read the Tennessee provision (and, by analogy, the Second
Amendment) narrowly, finding that the right to arms was only
so that the people as a whole could rise up against tyranny; the
right was not for “private” defense.
205
Further, the right tobear
arms” meant only the right to carry weapons in a public
military context , not to carry concealed weapons for personal
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1420 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
206. See id. at 161.
207. Id. at 158.
208. Id. at 160. A good argume nt could be ma de t ha t t he re is n ot a s m uch
difference between militia weapons and crime weapons as Aymette and the nineteenth
century majority line of cases would su gges t. Conceala ble k nives m ay b e usefu l for
hand-to-hand combat and for guerilla war fare, and small handguns even more so.
Conversely, rifles can be used to murder innocent people.
209. Aymette may ha ve been too facile in equ ating the ar ms r ight provision in
the Tennessee Constitution with th e Se cond Amendme nt . Th e Te nn ess ee Cons tit ut ion
protectedthe right of the people to keep and bear ar ms for their common defence”
and thus contained restr ictive language which t he U.S. Sena te ha d vot ed n ot t o
include in t he Secon d Amen dm en t. While com mon defense may have been the only
purpose of th e Tenn ess ee r igh t, t he Secon d Am endm ent language was broad enough
to in clude oth er pu rp ose s, s uch as self-de fense. See 1 BLACKSTONE, supra note 14,
app. at 300. The Aymette cour t’s th eor y th at conceale d carr y was n ot within the scope
of the arms right was predicated on reasoning that a militia-man would never carry
concealed. But while concealed carry might be of no use to someone engaged in the
“common defence,” concealed car ry could be quite use ful for per sonal defense. Thus
Aymette, an d the cases fr om ot her s ta te s wh ich cite to Aymette, may be on shaky
ground to th e extent that the other state cases involve const itutiona l pr ovision s
worded more broadly than Tennessee’s.
protection.
206
Given the anti-tyranny purpose of the right, the
only arms protected were weapons useful for resistin g tyranny,
but not those useful mainly for crime:
[T]h e use of those weapons wh ich a re usua lly em ployed in
private broils, and which are efficient only in the hands of the
robber and th e assassin . . . . The right to keep and bear th em,
is n ot, t herefore, se cur ed by t he con st itu tion .
207
As to the weapons which were protected:
The citizen s h ave the u nqu alified right to keep the
weapon . . . . But the right to bear arms is not of that
unqualified character. . . . [B]ut it does not follow, that they
may be borne by an individu al, mer ely t o terr ify the people, or
for pu rp oses of priv at e a ssas sin at ion. . . . [T]he legislature may
prohibit such manner of wearing as would never be resorted to
by persons engaged in the common defence.
208
Aymette laid down the line followed by the majority of state
courts considering right to arms cases: the right was for
protection from tyranny; the right encompassed the ownership
of weapons useful for resisting tyranny; bu t the right did n ot
encompass the carrying of concealed weapons not suitable for
resisting tyranny.
209
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1421
210. See And re ws v. Sta te , 50 Tenn . (3 H eis k.) 165 (187 1).
211. See id. at 168.
212. Id. at 170.
213. Barron v. Balti more , 32 U.S. (7 Pe t. ) 243 (183 3).
214. See Andrews, 50 Tenn. at 173-75.
215. Id. at 177.
After the Civil War, the Tennessee Supreme Court decided
another case, Andrews v. State, wh ich ela borated on the
principles of Aymette, and which, like Aymette, was widely cited
in other states.
210
The Tennessee legislature had banned the
carrying of certain weapon s—con cealed or openly—a nd several
defendants charged with violation of the law argued that the
law violated the Second Amendment and the Tennessee
Const itution. The summary of the briefs at the begin ning of the
case shows that, regarding the Second Amendment, the
Attorney General simply replied that the Second Amendment
was not enforceable against the states.
211
In oral argument,
apparently, the Attorney General went furt her, arguing that
the Second Am en dm ent and t he Ten nessee state const itutional
right to arms were meant to protect a “political right.”
212
Citin g Barron v. Baltimore,
213
the Andrews court held that
the Second Am en dm ent wa s inapplica ble to the states.
214
But
the Court const rued the Tennessee provision and t he Second
Amendment together, finding that, necessarily, the same
rights, and for simila r rea son s, were bein g provided for and
protected in both the Federal and State Constit ut ions . . . .”
215
The court’s construction of th e state and federal right to arms is
worth quoting at length, because it is a perfect example of the
dominant line of nineteenth -centur y case law on the right to
arms, expressing several principles:
1. Th e pu rpose of th e right is to secure a militia, which is a
foundation of a free society.
2. To m ak e possible a m ilitia, all persons have the right to
purchase, use, pr act ice with , an d ca rr y weapon s for all non-
nefarious purposes.
3. The right only inclu des th e type of arms u sed by a militia
(e.g., rifles and swords) and does not include non-militia type
weapons allegedly favored by crim inals (e.g., concealable
knives).
As the court wrote:
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1422 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
216. Id. at 178-79. A “r epeat er ” is “any firearm capable of fir ing mor e tha n on e
shot without ha vin g to be re loa ded m an ua lly.” R.A. STEINDLER, STEINDLERS NEW
FIREARMS DICTIONARY 213 (1985); see also 2 THE NEW SHORTER OXFORD ENGLISH
DICTIONARY 2548 (3d ed. 1993) (defining “repeat er” as “[a] firearm which fires several
shots without reloading,” and explaining that this usage first appeared in the middle
It was th e efficiency of the pe ople a s soldiers, wh en called int o
actual service for the security of the State, as one end; and in
order to this [sic], th ey w ere to be a llowed t o keep arms. What,
then, is in volved in th is r igh t of keeping ar ms? It necessa rily
involves the right to purchase and use them in such a way as
is usual, or to keep them for t he or din ary pu rp oses t o wh ich
they are adapted; an d a s they are to be kept, evidently w ith a
view that the citizens making up the yeomanry of the land, the
body of th e m ilitia, shall becom e fam iliar with t heir u se in
times of peace , th at th ey m ay th e m ore efficiently use them in
times of war; then the right to keep arms for this purpose
involves the right to practice their use, in order to attain to
this efficiency. The right and use are guaranteed to the citizen,
to be exer cised a nd enjoyed in tim e of peace, in su bor din at ion
to the general ends of civil society; but, as a right, to be
maintained in all its fullness.
The right to keep arms, necessarily involves the right to
purchase them, to keep them in a state of efficiency for use,
and to purchase and provide ammunition suitable for such
arm s, and to keep them in repair. And clearly for this purpase
[sic], a man would have the right to carry them to and from his
home, and no one could claim that the Legislature had the
right to punish h im for it, without violating th is clause of the
Constitution.
But farther than this, it must be held, that the right to
keep arms, involves, necessarily, the right to use such arm s for
all th e ordin ar y pu rposes, an d in all the ordina ry m odes usual
in th e coun try, an d to which a rm s are adapted, limited by the
du ties of a good citizen in tim es of pea ce . . . .
. . . .
What, then, is he protected in the right to keep and thus
use? Not ever y thin g that m ay be u seful for offen se or defen se;
but what may properly be included or understood under the
title of arms, taken in connection with the fact that the citizen
is to keep them, as a citizen. . . . [W]e would hold, that the rifle
of all descriptions, the shot gun, the musket, and repeater, are
such arms . . . .
216
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1423
nineteenth century).
217. Andrews, 50 Tenn. at 182.
218. State v. Staten, 46 Tenn. (6 Cold.) 233, 277, 279 (1869) (Shackleford, J .,
concur ri ng). The state court explained:
The right of suffrage being a political, and not a natural or inherent
right, the sovereign power has the righ t to restrict or enlarge t he pr ivilege.
. . .
. . . The one [the right to follow a profession] is an inherent and na tural
right, an d [the rig ht to vot e], a polit ical right or privilege, a trust delegated.
The first falls directly wit hin t he pr ohibitions of t he Con st it ut ion of th e
United States; the other is a trust, subject to be r evoked by t he sover eign
will.
Id. at 277-79. Ridley v. Sherbrook , 43 Tenn. (3 Cold.) 569, 576-77 (1866), is also
instru ctive of th is dist inct ion:
The elective franchise is not an inalienable right or privilege, but a political
right, conferred, limited, or withheld, at the pleasur e of the people, actin g
in their sover eign capacity.
. . . .
These [rights to follow a pr ofession or calling] are civil rights, and
inalienable, an d of which h e ca nn ot b e depri ved by t he people of the State.
But a political right st an ds u pon a very differen t p rinciple; it is a political
privilege or gra nt, that may be extended or recalled, at the will of the
sovereign power.
Id.
219. Andrews, 50 Tenn. at 182.
220. See id. at 183; see also supra notes 112, 114 and a ccompanying text.
The Attorney General, however, had arguedthat the right
to keep a nd bear arms is a political, n ot a civil right .”
217
Under
existing Tennessee doctrine, r igh ts classified a s “political” (su ch
as voting) were subject to limitless legislative restriction, while
rights classified ascivil” were not.
218
The Ten nessee court
responded that the Attorney General
fails to distinguish between the nature of the right to keep,
and its necessary incidents, and the right to bear arms for the
com mon defense. Bearing arm s for the common defense may
well be held to be a politica l right, or for pr otection an d
maintenance of such rights, intended to be guaranteed; but the
right to keep them, with all that is implied fairly as an incident
to this right, is a pr ivate individu al right, guar an teed to t he
citizen, not the soldier.
219
The court then quoted at length from Justice Story’s treatise on
constitutional law:
220
We cite this passage as throwing light upon wha t was intended
to be gu ar an teed to t he people of the States, against the power
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1424 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
221. Id. at 183-84.
222. 21 Tenn . (2 H um .) 154 (1840).
223. See Andrews, 50 Tenn. at 184-85 (quoting Amyette v. State, 21 Tenn. (2
Hum.) 154 (184 0)).
224. Id. at 186.
225. Id. at 187. This formulation closely prefigured the U .S. Supreme Court’s
handling of a challenge to a federal law prohibiting unregister ed possession of short
shotguns; the Court sent the case back to trial court to determine if short shotguns
were milit ia-type wea pons. S ee United States v. Miller, 307 U.S. 1 74, 178-83 (1 939 ).
226. See Andrews, 50 Tenn. at 187-88.
227. See id. at 193-95.
of the Federal Legislature, and at the sam e time, as showing
clearly what is the m ea ning of our ow n Con stitu tion . . . . So
that, the m eaning of the one, will give us an understanding of
the purpose of the other.
The passa ge from Story, show s clearly that this right was
intended , as we have maintained in this opinion, and was
guaranteed to, and to be exercised and enjoyed by the citizen
as su ch, a nd not by him as a soldier, or in defense solely of his
political rights.
221
The court quoted additional material from Justice Story and
shared his worries about the neglect of the militia. The court
also quoted the earlier Tennessee case, Aymette v. State,
222
and
its invention of the “civilized warfare” test for determining the
types of arms constitutionally protected.
223
The Tennessee statute had forbidden the concealed carrying
of, among other small weapons, any “pocket pistol.”
224
The
Tennessee Supreme Court ruled that whether the defendants
revolver was a weapon—the “skill in the use of which will add
to the efficien cy of the soldier ”—was a matter for decision at
trial, based on the evidence.
225
The instant statute was clearly
unconstitutional, however, because it forbade all carrying,
rath er than just concealed carr y.
226
A concurring and dissenting opinion argued for a broader
rule than the majority, not limiting the type of arms t o
civilized warfare weapons and allowing only the “regulation”
of concealed carry, but not its prohibition.
227
2. Arkansas
The anti-individual interpretation of the Secon d
Amendment made its first appearance in a concurring opinion
in an 1842 Arkansas decision upholding a law against carrying
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1425
228. See St at e v. Bu zza rd , 4 Ar k. 18 (1842 ).
229. See ARK. CONST. of 1836, ar t. II , § 21 (“That the free whit e men of this
State sh all ha ve a rig ht to k eep an d to bear arm s for their common defence.”). The
Arkansas Constitution was one of a few of the nineteenth century st at e const itu tion s
to include a “common defence” purpose and no oth er. During Senate debate over the
Secon d Amendme nt , th e Unit ed S ta te s Se na te re jected a mot ion t o add “for t he
comm on defense” to the end of the Second Amendment. See SENATE JOUR NAL , Sept.
9, 1789, attested by Sam A. Otis, Secretary of the Senate, Executive Communications,
box 13, p.1, Virginia Sta te Libra ry a nd Archives, cited in Dennis, supra note 1, at 70
n.54; SENATE SUBCOMM. ON THE CONST., supra note 1, at 6.
230. See Buzzard, 4 Ark. at 19-23.
231. Id. at 24.
concealed weapons against a challenge under the Arkansas
Const itution and the Second Amendment.
228
Existing Arkansas
case law provided sufficient authority to uphold the law, but
the court majority went further, offering a narrow construction
of the Second Amendment and its corresponding provision in
the 1836 Ar kansa s con st itution.
229
The majority argued that:
1. All natural rights are surrendered to full government
control upon the creation of a government;
2. An “absolu te” right to ar ms would mean t ha t disarm ing
violent criminals upon their apprehension was
unconstitutional;
3. Th er efor e, since t he p olicy im plications of t he str aw-m an
absolute” right to arms are unacceptable, there must be no
right to arms at all.
230
Accordin g to this Arkansas court, the sole purpose of the
Second Amendment was to secure a well-regulated milit ia: “the
language used appears to indicate, distinctly, that this, and this
alone, was the object for which the article under consideration
was adopted.”
231
The Am en dm ent wa s based on the t heor y
that the militia, without arms, however well disposed, might
be unable to resist, successfully, the efforts of those who
should consp ire to overthrow the esta blished institutions of the
country, or s ubju ga te th eir common libert ies . . . . [F ]or this
purpose only, it is conceived that the right to keep and bear
arms wa s retained, and the p owe r w hich, wit hout s uch
reservation , would have been vested in the government, to
prohibit, by law, their keeping and bearing arms for any
purpose wh at ever, w as so far limited or withdrawn . . . that
the people designed and expected to accomplish this object, by
the ad option of th e article under consid eration, which wou ld
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1426 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
232. Id. at 24-25.
233. See id. at 27.
234. Id. at 28.
235. Id. at 32 (D ickinson , J ., con cur ring ).
236. See id. at 33 (Dick inson , J ., con cur ring).
forever invest them with a legal right to keep and bear arms
for that purpose; but it surely was not designed to operate as
an immunity t o th ose, who shou ld so k eep or bear th eir ar ms
as to in jure or enda nger th e privat e righ ts of oth er s, or in any
ma nn er prejudice the common interests of society.
232
Thus, since the restriction on carrying concea led arms did not
impair the ability of the people to rise against tyranny, the law
did not violate the state constitution’s right to arms.
233
As for
the Second Amendmen t, it wasan open qu estion” since no
court had yet construed it.
234
Justice Dickinson’s concurring opinion went much further.
The provision of the Federal Constitution . . . is but an
assertion of that gen eral right of sovereignty belonging to
independent nations, to regulate their military force.”
235
Since
the law against carrying concealed weapons did not interfere
with the performance of federal militia duty, it did not violate
the Second Amendment.
236
This represents the birth of the anti-
individual version of the Second Amendment.
The dissent bitterly contested the majority’s arguments one-
by-one, pointing out that the same rationale could be used to
obliterate any natural law right guaranteed under the
Arkansas or federal constitutions. Regarding the Second
Amendment, the dissent lamented that under the concurring
opinion’s interpretation,
it is th e m ilitia alon e wh o possess th is right, in
contradistinction from th e m ass of th e people; and even they
cannot use th em for p rivat e defen ce or personal aggression ,
but mu st use them for public liberty, according to th e
discre tion of the Legislature. According t o the rule laid down
in their interpretation of this clause, I deem the right to be
valueless, and not worth preserving; for the State
un qu est iona bly possesses the power, without the grant, to arm
the militia, and dire ct h ow t hey s hall be em ployed in cas es of
invasion or dom estic in su rr ection. If this be the meaning of the
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1427
237. Id. at 35 (Lacy , J ., d iss en ting ).
238. Carroll v. Sta te , 28 Ark . 99, 101 (18 72).
239. Id.
240. See Fi fe v. St at e, 31 Ar k. 455 , 456 (1876).
241. See id. at 458.
242. See id. at 458-59. Regarding the Second Amendment, the court cited 3
STORY, supra note 106, at 750-51, §§ 1896-97, and THOMAS COOLEY, infra note 395,
at 498, to support the statement that
the arm s which it [the Second Amendment] guarantees American citizens
the right to keep and to bear, are such as are needful to, and ordinarily
used by a well r egulated m ilitia, and such as are necessary and suitable to
a fre e people, to en able t hem to resist oppression, prevent usu rpa tion, repel
invasion, et c., et c.
Fife, 31 Ark. at 458.
Constitu tion , why give that which is no right in itself, an d
guaranties a privilege that is useless?
237
Wheth er rightly or wrongly reasoned, the concurrence in
State v. Buzzard mark s the birth of the states’ rights, anti-
individual view of the Second Amendment. It is notable that the
birt h occurs half a century after the ratification of the
Amendment, and the concurrence was not able to cite a single
authority of any type in su pport of its position. Anti-
individualists appear unaware of the Buzzard concurrence,
although it should have pride of place as the creat or of their
theory.
After the Civil Wa r, the Arkansa s cou rt moved away from
Buzzard’s more extreme la nguage, and bega n to restore some
force to the right to arms. An 1872 decision cited Buzzard
merely for the proposition that the legislature could prohibit
injurious uses of firearms, “so long as their discretion is kept
within reasonable bounds.”
238
Under this standard, a law
against concealed carry was “not unreasonable.”
239
In 1876, the court heard a Second Amendment and state
constitutional challenge to a new law prohibiting the
wearing—openly or concealed—of various edged weapon s,
pistols, and brass knuckles.
240
The court ruled that the Second
Amendment was not a limit on the states.
241
Following the 1871
Tennessee decision Andrews v. State, the Arkansas court held
that the state Constitution and the Second Amendment
protected citizen ownership of arms, but lim ited that pr otection
to weapon s t hat were useful for purposes of war.
242
Thus, the
ban on these particular concealable weapons was
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1428 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
243. See Fife, 31 Ark. at 461-62.
244. See id. at 461.
245. Wilson v. State, 33 Ark. 557, 560 (1878) (striking a ban on unconcealed
carry).
246. See Nu nn v. S ta te , 1 Ga. 243 (184 6).
247. Id. at 246.
248. Id. at 247.
constitutional.
243
While large military-size repeating pistols
were within the scope of the right to arms, small pistols were
not.
244
In 1878, the court struck down a ban on carrying weapons,
as applied t o the defendants carrying of a concealed army-sized
pistol:If cowardly and dishonorable men som et imes sh oot
unarmed men with army pistols or guns, the evil must be
prevented by the penitentiary and gallows, and not by a general
depr ivat ion of a constitutional privilege.”
245
Although the
Arkansas Supreme Court never formally overruled Buzzard,
the courts postwar decisions returned Arkansas law to the
mainstream. The Buzzard concurrence’s assertion that the
right to arms was n ot individual vanished from Amer ican case
law for the rest of the nineteenth century.
3. Georgia
The 1846 case Nunn v. State was the first case in which a
court used the Second Am endm ent to invalidate a gun control
law.
246
The Georgia legislature had banned the sale and
possession of knives intended for offensive or defensive
purposes and pistols, except “such pistols as are known and
used as horsemans pistols.”
247
The law made an except ion
which allowed possession (but not sale) of the banned weapons
if the weapon were wornexposed plainly to view.”
248
The Georgia Const itution at the time had no right to arms
provision, but the stat e Supreme Court combined nat ural rights
analysis with the Second Amendment to declare the law
unconstitutional:
[When] did any legislative body in the Un ion ha ve the right to
deny to its citizens the privilege of keeping and bearing arms
in defence of themselves an d their country?
. . . [T]h is is on e of t he fundamental principles, upon
which re st s t he gr ea t fa br ic of civil liberty, reared by the
fathers of the Revolution and of the country. And the
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1429
249. Id. at 249.
250. Id. at 250.
251. Id.
252. Id. at 251.
Con stitu tion of the United Stat es, in declar ing that th e right of
the people to keep and bear arms, should not be infringed, on ly
reiterated a t ru th an nounced a centu ry befor e, in th e act of
1689,to extend and secure the rights and liberties of English
subjects”—Whether living 3,000 or 300 miles from th e royal
palace.
249
And thus, “[t]he la nguage of the second amendment is broad
enough to embrace both Federal and State governmen ts—nor is
there anything in its terms which restricts its meaning.”
250
The Georgia court kept the introductory clause to the
Amendment firmly in view: “our Constitution assigns as a
reason why this right shall not be interfered with, or in any
manner abr idged , that the free enjoyment of it will prepare and
qu alify a well-regulated militia, wh ich are n ecess ary to the
security of a free State.”
251
Thus:
If a well-regulated militia is necessary to the security of th e
State of Georgia and of the U nited Sta tes, is it com petent for
the General Assembly to ta ke aw ay th is secu rit y, by disarm ing
the people? What advantage would it be to tie up the han ds of
the national legislature, if it were in the power of the S tates to
destroy this bulwa rk of defence? In solemnly affirming that a
well-regulated militia is necessary to the security of a free
State, and that, in order to train properly that militia, the
unlimited right of the people to k eep and bear arms shall not be
impaired, are not the sovereign people of the State committed
by this pledge to preserve this right inviolate?
252
And what is the scope of this “unlimited right”?
The right of the whole people, old and young, men, women and
boys, and not militia only, to keep and bear arms of every
description, and not su ch merely as are used by the m ilitia,
shall not be in fringed , curtailed, or broken in u pon, in the
smallest degree; and all this for the important end to be
attained: th e rearin g up and qualifying a well-regulated
militia, so vitally neces sa ry to t he se cur ity of a fr ee St at e. Our
opin ion is, that any law, State or Federal, is repugnant to the
Constitution, and void, which contravenes th is right, originally
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1430 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
253. Id. For th e im pact of t he right to a rm s on th e Texas wa r for independence
against Mexico—which was precipitated by the Mexican government’s attempt to
confiscate a cannon, and the Texans’ reply of “Come and take it,” see Stephen P.
Halbrook, The Right to Bear Arms in Texas: The Intent of the Framers of the Bills
of Rights, 41 BAYLOR L. REV. 629 (1989).
254. Nunn, 1 Ga. at 251. The Nunn Court’s approach to natural rights was not
unusual for its time. In an 1857 Massa chusetts case, Chief Justice Lemuel
Shaw—perhaps the most influential state court judge of the period—used principles
ofnatural justice to find that the state constitut ion required th e use of grand juries
for infamous crimes, desp ite the absence of any gra nd jury language in the
Massachusetts Bill of Rights. S ee Jones v. Robbi ns , 72 Ma ss. (8 Gra y) 329 (18 57).
255. See Hill v. State, 53 Ga. 472, 473-74 (1874). Justice McCay opined that if
the qu est ion w ere on e of first impress ion, he would h old tha t both th e Se cond
Amendment and the Georgia provision only protected “the arms of a militiaman, the
weapons ordin arily used in battle, t o-wit: gun s of every k ind, swords, bayonets,
horseman’s pistols, etc.” Id. at 474. But, he admit ted, Nunn v. State requ ired a mu ch
broader definit ion. See id. at 475.
belon ging to our forefathers, trampled under foot by Charles I.
and his two wicked son s and su ccessor s, re-est ablished by the
revolut ion of 1688, conveyed to this land of liberty by the
colonists, an d fin ally in corp ora ted con spicuously in our own
Magna Charta! And Lexin gton, Concord, Camden, River
Raisin, Sandusky, and the laurel-crowned field of New Orleans
plead eloquen tly for this in terp re ta tion ! And t he a cqu isit ion of
Texas may be considered th e full fruits of this great
constitutional right.
253
The opinion concluded by holding that the ban on concealed
carrying was valid because it did not interfere with a citizen’s
Second Amendment right; but insofar as the lawcontains a
prohibition against bearing arms openly, [it] is in conflict with
the Constitution, and void
254
Since the indictment did not
specify that Nunn’s weapon was concealed, the charges were
quashed.
After the Civil War, Georgia added a right to arms to its
state constitution. Although courts enforced this provision, they
rejected the Second Amendment as a limit on state power, and
also rejected the use of natural law.
255
4. Louisiana
In 1850, the Louisiana Su pr em e Court faced a challenge t o a
state law banning concealed carry, bu t allowing open carry. The
court considered the Second Amendment to be applicable to the
states—to protect an individuals right to carry a gun for
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1431
256. See St at e v. Ch an dle r, 5 La . Ann. 489, 490 (18 50).
[The law] interfered with no ma n’s right to carry arms (to use its words) “in
full open view,” which pla ces m en up on an equality. This is the right
guaranteed by the Constitution of the United States, and which is calculated
to incite men to a manly and n oble defence of them selves, if necessary, an d
of their country, without any tendency to secret a dvantages an d un manly
assassinations.
Id.
257. See Sm it h v. St at e, 1 1 La . An n. 633 , 633 (1856).
The statute against carr ying concealed weapons does not contravene the
secon d article of the amendments of the Constitution of the United States.
The arms there spoken of are such as are borne by a people in war, or at
least carried openly. The a rticle explains itself. It is in these words: “A well
regulated militia being necessary to the security of a free State, th e right
of the people to keep and bear ar ms sha ll not be infringed.” This was never
intended to prevent t he ind ividua l St at es fr om a dopt ing su ch m ea sure s of
police as might be n ecessa ry, in order to prot ect th e or derly and well
disposed citizens from th e treach erous use of wea pon s not e ven design ed for
any purpose of public defence, and used most frequently by evil-disposed
men who seek a n advan tage over t heir an tagonist s, in the disturbances and
breaches of the peace which they are prone to provoke.
Id.
258. See State v. Jumel, 13 La. Ann. 399, 399-40 0 (18 58) (“ The statute in
quest ion does not infringe the right of the people to keep or bear arms. It is a
measure of police, prohibiting only a part icular m ode of bearing arms which is found
dangerous to th e pea ce of society.”).
259. See State v. News om, 27 N.C. (5 I red.) 250, 251 (1844) (up hold ing re striction
against possession of arms by free people of color since they were not parties to the
constitutional compa ct).
260. N.C. BILL OF RIGHTS § XVII (1776); see supra note 190.
personal defense—but held that a state law which banned only
carrying concealed did not violate the Second Amendment.
256
Subsequent cases in 1856
257
and 1858
258
reaffirmed this holding.
5. North Carolina
An 1844 decision of the North Carolin a Su pr em e Court
relied on Barron v. Baltim ore to rule that the Second
Amendment does not constrain state laws.
259
The state
constitution provided
[t]hat the people have a right t o bea r a rm s, for th e defen ce of
the State; and, as standing armies, in time of peace, are
dangerous to liberty, th ey ou ght n ot t o be kept up; and that
the military should be kept u nder s tr ict subordin at ion to, a nd
governed by, the civil power.
260
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1432 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
261. See Newsom, 27 N.C. at 254-55.
262. See Stat e v. Kerner, 107 S.E. 222, 224-26 (N.C. 1921) (citing Cooley to
declare unconstit utional a law against carrying pist ols, openly or concealed, on public
proper ty); Stat e v. S peller, 86 N .C. 697, 700-01 (1882); S tate v. Hu nt ly, 25 N .C. (3
Ired.) 418, 42 2-23 (184 3); see also Car l W. Thu rm an, III, N ote, State v. Fenn ell: The
North Car olin a T rad ition of Reason abl e Regulat ion of th e Right to Bear Arms, 68 N.C.
L. Rev . 1078 (1 990) (dis cus sin g va rious t went iet h ce nt ur y cases).
263. See Cock ru m v . St at e, 2 4 Te x. 394, 397 (185 9).
264. Id. at 402.
Although this provision was replet e with ant istanding army
language, the court held that the North Carolina provision
guaranteed more than just a right to the state militia. The
North Carolina Supreme Court treated the constitutional
guarantee as protecting a right of all persons to possess and
carry firearms, including for defensive purposes. The court
held, however, that an implicit exception allowed the
legislature to exclude free blacks from enjoying t his right;
therefore an 1840 law requiring free blacks who wished to own
guns to obtain a license was constitutional.
261
(The implication,
of course, was that a licensing statute applied to a citizen with
full civil rights would be unconstitutional.)
The North Car olina courts decision illustrates tha t, contra
the central argument of the anti-individualists, concer n about
standing armies is not inconsist en t wit h pr otect ion of a broad
individual right to personal defense. The other North Carolina
decisions from the nineteenth century (and the twentieth)
treated the arms rights provision as protective of an important
individual right of personal defense.
262
6. Texas
A Texas statute specified that manslaughter with a Bowie
knife or dagger would be treated as murder, and a defendant in
Cockrum v. State claimed that his conviction under this statute
violated the Second Amendment.
263
The court began by
explaining that the introductory clause of the Second
Amendmenthas referenee [sic] to the perpetuation of free
government, and is based on the idea, that the people cannot be
effectually oppressed a nd enslaved , wh o are not first
disarmed.”
264
The Texas clause “has the same broad object in
rela tion to the government, and in addition thereto, secures a
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1433
265. Id.
266. See id. at 402-03. “The right to carry a bowie-knife for lawful defense is
secured, and must be admitted. It is an exceeding destructive weapon. . . . The gun
or pistol may miss its aim . . . . The bowie-knife . . . is the instrument of almost
certa in death.” Id. at 403.
267. See En glis h v . St at e, 3 5 Te x. 473, 474 -75 (1872 ).
268. The English case h igh ligh ts th e flip sid e of the “civilized war fare” coin: if
“civilized warfare” was a good rationa le for excludin g various sm all weapons from the
right to ar ms, it could also im ply the right to own all military type weapons.
However, as Don Kates points out, the t extual language “keep and bearsuggests
that only per sonall y por ta ble w ea pons a re wit hin th e scop e of the right to “arms”;
therefore, th e siege gun a nd oth er form s of crew-served, non -portable artillery would
not be covered by the a rm s righ t. See Kates, Handgun Prohibition, supra note 1, at
261.
personal right to the citizen.”
265
In other words, the Second
Amendment guaranteed a right to possess arms to resist
tyranny, but not a right to possess arms for personal protection.
A second implication was that the Second Amendment was a
collective right, rather than a “personal” one. But there is no
indication that the Texas court meant that individual citizens
could not exercise Second Amendment rights. The court, basing
its decision on the Texas arms right, simply ruled that the law
was constitutional because it did not ban the carrying of the
Bowie knives, but merely set a higher penalty for criminal
misuse of this pa rticularly danger ous wea pon .
266
After the Civil War, while Texas was under a
Reconst ruction government very much concerned with
Confederate sympathizers, the legislature banned the carrying
of certain edged and blunt weapon s, whet her openly or
concealed; ther e wer e exceptions for carrying under certain
circumstances. Deciding a Second Amendment and Texas
Const itution challenge to the law, the Texas Supreme Court
decision in English v. State declared that the Second
Amen dment bound the states.
267
Following “civilized warfare”
precedent from other states,
268
the court stated
The word “arms” in the connection we find it in the
constit ution of the United States, refers to the arm s of a
militiaman or soldier , an d the word is u sed in its m ilitary
sense. The arms of the infantry soldier are the musket and
bayonet; of cavalry and dragoons, the sabre, holster pistols and
car bin e; of th e a rt iller y, the field piece, siege gun, an d m ort ar ,
with side arm s.
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1434 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
269. English , 35 Tex. at 476-77.
270. State v. Duk e, 4 2 Te x. 455, 458 (1875).
271. Id.
272. See id.
273. See Du nn e v. Pe ople , 94 Ill. 120, 124-2 8 (18 79).
274. The court was quoting language from Article I, Section 8 of the Constitution,
which in fact gives such authority to Congress. This grant is not inconsist ent with
pre-existent state authority, so long a s the sta te authorit y is not u sed in conflict with
the federal authority. See Houston v. Moore, 14 U.S. (1 Wheat.) 1, 16-17 (1820)
(holding that s ta te au th ority ove r t he mi lit ia pr e-exists th e Cons ti tu tion); 1
BLACKSTONE, supra note 14, app. at 273.
The terms dirks, daggers, slungshots, sword-canes, brass
knuckles an d bowie kn ives, belong to no military vocabulary.
269
Three yea rs later, political power in Texas h ad shifted, and
State v. Duke repudiated English’s narrow reading of the type
of arms protected. Th e Texa s Const itution was r ead t o pr otect
allarms as are commonly kept, according to the customs of the
people, and are appropriate for open and manly use in self-
defense, as well as such as are proper for the defense of the
State.”
270
These included, besides the weapons described in
English,the double-barreled shot-gun, the huntsmans rifle,
and such pistols at least as are not adapted to being carried
concealed.”
271
Duke rejected the defendant’s effort to raise the
Second Amendment, stating that the Second Amendment did
not limit the states, and thus based the decision solely on the
Texas Const itution.
272
7. Illinois
In Dunne v. People, the Illinois Su pr em e Court affirmed the
centrality of state power over the militia, citing the Tenth
Amendment and the United States Supreme Court’s Houston v.
Moore precedent.
273
The Dunne Court also explained how a
state’s constitutional duty to operate a militia was
complemented by the right of the state’s citizens to have arms:
“A well regulate d m ilit ia being n ecessary to the secu rity of a
free State, the States, by an amendment to the constitution,
have imposed a restriction that Congress shall not infringe the
right of the “people to keep and bear arms.” The chief
executive officer of the State is given power by t he con stitu tion
to call out t he m ilitia “to execu te the laws, suppress
insu rr ection an d r epel in vasion .”
274
This would be a mere
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1435
275. Dunne, 94 Ill. at 132-33.
276. See W. VA. CONST. art. 3, § 22 (“A person has the r ight to keep and bear
arms for t he defens e of self, fam ily, h ome and state, and for lawful hunting and
recreational us e.”) (ena cted in 1986 ); see also Halbrook, supra note 19, at 68.
277. State v. Work ma n, 35 W . Va. 367, 367 (1 891 ).
278. Id. (quoting W. VA. CODE ch. 148, § 7).
279. Id. at 372.
280. Id. at 373 (citing Bish. Crim. St. § 792). Fur ther, t he court explained, th e
Secon d Am en dm en t wa s in ten de d t o p r ot ec t “pu bl ic li be rt y, ” a nd incorpora ted va rious
restrictions from E nglish law r egar ding t he carr ying of weapons. Id. at 372-73.
barren gran t of power u nless the Sta te had power to organize
its own militia for its own pu rposes. Un orga nized, t he militia
would be of no practical aid to th e executive in main ta inin g
order and in protecting life and prop er ty wit hin th e lim its of
the State. These are duties that devolve on the State, and
unless th ese righ ts ar e secur ed t o th e citizen, of wh at worth is
the State government?
275
8. West Virginia
West Virginia did not have a state constitutional right to
arms until the twentieth century.
276
The 1891 case of State v.
Workman involved a Second Amendment challenge to a statute
banning th e carrying of “any revolver or other pistol, dirk,
bowie-knife, razor, slung-shot, billy, met allic or other false
knuckles, or any other da nger ous or deadly weapon of like kind
or character.”
277
The statute allowed the defendant to win an
acquittal by proving that he was “carrying su ch weapon for s elf-
defence and for no other purpose.”
278
The applicability of the Second Amendment to the states
was, sa id the court, “a question upon which authorities
differ.”
279
Following the “civilized warfare” theory of other state
courts, West Virginia stated that the Second Amendment
protected ownership of
the weapons of warfare to be used by the m ilitia, su ch as
swords, guns, rifles, an d m uskets—arm s to be u sed in
defending the State and civil liberty—and not to pistols, bowie-
knives, brass knu ckles, billies, and such other weapons as are
usually employed in brawls, street-fights, duels, an d affrays,
and are only habitua lly carried by bu llies, blackgu ards, and
despara does, to t he ter ror of th e com munity an d t he in jury of
the State.
280
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1436 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
281. In addition to the cases discussed above, see Walburn v. Territory, 59 P.
972, 973 (Okla. 1899) (holding that a concealed weapon statute “violates none of the
inhibitions of the constit ut ion of the Un ited Sta tes”).
282. In addition to the cases discussed above, see State v. Shelby, 90 Mo. 302
(1886) (holding that the Second Amendment is inapplicable to the states; that a law
against carrying concealed weapons in certain places except when n ecessa ry for
personal defense is valid; that a law against carrying a weapon while intoxicated is
valid; an d t ha t a “revolving pist ol” is w ithi n s cope of st at e r igh t t o ar ms ).
283. But not everyone thought th at dirk s were only for scoundrels. Nathaniel
Beverly Tucker, son of St. George Tu cker (and, like his father, a law professor at
William and Mary and a state court judge) wrote a novel in which one of the heroes
(a Virginian wh o is participat ing in a guer illa war against a tyrannical federal
government) carries a dirk. See NATHANIEL BEVE RLY TUCKER, THE PARTISAN LEADER:
A TALE OF THE FUTURE 12 (197 1) (1856).
Thus, the anticarrying statute stood. However, the individual
rights implications of the decision are clear.
9. State case law summary
The majority of state courts in the nineteenth century
upheld restrictions on the carrying of concealed weapon s.
Courts affirmed the righ t of citizens t o carry firearms openly for
protection but held that concealed carry could be regulated, or
even banned, by the legislature.
281
Courts differed on whether
the Second Amendment applied directly to the states.
282
Similar ly, most st ate courts u ph eld restrictions on the types
of weapons which were protected by the state right to arms.
Rifles, shotguns, some or all handguns, and swords were
protected; but weapons thought to be associated with dangerous
characters—in particular , dirks and bowie kniveswere
gen erally held to be outside the scope of the righ t to arms.
283
While validat ing par ticular gun controls, every nineteenth
century state court judge who sa id anything about the Second
Amendment, except for one concurring judge in an 1842
Arkansas case, agreed that it protected the right of individua l
Americans to own firearms.
IV. ANTEBELLUM YEARS AND THE CIVIL W AR
The right to bear arms was often analyzed with the issue of
slavery in mind. Proslavery and abolitionist commentators
agreed: a freedman had the right to bear arms, while
disarmament was an essential characteristic of a slave.
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1437
284. S ee, e.g., Kat es, Hand gun Prohibit ion, supra note 1, at 246; Kopel & Little,
supra note 1, at 526.
285. Scott v. Sanford, 60 U.S. (19 How.) 393, 417 (1856). Of course, Chief Justice
Taney did not explicitly say “and the right to keep and bear arms wher ever they
went, which is guaranteed by the Second Amendment,” any more than he explicitly
said “the righ t t o hold public m eet ings u pon political affa irs, which is guar anteed by
the Fir st Am endmen t.”
286. Id. at 450.
A. Dred Scott
Dred S cott ma y be the best-known case decided by the
antebellum Supreme Court. Even persons who think that
Marbury vs. Madison ” was a n impor tant boxing match may
have some passin g familiarity withDred Scott.” The Dred
Scott case is sometimes found among Standard Model articles
on the Second Amendment,
284
but is entirely absent from the
anti-individual right articles.
Chief Justice Taney’s majority opinion held that a free bla ck
could not be an American citizen. To support this conclusion,
Justice Taney enumer ated the parade of horribles which would
follow from American citizenship for blacks: th ey would have
the right tothe full liberty of speech in pu blic and priva te upon
all subjects upon which its [a state’s] own citizens might speak;
to hold public meetings upon political affairs, and to keep and
carry arms wherever they went.
285
Another part of the opinion explained that Congress had no
power to infringe upon civil liberty (including, from the Taney
Court’s viewpoint, the righ t to possess pr operty in the form of
slaves) in the territories:
[N]o one, we p resume, will contend that Congress can make
any law in a Territ ory respecting the es ta blishmen t of religion ,
or t he free exercise ther eof, or ab rid gin g the freedom of speech
or of th e pre ss, or t he right of the people of the Territory
pea ceably to a ssem ble, an d t o petit ion th e Gover nmen t for the
redr ess of gr ieva nces. . . .
Nor can Congress deny to the people the right to keep and
bear arms, nor the right to trial by jury, nor compel any one to
be a wit ness against him self in a cr iminal pr oceed ing . . . .
286
The above statement, which treated the right to arms as one of
several enumerated constitutional right s belonging to
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1438 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
287. S ee, e.g., Stephen Dou glas, The Dividing Line Between Federal and Local
Authority: Popu lar S overeign ty in th e Territories, HARPERS, Sept. 1859, at 519, 530.
One other slavery case involving a Supreme Court Justice should be mentioned.
In 1833, two months after Barron v. Baltimore was decided, Supreme Court Ju stice
Henry Baldwin, while circuit-riding, listed the Second Amendment among the
individual rights protected by the U.S. Con st itu tion , an d im plied t ha t t he Secon d
Amendment was binding on the states. See Johnson v. Tompkins, 13 F. Cas. 840
(C.C.E.D. Pa. 1833) (No. 7416). T he cas e of Johnson v. Tompkins arose out of a slave-
owner’s lawsuit against a Pennsylvania consta ble who had arrested t he slave-owner
for kidnappin g and breach of the peace while th e slave-owner was a ttempting to
recapture an alleged runaway slave. After the slave-owner, Johnson, was acquitted
of the criminal charges, he sued Tompkins and the others who had arrested him and
had interfered with his a ttempt to recaptur e his slave pr operty. (Justice Baldwin
instru cted the jury that although slavery’s existence “is abhorren t to all our ideas of
natural right and justice,” the jury must respect the legal sta tu s of slaver y. Id. at
843.)
As part of the jury charge, Justice Baldwin listed some of th e constitutional rights
possessed by the plaintiff, Johnson. J ustice Baldwin listed the Pennsylvania
Constitution’s right to acquire, possess, and protect property; the P enn sylvania
Constitution’s bar on deprivation of property except “by the judgement of his peers,
or the law of the land; and the Pennsylvania Constitution’s “right of citizens to bear
arms in defence of them selves and th e stat e.” Id. at 850. Justice Baldwin then began
listing Johnson’s rights under the U.S. Constitu tion—the Article IV guarantee that
the citizens of ea ch sta te shall be ent itled t o th e pr ivileges an d im mu nit ies of
citizens in the several states; the prohibition on stat e im pairment of th e obligat ions
of contract—and then stated that “[t]he second am endm ent provides, ‘that the right
of the people t o keep and bear arms shall not be infr inged.’Id. The rights litany
concluded with the ban on depriva tion of proper ty wit hout du e process. S ee id.
Additionally, Justice Baldwin explained the U.S. Constitution’s fugitive slave clause.
See id. at 850-51.
Ju stice Baldwin s list of righ ts m ade it clear t hat each of the r ights, including the
Secon d Amendment right to arms, was a personal right, since the right belonged to
the plain tiff. Since J ohns on’s lawsu it wa s a gain st an em ployee of a s ub division of th e
Pen nsylva nia state government, Justice Baldwin’s listing of the Second Amendment
implied that Justice Baldwin considered the Secon d Am endm ent t o be a re striction
on state actions against individuals.
In 1837, Justice Baldwin wrote A General View of the Origin and Nature of the
Constitu tion of th e Un ited States. S ee HENRY BALDWIN, A GENERAL VIEW OF THE
ORIGIN AND NATURE OF THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES (N.Y., Da Capo
Press 1970) (1837). The book focused on the political status of the states and the
people, examining the transitions from colony to independent states to confederated
states to parties to the Constitut ional compact. The book did not address the Second
Amendment or the militia.
individuals, was widely quoted during the debates over slavery
and popu lar sovereignty.
287
Dred Scott, while never formally overru led, is not good law
today, having been deliberately invalidated by sect ion one of
the Fourteenth Amendment. The purpose in discussing Dred
Scott is not to cite it as binding precedent, but to acknowledge it
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1439
288. Tom G. Palmer, Are Pa ten ts a n d Co py ri gh ts M or al ly J u st if ie d? T h e
Philosophy of Propert y R igh ts an d I deal Ob jects, 13 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POLY 817, 821
(1990).
289. See, e.g., LYSANDER SPOONER, AN ESSAY ON THE TRIAL BY JUR Y (1852);
LYSANDER SPOONER, THE LAW OF INTELLECTU AL PROPERTY: OR AN ESSAY ON THE RIGHT
OF AUTHORS AND INVE NTO RS TO A PERPETUAL PROPERTY IN THEIR IDEAS (1855).
290. Jules Lobel, Losers, Fools & Prophets: Ju stice as Struggle, 80 CORNELL L.
REV. 1331, 1 359 (199 5).
291. See Tom G. Palmer, Book Review, The Lysan der S poon er R ead er (visited
Jan. 16, 1998) <http://www.laissezfaire.org/pl5578.htm l>.
292. C. Shively, In trod uction to 4 LYSANDER SPOONER, COLLECTED WORKS 11
(1971). But see ROBERT M. COVER, JUSTICE ACCUSED: ANTISLAVERY AND THE JUDI CIAL
PROCESS 156-58 (1975) (arguing that Spooner did not r eally intend to prove tha t
as one of several nineteenth-century Supreme Court cases
involving the right to arms—all of which, as we shall see, treat
the Second Amendment as an individual right.
B. The Human Rights Advocates
Antislavery activists deplored Dred Scott, but they agreed
with Chief Justice Taney that owning and carrying guns was a
badge and incident of freedom and was inconsistent with status
as a slave. The abolitionists used this theory, however, to reach
a conclusion opposite to Taney’s. Their basic argument was that
the institution of slavery, which prevented certain people from
bearing arms, was r epugnant to the Second Am endm ent, wh ich
guaranteed the right to bear arms to all persons. The argument
thus illustrates the popularly held belief that the Second
Amendment guaranteed a personal right.
1. Lysander Spooner
Lysander Spooner was surely one of the most rema rkable
Amer ican men of letters of the Nineteenth Century.”
288
He
wrote important books an d pamphlet s on scores of subjects,
from intellectual property to the right to jury trial.
289
But his
greatest passion was antislavery. “[O]ne of the most prominent
radical theorists”
290
of th e antebellum era, Lysander Spooner
was a hero to many antislaver y activist s, including J ohn
Brown, whose raid on Harpers Ferr y was inspired by reading
Spooner.
291
Spooner’s prewar writing remained influential after
the Civil War, making Spoonerpre-eminent in the group of
abolitionists who developed the constitutional law now
incorporated in the Fourteenth Amendment.”
292
He remains a
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1440 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
slavery was un constitut ional, and that he sought instead to convince abolitionists to
seek out jud ges hips, so t ha t t he y cou ld fr ee sla ves ).
293. Spooner distributed many of his works thr ough an alterna tive mail system,
sin ce ma ny pr osla ver y pos tm as te rs refus ed t o car ry antislavery literature. Spooner’s
Ame ri can Mail Company was cheaper than the United States Post Office, which led
the Post Office to lower its rates, and Congress to pass “Spooner Acts,” forbidding
competiti on with the governmen t postal monopoly. See Dmit ry N. Feofanov, Luna
Law: The Libertarian Vision in Heinlein’s The Moon is a Ha rsh Mistress, 63 TENN.
L. REV. 71, 133 (1995). Spooner is one of th e fat her s of cheap posta ge in America . See
Ernest A. Kehr et a l., Look Before You Lick, READERS DIGEST, June 1947, a t 126.
294. The compact which exists between the North a nd the South is a covenant
with death and an agreement with hell.” William Lloyd Garr ison, Resolu tion Ad opted
by the Antislavery Society, Jan. 27, 1843, available online at William Lloyd Garrison.
1804-1879. (visited Sept . 22, 19 98) <http://www.sol.com.sg/classroom/references/bartlett /
346.htm >; cf. Isaiah 28:15 (We have made a covenan t with death, and with hell are
we at agre em en t.”).
295. David A. J. Rich ards, Abolitionist Political and Constitutional Theory and
the Reconstruction Amendments, 25 LOY. L.A. L. REV. 118 7, 1193 (199 2).
296. See HALBROOK, THAT EVER Y MAN BE ARMED, supra note 1, at 231 nn. 82-83.
For a modern analysis of the essay, see gener ally Ra ndy E . Bar net t, Was Slavery
Unconstitutional Before th e Th irteenth A m end m ent ?: Lysan der S pooner’s Th eory of
Interp retation , 28 PAC. L.J . 977 (199 7).
popular author among libertarians and other advocates of small
government.
293
In contrast to Willia m Lloyd Garrison and his Antislavery
Society, who denounced the Constitution as pr oslavery,
294
Spooner was “t he most theoretically profoun d a dvocat e” of th e
position that slavery was unconstitutional.
295
In the widely-
distributed and frequently reprinted book The
Unconstitutionality of Slavery, Spooner argued that the
Const itution should be interpreted according to principles of
natural justice.
296
His natural justice interpretation of the
Second Amendment explained:
This rightto keep and bear arms, implies the right to use
them—as much as a provision securing to the people the right
to buy and keep food, would imply their right also to eat it. But
this implied right to use arm s, is on ly a righ t to use them in a
manner consistent with natural rights—as, for example, in
defence of life, liberty, chastity, &c. . . . If the court s could go
beyond the innocent and necessary meaning of the words, and
imply or infer from them an authority for anything contrary to
natural right, t hey cou ld imply a constitutional authority in
the people to u se a rm s, not m erely for t he just and innocent
purposes of defence, but also . . . robbery, or any other acts of
wrong to which arms are capable of being applied. The mere
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1441
297. LYSANDER SPOONER, THE UNCONSTITUTIONALITY OF SLAVERY 66 (Burt
Franklin 1965) (1860). For reprinted selections, see Lysander Spooner, The
Unconstitutionality of Slavery, 28 PAC. L.J . 1015, 1022 (199 7).
298. S ee, e.g., ROSCOE POUND, THE DEVELOPMENT OF CONS TITU TION AL
GUARANTEES OF LIBERTY 91 (1957) (“In th e urban ind us tr ial societ y of t oday a general
right to bear efficient arms so as to be enabled to r esist oppression by the
government would mean that gangs could exercise an extra-legal r ule which would
defeat th e wh ole Bill of Righ ts.”). Alth ough Pou nd is sometimes cited by opponents
of the Sta ndard Model, Poun d’s point is not really tha t the Standard Model is wrong
as a m at te r of hist ory, but sim ply th at th e Secon d Am endment is n o longer a good
idea as a m att er of public policy. Pound’s view that th e Second Amendment could be
ignored if modern persons thought it was no longer a good idea is consistent with his
general view that legislation which once would have been clearly unconstitutional
could be con sider ed con st itu tion al in m oder n t imes, based on changed social needs.
See generally Roscoe Pound, Mech an ical J ur ispru den ce, 8 COLUM. L. REV. 605 (1908).
verbal implication would as much authorize the people to use
arms for unjust, as for just, purposes. But the legal im plica tion
gives only an authority for their innocent use.
297
Spooner obviously viewed the Second Amendment as a right
belonging to individuals. His exposition is an answer to
twentieth-century gun pr ohibition advocates who assert that an
individual right to arms constitutes a right protecting crimin als
who use weapons offensively.
298
Spooner used the Second Amendment to argue that slavery
was unconstitutional. Since a slave is a person who cannot
possess arms, and the Second Amendment guarantees that all
persons can possess arms, no person in the United States,
therefore, can be a slave. Similarly, the militia clause—Article
I, Section 8—gives Congress the power to have everyone armed.
He elaborated:
These pr ovisions obviously r ecogn ize t he n at ura l right of
all m en “to ke ep an d bear a rm s” for their personal defence;
and prohibit both Con gress and the Sta te govern m en ts from
infring ing th e r igh t of “the p eop le”—t hat is, of any of th e
people—to do so; and more esp ecially of any wh om Congress
have power to include in their militia. The right of a man “to
keep and bea r a rm s,” is a right palpably inconsistent with th e
idea of his being a slave. Yet the right is secured a s effectua lly
to those whom th e Sta tes presu me to call sla ves , as to a ny
whom the States condescend to acknowledge free.
Under th is provision an y m an has a r igh t eith er to give or
sell arm s to those persons whom the States call s la ve s; a nd
there is n o constitutional power, in either the national or State
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1442 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
299. SPOONER, supra note 297, at 98.
300. See U.S. CONST. ar t. IV, § 2, cl. 3 (“No Per son held to Ser vice or Labour in
one Stat e, u nder th e La ws t he reof, esca pin g into a not her, s ha ll, in Conseque nce of
any Law or Regulation therein, be discharged from such Service or Labour, but shall
be delivered up on Claim of the Party to whom such Service or Labou r m ay be d ue .”).
Spooner attacked this clause by claiming that since the clause did not specifically
ment ion slaves, the clause shou ld, consistent with natural justice, be rea d as a pplying
to indentured servants.
301. LYSANDER SPOONER, A DEFEN CE FOR FUGITIVE SLAVES 27 (1850). The
Fugitive Slave Act promoted widespread violence in the recapture of fugitive slaves,
in Nort her n wh ite vigilan te resist ance to the slave-hunter s an d to federal authorities,
and in th e u se of th e U .S. milit ar y aga inst th e vigila nt es. “In th ese fr igh tfu l
circumstances, blacks warned t heir fellows to keep firearms close at hand.” NELL
IRVIN PAINTER, SOJOURNE R TRUTH: A LIFE, A SYMBOL 133 (199 6).
governments, that can punish him for so doing; or that can
take those arms from the slaves; or that can make it criminal
for the sla ves to u se t hem, if, from t he inefficiency of th e laws,
it sh ould becom e n ecessa ry for them to d o so, in defence of
th eir own lives or lib erties; for t his constitu tion al right to keep
arms implies the constitutional right to use them, if need be,
for the defence of one’s liberty or life.
299
Twentieth century readers are not required to find
Spooner’s argument persuasive. Article IV, Section 2 of the
Const itution, requiring the retu rn of fugitive slaves, obviously
contemplated that persons in the United States could be
slaves.
300
Instead, the point for purposes of this article is that
Spooner saw the Second Amendment as guaranteeing an
individual right to own and u se guns for self-defense or defense
of others, and he used this fact in arguing against slavery.
Spooner made further use of the Second Amendment’s
individual right to arms in other arguments. Advocating the
right of fugitive slaves to use weapons to resist recapture,
Spooner wrote:
The cons tit ution contemplates no such submission, on the
part of the people, to the u su rp at ions of the governmen t, or to
the lawless violence of its officers. On the contrary it provides
thatThe right of the people to keep and bear arms shall not
be infrin ged .” This cons tit ution al secu rit y for “the right to keep
and bear arms, implies the right to use them . . . . The
constit ution , th erefore, ta kes it for gran ted tha t, as the peop le
have the right, they will also have the sense, to use arms,
wh enever the necessit y of th e case ju stifies it.
301
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1443
302. SPOONER, supra note 297, at 104.
303. LYSANDER SPOONER, AN ESSAY ON THE TRIAL BY JURY 17 (1852 ).
304. LYSANDER SPOONER, ADDRESS OF THE FREE CONSTITUTIONALISTS TO THE
PEOPLE OF THE UNITED STATES 25 (2 d ed. 1860 ).
305. See JOEL TIFFANY, THE NEW YORK PRACTICE: A TREATISE UPON PRACTICE AND
PLEADINGS IN ACTIONS AND SPECIAL PROCEEDINGS (186 4-18 65); J OEL TIFFANY, THE LAW
OF TRUSTS AND TRUSTEES, AS ADMINISTERED IN ENGLAND IN AMERICA (1862).
306. RAOUL BERGER, GOVE RN ME NT BY JUDICIARY: THE TRANSFORMATION OF THE
FOURTEE NTH AMENDMENT 22 (1977); Raoul Berger, Bruce Ackerman on Interpretation:
A Critique, 1992 BYU L. REV. 1035, 1043 n.43 (1992) (reviewing BRUCE ACKE RMAN ,
WE THE PEOPLE : FOUNDATIONS (199 1)).
307. Trisha Olson, The Natural Law F oun da tion of th e Privil eges or Im m un iti es
Clause of th e Fou rteent h A m end m ent , 48 ARK. L. REV. 347, 373 n.109 (1995) (citing
various scholar s); see also WILLI AM M. WIECEK, THE SOURCES OF ANTISLAVERY
Similar ly, Spooner argued that unconstitutional laws need not
be obeyed pending their repeal; to require obedience to
unconstitutional laws would be to allow the governmentto
disarm the people, suppress the freedom of speech and the
press, prohibit the use of suffra ge, an d thus put it beyond the
power of the people to reform the government through the
exercise of those rights.”
302
Thus, the right to arms provided one
of the ways in which people could rea sser t control over an
erring government.
In Spooner’s best seller, the 1852 An Essay on the Trial by
Jury, he used language drawn from the paragraph quoted
above to prove that theright of resistance is recognized by t he
constitution of the United States.”
303
In the 1860 Address of the
Free Constitutionalists, Spooner again made the argument that
the right to keep and bear arms implies the right to use them,
and, therefore, this is an inherent right of people to resist
criminal assaults when the government fails to provide
protection.”
304
2. Joel Tiffany
Joel Tiffany made his living as the reporter for the New
York Court of Appeals, as an author of legal treatises,
305
and as
publisher of Tiffany’s Monthly magazine. But like Lysander
Spooner, he was consumed with the antislavery cause.
Lysander Spooner and Joel Tiffany were “the ‘principal
spokesmen’ and theorist s of the abolitionist movement.”
306
Spooner’s and Tiffany’s importance is recognized by nearly
all.”
307
The Spooner and Tiffany theory that the Constitution
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1444 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
CONSTITUTIONALISM IN AMERICA, 1760-1848, at 269 (1977); Micha el Kent Cu rtis, The
Bill of R igh ts as a Lim ita tion on S tate A ut hority : A R eply to Professor B erger, 16
WAKE FOREST L. REV. 45, 55 (1 980 ); John Choon Yoo, Our Declaratory Ninth
Amendment, 42 EMORY L.J . 967, 1000 (1993) (“Influential abolitionist writers such as
Lysander Spooner an d J oel T iffany . . . .”).
308. David S. Bogen, The Tran sform ation of th e Fourteent h A m end m ent :
Reflection s from the Admission of Maryland’s First Black Lawyers, 44 MD. L. REV.
939, 964 (198 5).
309. JOEL TIFFANY, A TREATISE ON THE UNCONSTITUTIONALITY OF AME RICAN
SLAVERY 117-18 (1849).
guaranteed certain rights to all citizens “marked out a path for
using the doctr ines of substantive du e process and of the
natural law privileges and immunities of citizenship to further
minority freedom.”
308
Like Spooner, Tiffany argued that the Second Amendment’s
guarantee of a right to arms applied to all persons, and since an
armed man could not be a slave, slavery was unconstitutional.
Here is another of the immunities of a citizen of the United
States, which is guaranteed by the su prem e, organ ic law of th e
land. This is one of the su bordinate rights, mentioned by
Bla ckston e, as belonging to every Englishman. It is called
subordinate in reference to the great, absolu te righ ts of man;
and is accorded to ever y subje ct for th e p urpos e of protecting
and defending h im self, if need be, in the enjoymen t of his
absolute rights to life, liberty and property. And this guaranty
is to all without any exception; for there is none, either
expressed or im plied. An d ou r cou rt s have already decided,
that in such cases we have no right to make any exceptions. It
is har dly n ecessar y to rem ar k t ha t t his guar an ty is absolutely
inconsistent with permitting a portion of our citizens to be
enslaved. The colored citizen, under our constitution, has now
as full and perfect a right to keep and bear arms as any other;
and no State law, or State regulation has authority to deprive
him of that right.
But ther e is a nother thin g im plied in this gu aranty; a nd
that is the right of self defence. For the right to keep and bear
arm s, also implies the right to use them if necessa ry in self
defence; without this right to use the gu aran ty would ha ve
hardly been worth the paper it consumed.
309
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1445
C. Bloody Kansas
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1446 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
310. Invented in 1848, the Sh arps could fire five rounds a m inute; it rapidly
displaced muzzle-loading guns and was especially popular in the West. John Brown’s
raiders carr ied the Sha rps carbine (a type of short rifle). See HAROLD F. WILLIAMSON,
WINCHESTER: THE GUN THAT WON THE WEST 5 (19 52).
311. See JAY MONAG HAN, CIVIL WAR ON THE WESTERN BORDER 1854-1865 (1955).
Although th e a boliti on movem en t h ad a s tr ong st ra in of non-resistance and pacifism,
theBeecher Bibles” were widely approved. For example, Wendell Ph illips sa id, “I
believe the age of bullets is over. I believe the age of ideas is come . . . . Yet, let me
say, in passing, tha t I t hink you can make a bett er use of iron than forging it in to
chains. If yo u m u st h a ve m et a l, pu t it in t o S h ar pe ’s [s ic ] r ifle s.” L AWRENCE J.
FRIE DMAN , GREGARIOUS SAINTS: SELF AND COMMUNITY IN AMERICAN ABOLITIONISM,
1830-1870, at 210 (1982) (omission in original).
Just as the civil war in Spain served as a prelude to World
War II, civil war broke out in the Territory of Kansas several
years before the American Civil War . Following the 1854
Kansas-Nebraska Act, proslavery and antislavery settlers
rushed in to take control of the territory and win the vote on
whether Kan sas would join the Union as slave or free. Th e pro-
slave forces, with hea vy support fromBorder Ruffians in
Missouri, stuffed ballot boxes, violently drove free soilers away
from the polls in 1855, and expelled all slavery opponents from
the territorial legislature.
The free-soil settlers asked for guns for themselves, and the
Massachusetts Emigrant Aid Company prompt ly began
smuggling Sharps Rifles t o Kansas. (The Company falsely
claimed that while some of its members might be sending rifles,
the armament program was not officially run by the Compan y.)
The Sharps were high-tech rifles, incorpor ating the new br eech
loading design (as opposed to loading from the muzzle).
310
The
rifles did their job and rapidly evened the balance of power in
Kansas. The proslavery government, however, attempted, with
some success, to disarm various armed groups of free-soil
men.
311
On May 19, 1856, Massachusetts Senator Charles
Sumner—an antislavery radical—rose to deliver what would
become one of the most famous orations ever delivered on the
floor of the United Stat es Senate. Sumners speech, “The Crime
against Kansas,” continued until t he twentiet h of Ma y. South
Carolina Senator A.P. Butler had allegedly remarked that the
people of Kansas should be disarmed of their Sharps rifles.
Sumner thundered:
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1447
312. CHARLES SUMNER, THE KANSAS QUESTION. SENATOR SUMNERS SPEECH ,
REVIEWING THE ACTION OF THE FEDERAL ADMINISTRATION UPON THE SUBJECT OF
SLAVERY IN KANSAS 22-23 (Cin cinna ti, G. S . Bla nch ar d, 1856) (repr inting speech
delivered on the floor of th e Sen at e, May 19-20, 1856), also available online at
<htt p://m oa.um dl.u mich.
edu/cgi-bin/moa/sgml/moa-idx?notisid=ABT6369>.
313. The speech (incl ud ing Bu tl er ’s len gthy qu ota tion of Su mn er ) was reprinted
for general circula tion. See ANDREW PICKINS BUTLER, SPEECH OF HON. A. P. BUTLER,
OF SOUTH CAROLINA, ON THE BILL TO ENABLE THE PEOPLE OF KANSAS TERRITORY TO
FORM A CONSTITUTION AND STATE GOVERNMENT, PREPARATORY TO THEIR ADMISSION
INTO THE UNION, ETC. 24 (Washington, D.C., Union Office 1856), also available online
<http://moa.umdl.u mich.edu/cgi-bin/moa/sgm l/ moa-idx?notisid=AJA3511>.
South Carolina Representative Preston Brooks, Butler’s nephew, was so infuriated
by Sumner’s atta cks on Brooks (such as the claim that while Brooks “believes himself
a chivalrous kn ight, with sentiments of honor and courage, he “has chosen a
mistress” who is “th e h ar lot s laver y”) that he bea t S um ner on the head with a heavy
cane until the cane broke, incapacitating Sumner for four years.
Really, sir, ha s it come to this? The rifle has ever been the
com pa n ion of the pioneer and, under God, his tutelary
protector aga inst th e r ed m an and t he bea st of th e forest.
Never was this efficient weapon more neede d in just self-
defence, than now in Kansas, and at least one article in our
National Constitution must be blotted out, before the complete
right to it can in any way be impeached. And yet such is the
madness of the hour, that, in defiance of the solemn guaranty,
embodied in the Amendments to the Constitution, that “the
right of the people to keep and bear arms shall not be
infringed,” the people of Kan sa s h ave be en ar ra ign ed for
keeping and bearing them, and the Senator from South
Carolina has had the face to sa y open ly, on th is floor, that they
should be disar med—of cours e, that th e fanat ics of Sla ver y, his
allies and cons tit uen ts, may meet n o impedim en t. Sir, t he
Senator is venerable . . . but n either h is yea rs , nor h is posit ion,
past or presen t, can give respecta bility to the demand he has
made, or save him from indignant condemnation, when, to
compass the wretched purposes of a wretched cause, he thus
proposes to trample on one of the plainest provision s of
constitutional liberty.
312
Senator Butler indignantly replied that he had never proposed
disarming the people of Kansas. He had simply proposed
bringing before appropriate judicial authority “an organized
body” who possessed Sharps rifles.
313
But even if Senator Butler could claim that his remarks
were misunderstood, antislavery Congressmen had no doubt
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1448 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
314. G.A. Grow, Adm ission of Kansas, J un e 30, 1856, reprinted in POLIT ICAL
SPEECHES, PARTLY IN THE HOUSE AND SENATE, DEALING MAINLY WITH KANSAS AND
SLAVERY 7 (Wash ingt on 1855), also av ail able online <ht tp://moa.u mdl.umich.ed u/cgi-
bin/moa/sgml/moa-idx?notisid=ABT6364>.
315. Reprinted in EVERETT CHAMBERLIN, THE STRUGGLE OF 72. THE ISSU ES AND
CANDIDATES OF THE PRESENT POLITICAL CAMPAIGN 23 (San Francisco, Union Publ.
187 2), also available online <htt p://moa.u md l.umich.e du/cgi-bin /moa /sgm l/moa-
idx?notisid=AEW6886>.
316. See GUNJA SENGUPTA , FOR GOD AND MAMMON: EVANGELICALS AND
ENTREPREN EURS, MASTERS AND SLAVES IN TERRITORIAL KANSAS , 1854-1860, at 105-11
(1996).
about the atrocities being perpetrated in Kansas.
Representative G.A. Grow of Pennsylvania, for example, gave a
litany of constitutional abuses perpetrated by the proslavery
government in Kansas, including: “With the shout of law and
order you disarm the citizen, while the Constitution of his
country declares that the right ‘to keep and bear arms shall not
be infringed.’
314
The 1856 national Republican Convention resolved thatthe
dearest cons titutional righ ts of the people of Kansas have been
fraudulently and violently taken from them . . . the rights of the
people to keep and bear arm s have been infringed.”
315
The federal governm ent, obviously, had done nothing to
interfere with the official militia of the proslavery government
in Kansa s. Yet the Republicans s till sa w a viola tion of the
Second Amendment: some of the state’s citizens were being
disarmed because they considered the current state government
illegitimate. Indeed, the event that had precipitated Repu blican
Sumner’s speech was the “Sack of Lawr ence,” in which the
Kansas territorial militia, bearing arms supplied by the United
States government and under the command of a deputy federal
marshal, confiscated the guns of a group of free-soilers.
316
The
Republicans, seeing their constituents disarmed, invoked the
Second Amendmen t. However, soon the Democrats would
invoke the Second Amendment to protest the disarmament of
citizens who did not belong to active state m ilitias.
D. The Civil War
During the Civil War, President Lincoln ordered many
suppressions of civil liberties. His suspension of habeas corpus
in states which were not in rebellion against the Union,
through which he imprisoned newspaper editors and other
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1449
317. S ee, e.g., Ex parte Milligan, 71 U.S. (4 Wall.) 2 (1866). See generally MARK
E. NE ELY, JR., THE FATE OF LIBERTY: ABRAHA M LINCOLN AND CIVIL LIBERTIES (1991)
(dealing exclusively with habeas corpus iss ue s a nd defen din g Lincoln ’s act ions).
318. See 3 WAR OF THE REBELLION, ser. 1, 467 (Frémont’s Declaration of Martial
Law, Aug. 30, 1861), quoted in HALBROOK, THAT EVER Y MAN BE ARMED, supra note
1, at 233 n.96. Frémont , of cour se, had been the 1856 Republican Presidential
candidate and had run on a plat form den oun cing th e pr osla ver y govern me nt of
Kansas for the sam e th ing he was now doing.
319. 13 id. at 506, quoted in HALBROOK, THAT EVERY MAN BE ARMED, supra note
1, at 233. In defense of Lincoln’s actions against people living in Confederate states,
William Whiting list ed var ious ind ividua l ri ghts protecte d by t he Constitu tion an d
then showed that they could not be applicable in time of war; otherwise, th e army
would not be able to kill enemy soldiers without due process. Similarly, “[i]f all men
have the right to ‘keep and bear arms’ what right has the army of the Union to take
them aw ay from r ebe ls?” H e con cluded t ha t t he Bill of Rights “[was ] inte nd ed as [a]
declara tion[] of the rights of peaceful an d loyal citizens,” and ther efore inapplicable
to th e Sout her n r ebels. WILLIAM WHITING, THE WAR POWERS OF THE PRESIDENT AND
THE LEGISLATIVE POWERS OF CONGRESS IN RELATION TO REBELLION, TREASON, AND
SLAVERY 49-51 (Boston , J .L S hore y 1862) available at <http://moa.u mdl.u mich.edu/cgi-
bin/moa/sgml/moa-idx?notisid=AEW5618>. Whit ing ser ved as a lead ing at tor ney for
the War Department; un der a modified tit le, this pam phlet was reprinted 43 t imes
over th e next eigh t yea rs. See Richard J . Pu rcell, William Whiting, in DICT. AM. BIO.,
supra note 90.
320. T.W. MCMAHON, CAUSE AND CONTRAST: THE AMERICAN CRISIS, excerpted in
32 DEBOWS REVIEW, AGRIC ULT URAL , COMM ERC IAL, INDUSTRI AL PROGRESS AND
RESOURCES 317 (1862), available online at <http://moa.u mdl.umich.edu/cgi-
bin/moa/sgml/moa-idx?notisid=
ACG1336-1315DEBO-31>.
persons who criticized the war, is the most famous.
317
Less well
known are the Union governments confiscations of firearms.
Although Maryland and Missouri never seceded, both states
had significant pockets of Confederate sympathizers. In
Missouri, Union General John C. Frémont issued an order
declaring that all persons in a certain area found in possession
of arms would be shot.
318
Later, General Marsh ordered a
general confiscation of all arms and ammunition, “not in the
hands of the loyal militia and the transfer of all such arms and
ammunition to the militia.
319
Confederates made sure that
Lincoln’s actions were publicized in the South; as on e book put
it:The right of th e people to keep and bear arms shall not be
infringed, says the constitution; but upon this privilege he has
trampled in Maryland, Missouri and Kentucky.”
320
The 1864 Dem ocratic Convention denounced Lincoln’s
suppression of civil liberties, condemningthe subversion of th e
civil by military law in States not in insurrection; the arbitrary
military arrests . . .; the suppression of freedom of speech and of
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1450 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
321. E. POLLARD, THE LOST CAUSE 574 (1867), quoted in HALBROOK, THAT EVERY
MAN BE ARMED, supra note 1, at 233 n.96.
322. C. CHAUNCEY BURR, NOTES ON THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES
(N.Y., J. F. Feeks 1864). Bu rr als o foun ded a monthly journal, The Old Guard , and
sometimes wrote for a N ew York n ewspaper, The Day Book or Caucasian. Few
Northerners sur passed Bu rrs strong opposition to Lincoln’s policies. See NEELY, supra
note 317, at 57.
323. U.S. CONST. art . I, § 8, cl. 15.
324. BURR, supra note 322, at 30-31.
325. See U.S. CONST. art . I, § 8, cl. 16.
326. BURR, supra note 322, at 34.
the press; . . . and the interference with and denial of the right
of the people to bear arms in their defence.”
321
Also in 1864, one of Lincoln’s strongest northern Democrat
critics, C. Chauncey Burr, authored Notes on the Constitution of
the United States.
322
The book analyzed the Constitution clause
by clause, adding commentary intended to show that President
Lincoln was viola ting the Constitution. Regarding federal
militia powers, Burr noted that the Constitution provided that
the militia could be called into federal service for three
purposes only: “to execu te the Laws of the Union, suppress
Insurrections, and repel Invasions.”
323
Burr contended that the
militia was being used improperly in the Civil War because the
war was not being fought to execute the laws of the Union, but
to abolish slavery and to subjugate the South. There was no
insurrection since state governments (as opposed to individuals
within a state) could not commit insurrection: state
governments “ar e not subjects. They are sovereign bodies.”
324
And obviously, there was no foreign power invading the United
States.
In discussing the next clause of the Constitution (granting
Congress authority over militia training standards and
discipline, while reserving to states the appointment of militia
officers and supervision of militia training),
325
Burr commented,
The militia is strictly a State institution. . . . The object of this
provision is to preserve the State character of the militiato
keep it as representative of State sovereignty, even while it is
but for a specified service under the direction of the United
States.
326
This would have been the perfect time to criticize
Lincoln for violating the Second Amendment had Burr thought
that the Amendment protected state militia from federal
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1451
327. Id. at 80.
328. Id. Here, Bur r accused the Lincoln government of the same act perpetrated
more than a century later by the Chicago Housin g Auth ority, with the encouragement
of th e Clint on a dm inist ra tion . See Pra tt v. Chicago Hous. Auth ., 848 F. Supp. 792
(N.D. Ill. 1 994) (h oldin g th at police swe eps of public h ous ing in or der to confiscate
firearms wa s u ncons titu tional).
329. See Amar, Th e Bil l of R igh ts a s a C ons titut ion, supra note 1, at 1171-73.
330. BURR, supr a note 322, at 81. Rep. Samuel Sullivan Cox made the same
argument on Feb. 26, 1863, in opposition to the Lincoln administration’s Conscript ion
Bill. Cox relied mainly upon t he m ilitia clauses and Just ice Story, bu t also cited the
Secon d Amendment . See SAMUEL SULLIVAN C OX, EIGHT YEARS IN CONGRESS, FROM
1857 TO 1865, at 313 (New York, D. Appleton & Co. 1865), als o availabl e online
<http://moa.
umdl.umich.edu/cgi-bin/moa/sgml/moa-idx?notisid=ACP4141>.
331. BURR, supra note 322, at 80.
interference. But the Secon d Am endm en t was a bsen t from
Burr’s criticism.
Instead, the Second Amendment discussion came much
later. Burr quoted J ustice Story at length on how tyrants
accomplish their purposes . . . by disarming the people.”
327
The present administration,” cha rged Burr, “has violated this
article of the Constitution in every particular. It has, in a great
many instances, disarmed the people by forcibly entering their
houses and seizing their arms of every description.”
328
Burr also
complained that the Lincoln administration had “substituted
United States soldiery for militia” and had imposed de facto
martial law by stationing regular troops in New York City.
And, as Akhil Amar would argue many years later,
329
Burr
wrote that federal conscription for a standing army violated the
Second Amendment, since conscription “tends to annihilate the
ranks of the state militias.
330
To Burr, Lincolns firearm confiscations apparently violated
the main clause of the Second Amendment (“the right of the
People”), while Lincoln’s reliance on a conscripted standing
army at the expen se of the militia viola ted the in trodu ctory
clause (“A well-regu lated militia, being necessary to the
security of a free St ate”), wh ich is why Lincoln’s policies could
be said to violate the Second Amendment “in every
particular.
331
Whether Lincoln’s policies were right or wrong is not the
subject of this article. The objections of the Democratic
Conven tion and Burr to Lincoln’s actions reflected the belief
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1452 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
332. For the discussion of the Fourteenth Amendment and the sta tutes which led
up to it , th e aut hor is deeply in deb te d to Steph en Ha lbr ook.
333. H.R. EXEC . DOC. NO. 70, at 233 , 236 (1866).
that the Second Amendment guaranteed the right of
individuals to bear arms.
V. RECONSTRUCTION AND LABOR UNREST
A. Congress, Civil Righ ts, and th e Fourteenth Am endm ent
After the Union victory in the Civil War, Congress debated
and pa ss ed various m easu res, such as t he Civil Rights Act and
the Fourt eenth Amendment, designed to protect the civil rights
of freedmen. During this period, the Second Amendment was
mentioned many times in Congressional testimony, in reports
to Congress, in Committee reports, and in floor debates.
332
These statements treated the Second Amendment as an
individual right. Record s of Congress from this era are replete
with references to the right” to arms, but since this article is
about the Second Amendment, and not about the state
constitutional or natural right to arms, this article quotes only
those st atem en ts t hat specifically refer to the Secon d
Amendment.
1. The Freedmen’s Bureau
The Freedm ens Burea u reported to Congress on the
numerous abuses of civil r igh ts t aking place in the defeated
Southern states. For example, in Kentucky, “[t]he civil law
prohibits the colored man from bearing arms . . . . Their arms
are taken from them by the civil authorities . . . . Thus, the
right of the people t o keep and bear arms as provided in the
Const itution is infringed . . . .”
333
Sim ila rly, General Ru fus
Saxton, the former assistant commissioner of the Freedmens
Burea u in Sou th Carolin a, provided Congress with evidence
that in some parts of th is Sta te ar med pa rt ies ar e, with out
proper authority, engaged in seizin g all fire-arm s foun d in th e
hands of th e freedm en . Su ch condu ct is in pla in and direct
violation of their personal rights as gua ranteed by the
Con stitu tion of the United States, which declares that “the
right of the people to keep and bear arms shall not be
infringed.” The freedmen of South Carolina ha ve shown by
their peacefu l and or derly condu ct t hat t hey ca n safely be
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1453
334. REPORT OF THE JOINT COMMITTEE ON RECONSTRUCTION, H.R. REP. NO. 39-30,
pt. 2, a t 2 29 (1 866).
335. See Ha lbrook, Personal Security, supra note 1, at 353-54, 363, 384-88, 396-
97, 401-02, 405-08, 414-15, 418, 424.
Related to the complaints about disarmament were complaints about Southern
governments’ tolera nt attitude a bout white violence against blacks. Virginia attorney
George Tucker (ye s, on e of the descen dant s of Hen ry St. George Tucker) testified
about the need for Congressiona l action t o protect blacks a gainst such abuses of the
unreconstructed gover nm en ts : “Th ey h ave not an y ide a of prosecutin g wh ite me n for
offenses a ga in st col or ed pe op le ; t h ey do n ot a pp rec ia t e t h e i de a .” McCleskey v. Kemp,
481 U.S. 279, 347 n.2 (1987) (quotin g H.R.J . COMM. REP. NO. 39-30, pt. 2, at 25
(1866)).
336. CONG. GLOBE, 39t h C ong., 1st Se ss. 371 (18 66).
337. Id. at 585.
trusted with fire-arm s, and they need them to k ill ga m e for
subsistence, and to protect their crops from destruction by
birds and animals.
334
Throughout Reconstruction, many witnesses and special
committees complained that unreconstructed governments and
terrorist organizations, such as the Ku Klux Klan, were
violating the Second Amendment rights of freedmen by
disarming them.
335
To address the civil rights viola tions, Congress t ook u p
Senate Bill 60, a bill to expand the powers of the Freedmens
Bureau. During debate over the bill, Kentucky Democratic
Senator Garret Davis emphasized that a shared commitment to
civil liberty united Americans more than party factionalism
divided them:
But there were some principles upon which those great, grand,
noble old parties agreed; and what were they? . . . They were
for every man bearing his arm s about him and keeping them
in his house, his castle, for his own defense. They were for
every right an d liberty secured to the citizen by the
Constitution.
336
In the House, Massachusetts Congressman Nathaniel
Banks announced his plans to offer a n amen dment to the bill
inserting after the word ‘including’ the words ‘the
constitutional right to bear arms;’ so that it will read, ‘including
the constitutional right to bear arms, the right to make and
enforce contracts, to sue.’
337
As passed by Congress, the final
bill reflected Banks’s desire for a specific r ecognition of th e
individual right to arms:
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1454 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
338. Act of J ul y 16, 1866, 14 S ta t. 173 , 176-77 (186 6).
339. 14 St at . 17 3, 176 (1866 ).
340. CONG. GLOBE, 39t h C ong., 1 st Sess. 1073 (1 866 ).
341. Id. at 1168.
That in every State or distr ict wh ere the or din ar y course of
judicial proceedings has been interr upt ed by t he r ebe llion, an d
until the sam e sha ll be fully restored . . . the right to make and
enforce contracts . . . and to ha ve full an d equa l ben efit of all
laws and proceedin gs concerning personal liberty, personal
security, and the acqu isit ion, en joym en t, a nd disposit ion of
estate, real a nd per sonal, including the constitutional right to
bear arms, shall be secured to an d enjoyed by a ll th e citizen s of
such State or district without r espect t o ra ce or color, or
previous condition of slavery.
338
President J ohnson vet oed the bill. Con gress, however , came
back with the Second Freedmen’s Bureau Bill, which it passed
over President Johnson’s veto. Section 14 of that Second Bill
contained the same language as that quoted above, protecting
the constitutional right to bear arms.”
339
2. Southern representation in Congress
In early 1866, Congress took up the question of whether the
defeated states should be allowed representation in Congress.
During the debate, Nevada Senator James W. Nye stated that
“[a]s citizens of the United States [freedmen] have equal right
to protection, and to keep and bear arms for self-defense. They
have long cherished the idea of liberty . . . .”
340
In support of Southern represen tation, Illin ois
Representative Anthony Thornton suggested that once the war
had ended, all constitutional rights were immediately restored.
In support of this theory, he argued:
In all of the northern States, du rin g th e war , th e privilege of
the writ of habeas corpus wa s susp en ded; freedom of speech
was denied; the freedom of the press was abridged; the right to
bear arms was infringed . . . . Our rights were not thereby
destroyed. Th ey are in her en t. Upon a re voca tion of th e
proclamation, and a cessation of th e sta te of th ings w hich
prompted these arbitrary measures, the Con st itu tion and laws
woke from their lethargy, and again became our shield and
safeguard.
341
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1455
342. Id. at 1266.
343. THE RECONSTRUCTION AMENDME NTS DEBATES 193 (Alfr ed Avin s ed., 196 7).
344. CONG. GLOBE, 39t h C ong., 1 st Sess. 1838 (1 866 ).
Thus, Senator Nye and Representative Thornton viewed the
Second Amendment right to arms as a personal right, similar to
the other rights in the first eight amendments.
3. Civil Rights Bill
Rep. Henry Raymond (R-N.Y.) served on the J oint
Committee on Reconstruction and as an editor of the New York
Times. He stated in support of the Civil Rights Bill: “Make the
colored man a citizen of the United States and he has every
right which you or I have as citizens of the United States under
the laws and Constitution of the United States . . . a right to
defend himself and his wife and children; a right to bear
arms . . . .”
342
Another New York Republican, Roswell Hart,
argued that the Constitution required states to maintain a
republican form of government, which meant, inter alia, a
governmentwhere ‘the right of the people t o keep and bear
arms shall not be infringed;’ . . . . Have these rebellious States
such a form of government? If they have not, it is the duty of
the United States to guaranty that they have it speedily.”
343
If
the Second Amendment only protected state governments
against the federal government, then Rep. Hart’s statement
that the Second Amendment must be obeyed by state
governments would make no sense.
Rep. Sidney Clarke of Kansas agreed with the New Yorkers:
[I] find in th e Con stitu tion of the U nit ed S ta tes an a rticle
which declares thatthe right of the people to keep and bear
arms sh all not be in frin ged .” For m yself, I shall insist that the
reconstructed rebels of Mississipp i respect the Constitu tion in
th eir local laws . . . .
344
4. Anti-KKK Act
The frequen tly-invoked feder al civil righ ts statutes, wh ich
allow criminal and civil prosecution of state officials who violate
federal civil r ig ht s, w ere cr ea t ed by t he “An t i-KKK Act .” T h e
Committee Repor t on the Act explained, “in many counties they
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1456 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
345. H.R. REP. NO. 41-3 7, a t 3 (1871).
346. Id. at 7.
347. CONG. GLOBE, 42d Con g., 1 st Sess . 337 (1871).
have preceded their outrages upon him [the freedman] by
disarming him, in viola tion of his right as a citizen tokeep and
bear arms, which the Constitution expressly says shall never
be infringed.”
345
Rep. Benjamin Butler (R-Mass.) elaborated:
Section eigh t is intended t o en force the well-known
constitutional provision guaranteeing the right of the citizen to
keep and bear arm s,” and provides that whoever shall take
away, by for ce or violen ce, or by threats and intimidation, the
arms and weapons which any person may h ave for his defense,
shall be deemed guilty of larceny of the same.
346
Tennessee Democrat Washington C. Whitthorne objected
that the lawsuit provision of the anti-KKK act (allowing
lawsuits for deprivation of constitutional rights) would allow a
New York police officer who disarmed a drunk to be sued,
because the right to bear arms is secured by the
Constitut ion.”
347
5. Fou rteenth Am endm ent
When deba te on the Fourteenth Amendm en t began, some
members of Congress argued that the Thirteenth Amendment
already gave Congress sufficient power to address Southern
laws which prevented the ex-slaves from enjoying the status of
free men. Supporting this position, Kansas Senator Samuel
Pomeroy asked:
And what are the safegu ar ds of liber ty under ou r for m of
Government? There are at least, under our Constitution, three
which are indispensable—
1. Every man should have a homestead, that is, the right
to acquire and hold one, and the right to be safe and protected
in th at cita del of his love. . . .
2. He should ha ve the right to bear arms for the defense of
him self and family and his homestead. And if th e ca bin door of
the freedman is broken open and the intruder enters for
purposes as vile as were known t o slavery, th en should a w ell-
loaded musket be in the hand of the occupant to send the
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1457
348. CONG. GLOBE, 39t h C ong., 1st Sess. 1182 (1 866 ).
349. Amar, The Bill of Rights as a Constit ut ion, supra note 1, at 1167 (quoting
CONG. GLOBE, 39th Cong., 1st Sess. 2766 (1866)). Senator Howard had “a wide
reading kn owled ge n ot on ly of law and his tor y, bu t a lso of liter atur e.” James O.
Knauss, Jacob Merritt Howard, in DICT. AM. BIO., supra note 90.
350. ERIC FONER, RECONSTRUCTION 258-59 (1988).
351. CONG. GLOBE, 42d Con g., 1 st Sess . app. at 8 4 (1871).
352. Id.
polluted w re tch to another world, wh ere his wr etchedn ess will
forever rem ain com plet e; a nd
3. H e sh ould h ave the ba llot . . . .
348
Congressmen expressed t heir intention to remedy the
deprivation of Second Amendment rights through corrective
statutes, and eventually through the Fourteenth Amendment.
For example:
Senator Howa rd . . . explicitly invokedthe right to keep and
bear arms” in his important speech cat alogu ing the “personal
rights” to be protected by the Fourteenth Amendment. Howard
and others may ha ve been influ en ced by th e ant ebellum
constitutional commentator William Rawle, who had argued in
his 1825 tr ea tis e t hat t he Second Amendm ent as written
limited both st at e a nd federa l govern men t . . . .
349
As Eric Foner observes,
[I]t is abundan tly clear that th e Repu blicans wish ed to give
constit ution al sa nction to sta te s’ obliga tion to respect such key
pr ovisions as freedom of speech, the right to bear arms, trial
by impartial jury . . . . The Freedmans Bureau had already
taken steps to protect these rights, and the Amendment was
deemed necessary, in part, pr ecisely because every one of them
was being systematically violated in the South in 1866.
350
After the Amendm en t had been ratified, its Congressional
sponsors explained its meaning in relation to other legislation.
For example, J onathan Bin gham (R-Ohio), discussing section 1
of the Fourteenth Amendment, stated “that the privileges and
immunities of citizens of the United States, . . . are chiefly
defined in the first eight amendments to the Const itution of th e
United Stat es.”
351
After listing the amendments, Bingham
explained:These eight articles I have shown never were
limitations upon the power of the States, until ma de so by the
fourteenth amendment.
352
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1458 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
353. Id. at 475.
354. CONG. GLOBE, 42d Con g., 2 d Sess. a pp. a t 26 (18 72).
355. CONG. REC., 43d Con g., 1st Se ss. app. at 2 41-4 2 (1874).
356. Id. at 302; see also Let ters from th e Federal Far m er XVIII, in 2 THE
COMPLETE ANTI-FEDE RALIST 341 (1981) (“A militia, wh en pr operly forme d, a re in fact
the people t hem selves . . . and include . . . a ll m en cap ab le of bea ri ng ar ms . . . .”);
George Ma son , Vir gin ia Ra tifyin g Con ven ti on of June 16, 1788, reprinted in ORIGIN,
supra note 37, at 430 (Who are the Militia? They consist now of the whole
people . . . .”).
357. The only known nin eteenth cent ur y inv ocation of the Second Amendment
as a meaningful state’s right occurred dur ing a floor speech by Delaware Democrat
Willard Saulsbur y, as he indicated that violation of the Second Amendment would
mean the disarmament of the ent ire population. Objecting to the proposed S.R. 32,
to disband most Southern stat es’ militias, Saulsbury said:
Rep. Henry Dawes (R-Mass.) agreed with Bingham that the
Fourteenth Amendment “privileges” incorporated the first eight
amendments against states, so a citizenhad secured to him
the right to keep and bear arms in his defense.
353
Later,
Senator Allen G. Thurman (D-Ohio) agreed that the “rights,
privileges, and immunities of a citizen of the United States”
included all the rights secured by the first eight amendments,
which he described in order, in cluding the r igh t to bear arms:
Here is another right of a citizen of the United States,
expressly declared to be his right—the right to bear arms; and
this right, says the Constitution, shall not be infringed.”
354
6. The Civil Rights Act of 1875
Georgia Democrat Thomas M. Norwood stated that U.S.
citizens living in territories en joyed “the privileges and
immunities of a citizen of the United States including “[t]he
right . . . of peacable [sic] a ssembly and of petition, and “to
keep and bear arm s.”
355
In debate on the same bill, Mississippi
Repu blican J ames Alcorn made it clear that the m ilitia
consisted of all cit izens, not just a select group: “The citizens of
the United States, the posse comitatus, or the m ilitia if you
please, and the colored man composes part of these.”
356
7. S um m ary of Con gressional policy
The Congressm en of this period were hardly interested in
strengthening the state militias (which had just been defeated
in the War of Rebellion, as they called it), or in reinforcing
states’ rights.
357
The Congressional concern about the constitu-
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1459
The proposition here . . . is an applica tion to Congress to do that which
Congress has no right to do under the second amendment of th e
Constitution. . . .
We hear a great dea l ab out th e oppre ssions of the n egr oes down Sou th ,
and a complaint here comes from somebody connected with the Freedmen’s
Bureau. . . . Yet, sir, no petitions are here to protect th e whit e people
against th e ou tr ages commi tt ed by t he ne gr o popul at ion; bu t i f a few letters
are written to member s her e th at oppres sion has been pr acticed a gainst
negroes, then the whole white population of a State [is] to be disarmed.
CONG. GLOBE, 39t h C ong., 1st Sess . 914-15 (1866).
358. Akhil Reed Amar suggests that the Fourteenth Amendment accomplished
a re-orientation of the Second Amendment. Whereas the Second Amendment had
originally dealt mainly with the right of people to own gun s to resist an oppressive
federal government through participation in the militia, the Second Amendment
extolled by the framers of the Fourteenth Amendment dealt with personal security,
and the means to r esist criminal at tack effectively. See generally Amar, Th e Bil l of
Rights and Fourteenth Amendment, supra note 1. Amar’s point is useful when taken
as an observation about two eras’ different views of the intended primar y pu rp ose of
the Second Amendment . We should keep in mind, however, that the Fourteenth
Amendment mer ely emphasized an existing thread of th e Second Amendm ent ; it did
not weave in anything new. The Fram ers of the Constitution and th e Second
Amendment saw comm unity defen se aga inst a crim inal governm ent as simply one end
of a continuum th at began with personal defense against a lone criminal; the theme
was self-defense, an d the question of how man y crim ina ls wer e involved (one, or a
standing army) wa s merely a detail. S ee Kates, Self-Pr otecti on, supra note 1, at 92-93.
Thus, the beginning of St. George Tucker’s exposition of the Second Amendment
reminded the rea der t hat “[t]he right of self defence is t he first law of nature.” See
1 BLACKSTONE, supra not e 14, ap p. a t 300; see supra text accompanying note 61.
359. See Kerm it L. Hall, Po li tical Po wer an d Con st it ution al Legit im ac y: T he
South Carolina Ku Klu x Klan Trials, 1871-1872, 33 EMORY L.J. 921 (198 4).
tional right to keep and bea r arms was plainly a concern about
the self-defense rights of individual citizens, especially
freedmen.
358
It would be ludicrous to attempt to explain the
record of the Reconstruction Congresses as anything but strong
support for a personal right to arms for self-defense. Thus, the
anti-individual authors simply avoid any mention of th e
subject. Jonathan Bingham and Jacob Howard, like St. George
Tucker, are carefully ignored.
B. Cruikshank
Under the authority of the new civil rights laws, federal
prosecutors brought many cases against white defendants who,
alone or in groups, had violated the civil rights of freedmen.
These defendants wer e frequently charged with violating the
Second Amendment rights of freedmen by taking their
firearms.
359
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1460 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
360. 92 U.S. 5 42 (1876 ).
361. See 16 Sta t. 1 40 § 6 (1870); see als o 18 U .S. C. §§ 2 41-2 42 (1 994 ).
That if two or more persons shall band or conspire togeth er, or go in
disguise upon the public highway, or upon the prem ise s of a not her . . . or
intimidate any citizen with intent to prevent or hinder his free exercise and
enjoyment of an y righ t or privile ge gra nt ed or s ecu red to him by the
Constitu tion or laws of the Un ited Sta tes . . . .
Id.
362. See GEORGE C. RABLE, BUT THERE WAS NO PEACE: THE ROLE OF VIOLENCE
IN THE POLITICS OF RECONSTRUCTION 125-29 (1984).
363. See United States v. Avery, 80 U.S. (13 Wall.) 2 51 (1871); United Sta tes v.
Crosby, 25 F. Cas. 701, 701-05 (D.S.C. 1871) (No. 14,893). The cases are discussed in
Hall, supra note 359, at 921.
Eventually, the federal prosecutions m ade their wa y to the
Supreme Court in United States v. Cruikshank.
360
Cruikshank
involved the afterm ath of the 1872 elections in Louisiana.
Following the elections, two separate gover nmen ts—on e
Unionist and one racist—declared themselves the winner and
the official government of the state. In the town of Colfax,
armed bla cks occupied the courthouse and the surrounding
district to asser t the legitimacy of their sides control of the
local governmen t. Atrocities had been committed on both sides;
a rioting band of white farmers attacked the courthouse,
burned it to the ground, and murdered blacks who tried to
escape the flames. Klansman William Cruikshank and other
leaders of the riot were tried in feder al district court for
violating federal civil rights laws. By t he terms of t he
Enforcement Acts,
361
the trial court found Cruikshank guilty of
conspiring to deprive the blacks of their Constitutional rights,
including the right to assemble peaceably and the right to bear
arms.
362
The Cr uiks hank case forced the United States Supreme
Court to squarely address the issue of whether the enumerated
provisions of the Bill of Rights were made enforceable against
the states by the Fourteenth Amendment and the
Congressional laws enacted pursuant to the Amen dment. The
issue had arisen a few yea rs before, in a feder al prosecution of
South Carolina Klansmen for conspiring to deprive blacks of
their arms and to destroy the black militias. There, the lower
federal courts had held that the Fourteenth Amendment did not
incorporate the Bill of Rights. The Supreme Court evaded
review on procedural grounds.
363
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1461
364. Cruik shank, 92 U .S. a t 551 (em phas is a dded). A su btext of th e opinion was
that the Reconstruction govern men t of Louisiana had encour aged bla cks to assem ble
armed, knowing tha t disturbances would result; hence, it was the sta te government’s
responsibility (not th e Supre me Cou rt s) to pr ote ct blacks from disarmament and
interfe re nce with th eir right to assemble.
365. Id. at 553 (quotin g Ne w York v. Miln, 3 6 U.S. (11 Pe t.) 125, 139 (1837)); cf.
Bliss v. Commonw ea lth, 12 K y. (2 Lit t.) 90, 92 (1822 ) (“The right [to arms in the
Kentucky Constitution] existed at the adoption of the constitution; it had then no
limits short of the moral power of the citizens to exercise it, and it in fact consisted
in noth ing else bu t in t he liber ty of th e cit ize ns to b ea r a rm s.”).
In Cruikshank, the Supreme Court held the Enforcement
Acts unconstitutional. The Fourteenth Amendment, the Cou rt
acknowledged, did give Congress the power to prevent
inter ference with rights granted by the Constitution. However,
the Court held that the right to assemble and the right to arms
were not rights granted or created by the Constitution. The
first part of the opinion explained:
The right of the people pea cea bly to assem ble for lawfu l
purposes existed long before th e a dop tion of th e Constitu tion of
the United States. In fact, it is, an d a lwa ys h as bee n, one of
the attributes of citizenship under a free government. It
derives its source,” to use th e la ngu age of Ch ief J ustice
Marshall, in Gi bbon s v. Ogden, 9 Whea t. 211, “from those laws
whose authority is ackn owledged by civilized m an th rou gh out
the world.” It is found whereve r civilization exis ts . It wa s n ot,
therefore, a right gra nted to th e people by the Constitu tion .
The government of the United States when esta blished foun d
it in existence, with the obligation on the part of the States to
afford it protection.
364
The Court further explained that the right to arms is a
fundamental human right:
The right . . . ofbearing arms for a lawful purpose” . . . is not a
right granted by the Constitution. Neither is it in any mann er
dependent upon that instrument for its existence. Th e se cond
amendment declares that it sh all n ot be infringed; bu t this . . .
means no more than that it shall not be infringed by
Congress . . . lea vin g the people to look for th eir pr otection
against any violation by th eir fellow-citizens of the righ ts it
recognizes, to what is called . . . the “powers which relate to
mer ely m unicipa l legisla tion . . . .”
365
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1462 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
366. Robert Palmer writes thatUnited States v. Cruikshank accomplished the
nu llifica tion of the fourteenth amendment that scholars traditionally attribute to
Slaughter-House.” Robert C. Pa lmer , Th e Param eters of Con stitu tion al R econstru ction :
Slaughter-House, Cruikshank, an d t he F ourteen th Am end m ent , 1984 U. ILL. L. REV.
739, 762. Palmer argues that Justice Waites opinion in Cruikshank misread
Slaughter-House, and wrongly assumed that state and federal privileges and
immunities were absolutely dist inct. See id.
Cruikshank was over ruled by implication by DeJonge v. Oregon , 299 U.S. 353
(1937), which held, d irectly contrary to Cruikshank, that the righ t to assem ble
peaceably was gu aranteed by the Fourteenth Amendment. Because Cruikshank had
applied identical reasoning to find that the First Amendment (assembly) and Second
Amendment (arms) were not protected by th e Fou rteenth Amen dment, Cruikshank
may not be good law today w ith re gar d to th e Fourteen th Amend ment s pr otection
of the right to bear arms.
One oth er Recon st ru ction Su prem e Cou rt case touch ed on th e right t o ar ms.
Cum mings v. Missouri was a n 1866 case growing out of th e 1865 Missou ri
Constitution, which imposed nu mer ous civil disabilities—pr ohibitions on engaging in
various professions, holding certain types of property, and h olding government
office—on persons wh o had supported th e Confederate caus e. Cummings v. Missour i,
71 U.S. 277 (1866). The State of Missouri defended the disabilities on the grounds
that deprivations of civil rights were not punishment. The Supreme Court disagreed.
Ju stice Stephen Field’s majority opinion observed that:
In Fr an ce, de priva tion or suspension of civil rights, or of some of them, a nd
among these is th e right of voting, of eligibility to office, of taking part in
family councils, of being gua rdian or t rustee, of bearing arms, and of
teaching or bein g em ployed in a sch ool or s eminary of learning, are
punishments prescribed by her code.
Id. at 321. The Court then explained that a deprivation of civil rights in the United
Cruikshank thus asserted that the Second Amendment
protected, but did not create, the individual’s right to bear
arms; the right instead derives from natural law. The Court’s
position that people must look to local governments “for their
protection against any violation by their fellow-citizens of the
rights” that the Second Amen dment recognizes is
comprehensible only under the individual right s view. If
individuals have a right to own a gun, then individuals can ask
local governments to protect them against “fellow-citizens” who
attempt to disarm them. In contrast, if the Second Amendment
right belongs to the state governments as protection against
federal interfer en ce, then mere “fellow-citizens” could never
infringe that right by disarming mere individuals.
The Cruikshank decision completed the work begun by The
Slaughter-House Cases, ruining the Fourteenth Amendment as
a check on most state abuses of the Bill of Rights until the
1920s.
366
Although no longer good law, the case clearly ap-
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1463
Stat es must also be considered a form of punishment:
The theory upon wh ich our inst itutions rest is, t hat all men have certain
inalienable rights—that among these a re life, liberty, and th e pu rsuit of
happiness; and that in the pursu it of happiness all avocations, all honors,
all positions, a re alike open t o eve ry one, and th at in pr otection of these
rights all are equ al before th e la w. An d depriva tion or su spen sion of th ese
rights for past conduct is pun ishm ent , and can in no otherwise be defined.
Id. at 321-22.
The Court st ru ck down the relevant provisions of the Missouri Constitution as a
bill of atta ind er, an ex post fact o law , an d a viola tion of due process. (The Missouri
deprivations did not prohibit the ownership or carrying of arms in any way; instead
the 186 5 Miss ouri Con st it ut ion affi rm ed th e r igh t of the people of Missouri “to bear
arms in defence of themselves and of the lawful authority of the State cannot be
questioned.” MO. CONST. art. I, § 8 (1865). Thus, th ere was no place for the Supreme
Court to consider the Second Amendm ent as a n objection t o the Missour i civil rights
depr ivations.) The Cou rt em phas ized th at th e ex-confed erat es cou ld be pu nis hed for
part icipa tion in th e r ebe llion according to law s which e xiste d a t t he ti me of th e
rebellion, but th at additional punishments could be not added after the fact. Id. at
327-29.
The Cummings principles rem ain valid law. F or example, in 1965, the Supreme
Court relied on Cum mings to ove rt ur n a law which b ar red ex-Commu nis ts from
becoming officers of labor unions. United States v. Brown, 381 U.S. 437, 447-48 (1965)
(holding that a dep rivation of civil right s is pu nish men t; th e Bill of Att ainder clause
is to b e br oad ly con st ru ed).
Cum mings raises inter estin g issues about modern gun control laws. The Supreme
Court in Cum mings labeled “bearing arms” a civil right, and insisted that a citizen
may be depr ived of civil r igh ts only as t he re su lt of a conviction for a crime when the
penalty for the crime was establish ed before , r at he r t ha n a fte r, th e com mi ssion of th e
crime. In the modern United States, in contrast, it is common for federal and state
laws to impose additional punishments for a crime, long after the defendant has pled
guilty and served his pun ishm ent. For exa mple, a pers on might have pled guilty t o
federal tax evasion in 1954 and ser ved a prison term or paid a fine. The punishment
for th e tax cr ime, a s of 1954, did n ot include loss of the right to keep and bear arms.
But in the Gu n Cont rol Act of 1968, the Congress banned the possession of firearms
by an yon e with a felon y con vict ion —eve n fe lony con vict ion s in cur re d lon g be fore 1968.
18 U.S.C. § 92 2(g)(1). Th e ba n likewise extends r etroa ctively t o per sons in var ious
cat egories un re late d t o crim e, s uch as bei ng dis honora bly dis cha rged from the
milita ry. Id. § 922(g)(6). Similarly, in 1994, Congress banned firearms possession by
anyone with a misdem eanor conviction for dome stic violence, no m at ter h ow long
befor e 1994 the conviction occur red. Id. § 922(g)(9). The courts have upheld these
retroactive prohibitions on the grounds th at they do not im pose an y retroactive
punishment; no on e will be s en t t o prison unless they possess a firearm aft er the
effective dat e of the law. See, e.g., United St ates v. Brady, 26 F.3d 282, 290-91 (2d
Cir. 1994). Thus, the modern courts adopt the position of the Missouri Attorney
General (that deprivation of civil rights is not punishment; only prison, executions,
and fines are punis hm en t), a nd reject th e positi on of the United States Supreme
Court. A per son dis hon ora bly d isch ar ged from th e sta nd ing arm y becau se of h is
object ions to the Vietnam War is deprived of the constitutional protections which were
accorded even to person s who had borne a rm s in rebellion against t he feder al army
in the n ineteent h century. It is not always true that modern cour ts pr otect civil
rights and enforce the Constitution with more zeal than did their nineteenth century
predecessors.
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1464 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
367. S ee, e.g., JEREMY BRECHER, STRIKE! (199 7); ROBERT W. BRUCE, 1877: YEAR
OF VIOLENCE (1989 ); PRISCILLA LONG, WHERE THE SUN NEVER SHINES: A HISTORY OF
AMERICAS B LOO DY COAL INDUSTRY (1989); Philip Taft & Philip Ross, Am erican L abor
Violence: Its Cau ses, Cha racter, an d O utcom e, in VIOLENCE IN AMERICA: HISTO RICAL
AND COMPARATIVE PERSPECTIVE S 281-395 (Hugh Davis Graham & Ted Robert Gur r
eds., 196 9). Another historian writes:
One of the major themes in American urban history since the 1850s has
been the struggle of municipal authorities and their business-class allies to
gain a monopoly on the use of violence. Th e pr oblem was n ot t ha t t he
electe d officials lacked a monopoly on the use of legally auth orized violence;
rather, th ey str uggled to convince turbulent portions of the populace that
all other violence was illegitimate.
Michael Feldberg, The Crowd in Philadelphia History: A Comparative Perspective, in
RIOT, ROUT , AND TUMULT: R EADINGS IN AMERICAN SOCIAL AND POLITICAL VIOLENCE 142
(Roger La ne & J ohn J . Tu rn er , J r., ed s., 197 8).
368. This title translates to “teaching and defense union.” CRAMER, supra note
1, at 130.
369. See PAUL AVRICH, THE HAYMARKET TRAGEDY 45-4 6 (19 84).
370. Presser v. Illin ois, 11 6 U.S. 252 , 265 (18 86).
371. The Court’s opinion was consistent wit h est ablish ed com mon law limits on
the right to arms which prohibited large, terrifying assemblies of a rmed m en. S ee 1
HAWKINS, supra note 96, at ch. 60.
proaches the Second Amendment from an “individual right”
perspective.
C. Presser
Labor and anti-labor violence, both in urban centers and in
rural coal mines, became quite frequent in the latter part of the
nineteenth century.
367
The major nineteenth century Supreme
Court interpretation of the Second Amendment involved a
group of German immigrants—Lehr und Wehr
Verein
368
marching in military exercise in pu blic. Th e ca se
grew out of an Illinois arms control measure enacted in
response to the labor uprisings of the late 1870s. State militias
and the federal army had brutally suppressed peaceful strikes.
When workers began forming self-defense organizations such as
Lehr und Wehr Verein, the state government outlawed private
militias.
369
A member of Lehr und Wehr Verein took the case to the
United States Supreme Court, and lost. First, the unanimous
Court stated that the Illinois laws “do not infringe t he r igh t of
the people to keep and bear arm s.”
370
Thus, the right to own
and carry gu ns does not include the right to carry guns in
public as part of a large group on military parade.
371
Further, as
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1465
372. Pres ser , 116 U.S. at 265.
373. Id. at 265-66.
374. Id. at 265.
375. S ee, e.g., Levinson, supra note 1, at 652-53.
376. See Planned Pa ren thood v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 848 (1992); Moore v. East
Cleveland, 431 U.S. 494, 502 (1977) (plura lity opin ion); Poe v. Ullman, 367 U.S. 497,
542-43 (196 1) (Har lan, J ., diss en ti ng).
Cruikshank had noted, the Second Amendment, under the
Slaughter-House rationale, “is a limitation only upon the power
of Congress and the National government, and not upon that of
the Stat es.”
372
In dictum, the Court stated that even though the Second
Amendment did not limit state gun control, there was still a
constitutional limit on state controls. The states could not
disarm the public so as to deprive the federal government of its
militia:
It is un dou btedly tr ue th at all citizens capa ble of bearing a rm s
constitute the reserved military force or re serve militia of th e
United States . . . and, in view of t his p rer oga tive of th e
general gover nm ent . . . th e St at es ca nn ot, even laying the
constitutional provision in question [the Second Amendment]
out of view, proh ibit t he peop le from keepin g and bearing
arm s, so as to deprive th e U nited St ate s of t heir righ tfu l
resource for maintaining the public security, and disable the
people from performing their duty to the general government.
But, as already stat ed, we th ink it clea r t hat th e section s
under con sid er ation do n ot h ave t his effect.
373
The militia thus includes “all citizens capable of bearing
arms.”
374
Anti-individualist authors who discuss Cruikshank and
Presser tend to emphasize the nonapplicability of the Second
Amendment to the states, while gliding over the cases clear
understanding of an individual right to arms. Most Standard
Model authors acknowledge Cruikshank and Presser as green
lights for state gun control. The Standard Modelers argue,
however, that Cruikshank and Presser should be repudiated in
light of modern Fourteenth Amendment doctrine,
375
or that the
two cases already have been repudiated by dicta in three
modern cases listing “the right to keep and bear arms” a s
among the “full scope of the liberty” protected against state
infringement by the Fourteenth Amendment.
376
Stephen
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1466 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
377. See Ha lbrook, Personal Security, supra note 1, at 343-44.
378. ALAN R. JONES, THE CONSTITUTIONAL CONSERVATISM OF THOMAS MCINTYRE
COOLEY 1 (19 87).
379. B. TWISS, LAWYERS AND THE CONSTITUTION : HOW LAISS EZ FAIRE CAME TO THE
SUPREME C OURT 34 (194 2), quoted in Stephen A. Siegal, Historism in Late Nineteenth-
Century Constitutional Thought, 1990 WIS. L. REV . 1431, 1485 n.302.
380. See ROSCOE POUND, THE FORMATIVE ERA OF AMERICAN LAW 30 n .2 (1 938).
381. See Paul D. Ca rr ington, Law as “The Common Thoughts of Men: The Law-
Teaching an d J ud gin g of T hom as M cIn tyre Cooley, 49 STAN. L. REV. 495 , 496 (1997).
382. See THOMAS COOLEY, A TREATISE ON THE LAW OF TAXATION, INCLUDING THE
LAW OF LOCAL ASSESSME NTS (187 6).
Halbrook, one of the most important Standard Model authors,
argues that the state gun control passages in Cruikshank and
Presser are mere dicta; the holding of Cruikshank was that the
Second Amendment could not be infringed by nongovernment
actors, and the holding of Presser was that the Second
Amendment was not infringed by a ban on armed parades.
377
VI. COMMENTARY FROM THE LATE 19TH CENTURY: COOLEY AND
OTHERS
Turning to the scholarly commentators of the late
nineteenth century, Part VI of this Article examines, among
other things, how Cruikshank and Presser were read by the
legal community of the period in which they were decided.
A. Thomas Cooley
By far the leading constitutional expositor of the post-Civil
War America, “the nation’s elder statesman on matters of
const itutional law,”
378
was Michiga n Su pr em e Court J ust ice
Thomas Cooley. He was considered “the greatest authority on
constitutional law in the world.”
379
Cooley served on the
Michigan Supreme Court from 1864 to 1885, was listed by
Roscoe Pound as one of the ten greatest judges in American
history,
380
and would have been appointed to the United States
Supreme Court, but for Republican bosses who feared his
independence.
381
Cooley also served as the first Dean of the Law Department
at the University of Michigan, which eventually became the
Michigan Law School. He taught Constitutional Law, among
other su bjects, and wrote im por tant treatises on taxation
382
and
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1467
383. See THO MAS COOLEY, A TREATISE ON THE LAW OF TORTS OR THE WRONGS
WHICH ARISE INDEPENDENT OF CONTRACT (1880). Th e tort s t reat ise “was long
considered the authoritative American treatment.” 4 DICTIONARY OF AME RICAN
BIOGRAPHY 393 (A. John son & D. Malone eds., 1930), quoted in Siegal, supra note
379, at 1486 n.309.
384. See Car rington, supra note 381, at 515-16.
385. See id. at 498.
386. P. PALUD AN, A COVENANT WITH DEATH: THE CONSTITUTION, LAW AND
EQUALITY IN THE CIVIL WAR ERA 252 (197 5), quoted in Siegal, supra note 379, at 1485
n.302.
387. Siegal, supra note 379, at 1487.
388. ROBERT G. MCCLOSK EY, THE AMERICAN SUPREME COURT 87 (1960 ).
389. Carrington, supra note 381, at 496-97.
390. Book Note, 27 ALB. L.J . 300 (1883).
391. BERNARD SCHWARTZ, THE LAW IN AMERICA 134 (197 4).
torts.
383
Professor Cooley was a superb lecturer, and (in great
contrast to Harvard’s Langdell) courteous to his students. In
his classes, he always paid heed to the social and cultural
context of the law.
384
President Cleveland appointed Cooley the first head of the
new Interstate Commerce Commission (ICC). Although Cooley
was a Republican, Democrat Cleveland selected him because
his reputation for impartiality would give the ICC the trust and
respect of persons of all points of view.
385
He is the only person
mentioned in this article to have a law school named after him.
In short, Thomas Cooley wa s “the most influen tial legal author
of the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries.”
386
1. A Treatise on Constitutional Limitations
“[T]he foundation of [Cooleys] fame and his central
contribu tion was his first major publication,”
387
the 1868
volume A Treatise on Constitutional Limitations, which went
through several editions over the following decades. It became
“a canonical text for jurists.”
388
Two decades later , it was still
the most sch olarly a nd certainly t he m ost adm ired Amer ican
law book.”
389
As a reviewer of a later edition explained, the book
wascited in every argument and opinion on the subjects which
it treats, and not only is t he book a uthoritative as a digest of
law, but its author’s opinions are regarded as almost
conclusive.”
390
A century later, Constitutional Limitations could
accurately be described as “the most influential lawbook ever
published.”
391
The fir st edition of Constitutional Lim itation s stated:
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1468 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
392. See supra note 152 and accompanying text.
393. See supra text accompan ying notes 246-54 (reviewing the Georgia case,
Nunn v. State, holding that the Second Amendment guarantees individual right to
open carr y, but not to concealed car ry).
394. 10 Ky. (3 A.K. Marsh .) 70 (1820) (holding a lso that free blacks have some
constitutional righ ts , as “pa rt ies to t he politi cal compa ct”).
395. THOMAS M. COOLEY, A TREATISE ON CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITATIONS WHICH
REST UPON THE LEGISLATIVE POWER OF THE STATES OF THE AMERICAN UNION 350
(Little, Br own 197 2) (18 68).
396. Id.
Right to bear Arms
Among the other defences to personal liberty should be
mentioned the right of the people to keep and bear arms. A
standing army is particularly obnoxious in any free
government, and the jea lousy of one has at times been
demonstrated so st ron gly in Engla nd a s a lm ost to lead to t he
belief th at a sta ndin g arm y recruited fr om among themselves
was more dr ea ded a s an instru men t of oppr ession than a
tyrannical king, or any foreign power. So impatient did the
English people become of the very army which liberated them
from the tyranny of James II., that they demanded its
reduction, even before the liberation could be felt to be
complete; and to this day, the British Parliament render a
standing ar my pr actically im possible by only passin g a mutiny
bill from session to session. Th e alternative to a standing army
isa well-regulated militia,” but this cannot exist unless the
people are trained to bearing ar ms. How far it is in the power
of the legislat ur e to regulate this righ t, we sh all not undertake
to say, as happily there has been little occasion to discuss that
subject by the courts.
1
1
In Bliss v. Commonwealth, 2 Lit. 90, the statute “to
prevent persons wearing concealed arm s” was held
unconstitutional, as infringing on the right of the people to
bea r a rm s in defen ce of th em selves an d of the State.
392
But see
Nunn v. State, 1 Kelly 243.
393
As bearin g upon th e r igh t of self-
defence, see Ely v. Thompson, 3 A.K. Marsh. 73,
394
where it
was held th at t he sta tu te su bjecting fr ee per son s of color to
corporal punishm ent for “liftin g th eir hands in opposition” to a
wh ite per son wa s held u ncon stitu tion al.
395
After denouncing standing armies, Cooley informed the
reader that “a well-regulated militia’ [requires that] the people
are trained in the use of arms.”
396
In the footnote, Cooley first
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1469
397. See id. Only one pre-Cooley treatise cited Ely. S ee DUER, supra note 165,
at 37 n .1. Coole y’s select ion of a ca se up holding just ifia ble self-defense by a bla ck
man may have been a reflection of Cooley’s own anti-racism. His Michigan Law
School was alwa ys open to people of all colors. See Car rin gton, supra note 381, at
516. On th e Mich igan S up reme Court , J us tice Cooley au th ore d an opinion voiding
racial segregat ion in the Det roit public schools. S ee People v. Board of Educ., 18
Mich . 399 (186 9).
398. See COOLEY, supra note 395, at 35.
399. Id. at 35-36.
mentioned a Kentucky case using the state const itution to
strike down a ban on concealed carry. Cooley next cited a
Georgia case using the Second Amendment to void a restriction
on carrying guns openly, while upholding a restriction on
carrying concealed guns. The third case shows plainly that to
Cooley, the “Right to bear Arms” (as h e entitled this section)
was about individual self-defense.
397
Elsewhere in the text, Cooley offered advice about the
Formation of State Constitutions.”
398
Among the elements
which Cooley thought appropriate to include in every state
constitution was
a decla ra tion of righ ts for th e pr otection of individ ua ls and
minorities. This declar at ion u sually contain s the following
cla ss es or pr ovision s:
1. Those declaratory of the general principles of repu blica n
government [including a ban on peacetime standing
ar m ies] . . . .
2. Those declaratory of the fundamental rights of the
citizen; . . . [inclu din g free speech, freedom of religion , freedom
from unreasonable searches and seizures, and] that every man
may bear arms for the defence of himself and of the State.
399
If Cooley could reflect “happily” on how little gun control had
been enacted in the United States, it is unsurprising that he
urged new states to adopt Bills of Rights which specifically
guarantee arms possession for personal defense.
2. The General Principles of Constitutional Law
In 1880, Cooley authored The General Principles of
Constitutional Law, an abridged version of the Constitutional
Limitations treatise. The book was “a popular college text and
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1470 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
400. Siegal, supra note 379, at 1486 n.307.
401. These last two se nt en ces were qu ote d (wit h p roper cita ti on) as an
explan at ion of the Second Amendment in C. ELLIS STEVENS, SOURCES OF THE
CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES, CONSIDERED IN RELATION TO COLON IAL AND
ENGLISH HISTORY 224 (New York, MacMillan 2d ed. 1894). The right to arms is a
right involving the latent power of resistance to tyrannical government, Stevens
explained. Id. at 223. “From prehistoric days the right to bear arms seems to ha ve
been the badge of a Teutonic freeman, and closely associated with his political
privileges. Su ch a rm ed fr eem en ma de u p the militar y host of t he t ribe.” Id. Stevens
traced the right to arms and the corresponding militia duty from Saxon times to the
middle ages, and finally to th e 1689 E nglish Bill of Rights . See id.
402. See T HOMAS M. COOLEY, THE GENER AL PRINCIPLES OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW
IN THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA 281 -82 (Bost on, Litt le, Br own 2d ed. 1891).
student’s guide.”
400
General Principles had a much longer
exposition of the righ t to arms:
Section IV. — THE RIGHT TO KEEP AND BEAR ARMS.
The Con stitu tion . — By the second amendment to the
Con stitu tion it is d eclar ed t ha t “a w ell-regulat ed m ilitia bein g
necessary to t he se cur ity of a free Stat e, th e right of th e people
to k eep a nd bea r a rm s shall not be in frin ged .”
The amendm ent, like most other provisions in the
Constitution, has a h istory. It wa s adopted with som e
modifica tion and enlargem ent from the E nglish Bill of Rights
of 1688, wh ere it stood a s a pr ote st against ar bitra ry act ion of
the overturned dynasty in disarming the people, and as a
pledge of the new rulers th at th is tyran nica l action shou ld
cease.
401
Th e r igh t d ecla red was mea nt t o be a stron g m ora l
check against the usurpation and arbitrary power of rulers,
and as a necessa ry and efficient m eans of regainin g rights
when temporarily overturned by usu rpation. [Cooley then
placed a foot note to St. George Tucker’s extravagant tribute to
the individual right to arms.
402
]
The Righ t is General. — It may be supposed from the
phraseology of this provision that the right to keep and bear
arms was only guara nteed to the militia; but th is would be an
interp re ta tion not warr anted by the intent. The militia, as has
been elsewhere explained, consists of those persons who,
under th e law, a re liable to the perform an ce of military du ty,
and are officered an d enrolled for service w hen called upon .
But the law m ay make provision for th e en rolm ent of all wh o
are fit to perfor m militar y duty, or of a sm all number only, or
it may wh olly omit to mak e any provision at all; and if the
right were limited to those enrolled, the purpose of this
guaranty might be defeate d a ltogether by t he a ction or neglect
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1471
403. Id. at 282-83. At the end of the section, Cooley cited Andrews v. State, 50
Tenn (3 Heisk.) 165 (1872), for the proposition th at the impr oper car rying of small
weapons not s uita ble for defense against tyran ny could be prohibited. COOLEY, supra
note 402, at 283 n .1; see also 1 WILLIAM BLACKSTONE, COMMENTARIES ON THE LAWS
OF E NGLA ND 143 (Thomas M. Cooley ed., Chicago, Callaghan 1884) (conta ining
Cooley’s notes on Blackstone’s exposition of the right to arms: “In the Un ited States
this right is preserved by express constitutional provisions. But it extends no further
than to keep and bear those arms wh ich are suited and proper for the general
defense of the community against invasion an d oppression.”). Lawrence Cress quotes
this pa ss age fr om Coole y to su pport C re ss’s positi on th at th e Secon d Am endment
guarant ees only a right of sta te gover nm ent s. S ee Cress, supra note 2, at 42. In light
of Cooleys statements in Constitutional Limitations (which Cress must have known
about since he cites Constitutional Limitations, ev en th ough he doe s n ot q uote it),
Cress’s attempt to use Cooley to support an anti-individu al Second Amendment is
tota lly implausible.
Also implausible is the claim of Robert J. Spit zer , aut hor of The Politics of Gun
Control, that the “classic analyses of the nineteenth century, like those of Joseph
Story and Thomas Cooley” support Spit zer’s theor y that no individual has a right to
own a gun. SPITZER, supra not e 2, a t 42-43. In th e en dnote for t he assertion, Spitzer
cites Story and Cooley, but does not quote any of their words. Instead, Spitzer writes
that “Cooley did not in clud e discussi on of the importa nt Presser case until the
subsequent (fourth ) edition of his book, published in 1931, when he buttressed the
standard interpr etation foun d in the wr itings of other cons titutional sch olars.” Id. at
56 n.60 (parenthetical in original). Actually, Judge Cooley had been dead for 33 years
when the fourt h edition was publishe d. See Andrew C. Mclauchlin, Thomas McIntyre
to act of the government it was meant to hold in check. The
meaning of the provision undoubtedly is, that the people, from
whom the m ilitia must be taken, shall have the right to keep
and bea r a rm s, a nd t hey n eed n o perm ission or regulation of
law for the purpose. But this enables the governm ent to ha ve a
we ll-r egulated militia; for to bear ar ms im plies som ethin g
more than th e m ere keeping; it im plies th e lea rn ing to h an dle
and use them in a way that makes those who keep them ready
for th eir efficient use; in ot he r words, it im plies the right to
meet for voluntary discipline in arms, observing in doing so
the laws of public order.
Standing Arm y. — A further purpose of this amendmen t
is, to preclude any necessit y or r easonable excu se for keepin g
up a standin g arm y. A sta ndin g a rm y is condemned by the
tr ad ition s and sen tim en ts of th e people, a s be ing as dan ger ous
to the liberties of the people as the general preparation of the
people for th e defence of their institutions with arms is
preservative of them .
What Arm s may be kept. — The arms intended by the
Con stitu tion are such as are suita ble for t he general defence of
the community against invasion or oppression, and the secret
carrying of those suit ed merely to deadly individual
encounters may be prohibited.
403
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1472 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
Cooley , in DICT. AM. BIO., supra note 90.
404. See THO MAS M. COOLEY, THE GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW
IN THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA 297 -99 (Bost on, Litt le, Br own 3d ed. 1898).
405. COOLEY, supra note 395, at 270; see generally William s, Civic Republicanism ,
supra note 8.
406. See Hen igan , Arms, Anarchy, supra note 2, at 122. Hen igan credits him self
with scor ing a poin t on Levinson , since th e fourt h e dit ion un der cuts Levinson’s point
that the Second Amendment may invalidate state antigun laws. See id. But Levin son
was not re lying on C ooley’s th ird edition in re gar d to st at e gu n la ws; Levin son
elsewhere cited and ack nowle dge d t he au th ority of Cruikshank and Pres ser. Levinson’s
point about state gun laws turned on his argument that twentieth-century analysis
about the Fourteenth Amendment has rendered Cruikshank and Presser obsolete. See
Levinson, supra note 1, at 652-53.
Cooley repeated the above language verbatim in the 1898
edition of General Principles.
404
Cooley’s discussion in “The Right is Genera l” is perhaps the
most concise explica tion of how the in dividual righ t to arms
supports the Second Amendment’s goal of “a well-regulated
militia.” Ther e is no ambiguity to Cooley’s view of the Second
Amendment as an individual right, and there is no questioning
Cooley’s position as, by far, the leading constitutional
commen tator of post-Civil War America.
Cooley also provided the succinct St andard Model reply to
the argument of David Williams that the right to bear arms is
contingent on the government maintaining the militia:if the
right were limited to those enrolled, the purpose of this
guaranty might be defeated altogether by the action or neglect
to act of the government it was meant to hold in check.
405
If
govern-ment neglect could destroy the Second Amendment,
then the Amendment would hardly be a check on government
abuse.
Heniga n addresses Cooley, bu t sidest eps t he Second
Amendment issue. He first notes that Levin son qu otes from
Cooley’s third edition. Henigan then points out that the fourth
edition (published years after Cooley’s dea th) contains a
citation to Presser, not contained in the third edition, which
stands for the principle that the Second Amendment limits only
the federal government, and not the states.
406
This is true
enough, but Henigan does not show any flaws in Cooley’s
interpretation of the Second Amendment, nor does he show that
Cooley’s view was r ejected by a ny contempor ary. Henigan fails
to acknowledge another statem ent by Cooley, which directly
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1473
407. Thomas M. Cooley, The Abnegation of S elf-Governm ent , PRINCETON REV.,
July-Dec. 1883 , at 209, 213-14; see also Levin son, supra note 1, at 649 n.64 (q uoting
Cooley’s us e of t hi s t ext in th e t hird edit ion of GEN ERAL PRINCIPLES OF
CONS TITU TION AL LAW). In the next paragraph, Cooley wrote that a person who refuses
to heed an unconstit utional law “need for th e pur pose no judicial decision, n o official
assistance; he simply obeys the constitution, which is the law made by t he sovereign,
and is t he refore par amount , instead of th e law a ttempted to be ma de by th e
subordinate, which m ust n ecessa rily be inferior, and if conflicting, inopera tive.”
Cooley, supra note 404, at 214. The concluding paragraph urged Americans to exceed
the minimal dut ies of good citizenship, which were “that they sh ould cast their ballots
for suitable pe rsons in election, or th at they sh ould p erform ju ry du ty, or bear arms
when sum moned to the defen ce of the State.” Id. at 226.
408. See Hen igan, Arms, Anarchy, supra note 2, at 119-20.
409. See Levinson, supra note 1, at 649 n.64.
addresses Henigan’s concern that a constitution cannot
contemplate the overthrow of the government created by the
constitution, should the government become tyrannical:
The right of the people to bear arms in their own defence,
and to form and drill military organ iza tion s in defen ce of t he
State, may not be very impor ta nt in th is cou ntry, but it is
sign ificant a s having been reserved by the peop le as a possible
and necessary resort for the protection of self-government
against usurpation, and against any attempt on the part of
those who may for the time be in possession of St at e aut hor ity
or resources to set aside t he const itu tion an d su bst itu te th eir
own rule for th at of the people. Should th e contingency ever
ar ise w hen it wou ld be necessa ry for th e people to make use of
the arms in their hands for the protection of constitutional
liberty, the proceeding, so far from being revolutionary, would
be in strict accord with popular right and duty.
407
In analyzing Cooley, Heniga n was a ttem pt ing to refu te Sanford
Levin son s The Embarrassing Second Amendment point by
point (wh ile accusing Levin son of select ive quotation).
408
It
seems likely, then, that Henigan was awar e of Cooley’s
statement—since Levinson had quoted the statement in full in
his own article.
409
Thomas Cooley wa s u nqu estionably an adh eren t to the
Standard Model, and believer in what Henigan derides as the
insurrectionary view of the Second Amendment. Of course,
Cooley, like ever y other comm entator of th e nineteenth century,
saw the use of arms to restore the Constitution and to remove a
government that was destroying the Constitution as a method
of upholding the law, not as “insurrection.” If, as Henigan’s
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1474 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
410. JOEL TIFFANY, A TREATISE ON GOVERNMENT AND CONSTITUTIONAL
LAW—BEING AN INQUIRY INTO THE SOURCE AND LIMITATIONS OF GOVERNMENTAL
AUTHORITY ACCORDING TO THE AMERICAN THEORY (186 7).
411. The good of the republic is the supreme law.
group claims, the Standard Model of the Second Amendment is
“a fraud, then was Justice Cooley a participant in that “fraud”?
Or a victim? Or is it perhaps inappropriate to describe as a
fraud” the view held by the lea ding commentator of the late
nineteenth centurya view which, we shall see below, was held
by every other scholar in the period who discussed the issue?
B. The Lesser Com m entators
Many other scholar s wrote constitutional trea tises in the
postwar years, alth ough none was as influential as Cooley’s. All
of these scholars, like a ll of the commentators before them,
treated the Second Amendment as an individual right.
1. Joel Tiffany
Antisla very attorney Joel Tiffany remained active after the
Civil War. His 1867 book A Treatise on Government and
Constitutional Law
410
stated:
The second amendmen t of the constitution provides that the
right of the people to keep and bear arm s shall not be
infringed, beca use a w ell-regu lated m ilitia is necessa ry to the
security of a free state. The militia ar e the citizen soldier s, a s
distinguished from those who are trained to arms as a
pr ofess ion, an d who cons tit ute th e elem en ts of a standing
army. To be an efficient m ilitiaman the right to keep and bear
arms is essen tia l. Th is p rovision had it s source in that jealousy
of power in the hands of the central government, so manifest
in the people, at the time the constitution was framed and
adopted. This right in the people to keep an d bear arms,
although secu red by th is pr ovision of the constitution, is held
in subjection to the public safety and welfare. Whenever for
any cause, the public safety shall require th e su bst itu tion of
martial for civil administration, then the maxim, salus
resp ublica suprema lex,
411
applies; and this constitutional right
may be temporarily suspended. But while civil authority bears
sway, this provision of th e con stitu tion is t he su pr em e la w on
that subject. Of the same character is the third amendment.
No soldier sh all, in time of peace, be quartered in any house,
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1475
412. TIFFANY, supra note 410, at 394-95.
413. See supra note 309 and accompanying text.
414. Well, almost no one. Garr y Wills contends that the Third Amendment has
no lega lly m ea ningful content . S ee Wills, supra note 5, at 72. But see Powe, supra
note 1, a t 1 361 (re sp ondin g t o Wills on th e Third Ame nd me nt ).
415. Tiffany’s broad th eory of ma rt ial law (allowing su spe nsion of t he Secon d or
Third Amendment during war), which was n o doubt influenced by Lincoln’s aggress ive
and arguably unconstitutional u se of mar tial law powers during the Civil War, might
reasonably be quest ione d. The Third Amendm ent s pecifically pr ovides for
circumstances of war, and the habeas corpus clause states that it ma y be suspended
during ma rt ial la w. T he pr ovis ion for su spen sion of habeas corpus during martial law
implies that other constitutional rights, for which there are no suspension provisions,
may not be suspen ded during m artia l law.
416. See Richard L. Aynes, On Misreading John Bingham and the Fourteenth
Amendment, 103 YALE L.J. 57, 83-84 n .158 (1993).
417. See Pa ul D. Ca rr ington, The Revolutionary Idea of University Legal
Ed uca tion , 31 WM. & MARY L. REV . 527 , 562 (19 90).
418. TIMOTHY FARRAR, MANUAL OF THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES OF
AMERICA (Boston , Litt le, Br own 186 7).
419. Aynes, supra note 416, at 85 (a lter at ion in origin al) (cit at ions om it te d).
without the consent of the owner, nor in time of war, but in the
manner prescribed by law.
412
Tiffany’s prewar antislavery writings had used the
individual right in the Second Amendment as an argument
against slavery.
413
After the war, he construed the Second
Amendment in pari materia with the Third Amendment, which
no one
414
disput es is an individual right.
415
2. Tim othy Farrar
Antislavery attorney Tim othy Farrar had been the law
partner of Daniel Webster,
416
and also part of a group of
trustees of Dartmouth college who modernized the
curriculum.
417
By the time he wrote his 1867 Manual of the
Constitution of the Un ited S tates,
418
he had r isen to the ben ch.
Farrar was a respected figur e, and his views were wid ely
known. An Ohio congressman, J udge William Lawrence, cited
Farrar’s 1867 treatise as authority to defend the
constitut iona lity of the 1866 Civil Righ ts Act. Historians have
praised Fa rr ar s abilities and not ed h is influence on national
leaders du rin g th e Civil War a nd Recon stru ction as well a s his
role help[ing] to define clearly public attitudes on the nature
an d purp ose of th e Constitu tion .”
419
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1476 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
420. See id. at 83.
421. FARRAR, supra note 418, at 145.
422. See id. at 512-13.
423. Id. at 513-14.
424. Id. at 514.
Taking an expansive view of constitutional rights, similar to
the one shared by Fourteenth Amendment sponsor Jonathan
Bingham,
420
Farrar wrote:
The Stat es a re recognized a s govern ments, an d, when t heir
own const itu tion s perm it, may do as they please; provided they
do not interfere with the Constitution and laws of the United
States, or with the civil or natural rights of the people
recognized thereby, and held in conform ity to them. The right
of every person to “life, liberty, and property,”to keep and
bear arms,” to thewrit of habeas corpus,” to “trial by ju ry,
and divers others, are recognized by, and held under, the
Constitution of the U nited States, an d cann ot be infringed by
individuals or St ate s, or even by th e governmen t its elf.
421
In the chapter on “State Disabilities,” Farrar first listed the
provisions on the main text of the Constitution forbidding acts
which infringe civil liberty (such as t he prohibition on Bills of
Attainder).
422
He then observed:
Many subjects are sim ilar ly restricted in th e constitutional
amendments of wh ich th e followin g a re exa m ples: Th e fr ee
exercise of religion; . . . the right of the people to assemble and
petit ion the government; the right of the people to keep and
bear arms; the right of the people to be secure in their persons,
houses, papers and effects . . . . [These] acknowledged
constitutional rights of the people must be protected by the
government, not only against their own wrongdoing, but
against any other agency in the land.
423
He argued that the federal government has no rightto put a
citizen to the rack” nor “to permit a village magistrate to do the
same thing, under the pretended authority of a State law. And
so of every other prohibition in the catalogue.”
424
Thus, Farrar (lik e Lysander Spooner but unlik e J onathan
Bingham) believed that the Bill of Rights, including the
enumerated right of a person to keep and bear arms, was
enforceable against the states even without the Fourteenth
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1477
425. See Aynes, supra note 416, at 84. Farr ar recognized Barron v. Baltimore,
but ar gued t ha t J ustice John sons opinion in Houston v. Moore had suggested that
the Fifth Amendme nt is applicable to th e st at es. See id.; Houston v. Moore, 18 U.S.
(5 Whea t.) 1, 33-34 (1820) (separ ate opinion of John son, J .).
426. William Rawle and St. George Tucker made a similar point : even wit hou t
the limitation created by the Second Amendment, the federal government had no
power to enact antigun laws. See also supra notes 62-66, 96 a nd accompanying text.
427. See FARRAR, supra note 418, at 285.
428. Id. at 286.
Amendment.
425
What is relevant for our purposes is not
whether this theory of the direct applica tion of the Bill of
Rights to the states was correct, but that the right to arms was
treated as one of the important individual rights guaranteed by
the Constitution.
In another chapter, Farrar argued that many constitutional
provisions forbid the government to perform acts which it has
no positive power to perform anyway.
426
Pointing to the
constitutional prohibition against the gr anting of titles of
nobility, Farrar noted that even wit hout the prohibition,
Congress had no power to confer honorable titles.
427
Likewise,
the First Amen dm en t pr ohibits Congressional establish men t of
religion and Congressional interference with free exercise of
religion, peaceable assembly, or the right to petition. But what
specific pow er men tion ed in an y par t of the Constitu tion ,
authorizes Congress to tou ch a ny one of these su bject s, for an y
purpose whatever? Why, then, restrict the power? So ofthe
right to keep an d bear arm s,” and divers other valuable
comm on-law rights. Obviou sly th ey a re all carefully guarded;
because under the general powers of the governm ent to
provide for t he com mon defence, the general welfar e, and the
blessings of liberty, and to do any thing necessary and proper
for th ose pu rp oses, n othing could be said to be beyond the
legitimate claims of an agent charged with these duties.
428
Farrar was wrong in guessing wh ich particular clauses of
the Constitution would be used to twist the limited powers
given to Congress into unlim ited power. It was per haps beyond
the contemplation of any mid-nineteenth century legal scholar
that the federal powers to tax and to regulate interstate
commer ce would be twisted into power to regulate on any
subject whatsoever. Regardless of the textual source of the
abuse of Congressional power, however, the First and Second
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1478 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
429. Charles Fairman, Recon str uction an d R eun ion, 1864-1888, in 6 HISTORY OF
THE SUPREME C OURT OF THE UNITED STATES 632 (Pa ul A. Fre un d ed., 197 1).
430. See Aynes, supra note 416, at 86 n .174.
431. S ee, e.g., GEORGE W. PASCH AL, PASCH ALS ANNOTATED DIGEST (1868).
432. Charles Fairm an, Reconstruction and Reunion, 1864-1888, at 3-4, in 7
HISTORY OF THE SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES (Pau l A. Freun d & Sta nely
Katz eds., 1987).
433. GEORGE W. P ASCH AL, THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES DEFINED AND
CAREFULLY ANNOTATED (Wash ingt on, D.C., W.H . & O.H. Mor rison 1868).
434. HAROLD M. H YMAN, A MORE PERFE CT UNION 517 (197 3).
435. Aynes, supra note 416, at 87.
436. See id.
437. SAMUEL FREEMAN MILLER, THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES 34
(1880).
Amendments were construed by F arrar as n early identical
clauses, pr otect ing im por tant person al righ ts fr om an
overweening central government.
3. George W. Paschal
Aleading Texas lawyer”
429
and st aunch Unionist , George
W. Paschal was arrested by t he Confederate governmen t of
Texas during the Civil Wa r. Although he had served on the
Arkansas Supreme Court,
430
he spent many of his postwar
years in Wash ington, D.C., where he help ed found t he
Georget own University La w School, wrote books on various
legal topics,
431
and was on e of the “lea ding practitioners” before
the Supreme Court.
432
He authored The Constitution of the
United States Defined and Carefully Annotated in 1868.
433
The
treatise wasan important addition to nationalist
constitutionalism.”
434
Represen ta tive Jonath an Bingham
endorsed Paschal’s treatise” on several occasions, even urging
the House of Representatives to purchase ten thousand
copies.
435
Representative (and future President) James A.
Garfield cited Pasch al on the floor of Congress, as did
Representative William Lawrence, Senator George Vickers, and
Senator Lyman Trumbell.
436
Supreme Court Justice Samuel
Freeman Miller called Paschal’s treatise avery valuable
work.”
437
After quoting the Second Amendment, Paschal wrote:
This clause h as reference to a free gover nm en t, and is
based on the idea, tha t the people cann ot be oppressed or
enslaved, who are not first disarmed.
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1479
438. P ASCH AL, supra note 433 , a t 256 (ci ta tions om itte d).
439. See Cockrum v. State, 24 Tex. 394 (1859). The first paragraph of Pascha l’s
exposit ion is taken from Cockrum .
440. See PASCH AL, supra note 433, at 133-36.
441. Id. at 133, 135.
442. JOEL PRENTISS BISHOP, COMMENTARIES ON THE LAW OF STATU TOR Y CRIMES
§ 792, at 497 (1873) [hereinafter BISHOP, STATU TOR Y CRIMES]; see also 1 JOEL
PRENTISS BISHOP, C OMMENTARIES ON THE CRIMINAL LAW § 124, at 73 (3d ed.
1865)[hereina fter BISHOP, CRIMINAL LAW]. Bishop was a leading founder of the late
nineteenth centu ry “classical” appr oach to law, although his contribution has been
unjustly overshadowed by Lan gdell and other Ha rvard professor s. S ee St ephe n A.
Siegel, Joel Bishop’s Orthodoxy, 13 LAW & HIST. REV. 215-16 (1 995 ).
The President, by order, disbanded the volunteer
companies of the District of Columbia, in November, 1867. His
right to do so has been denied.
438
Paschal cited Tucker’s Blackstone, Rawle’s Treatise, and the
Texas case allowing an enhanced penalty for use of a bowie
knife in a manslaughter.
439
Paschal’s discussion of the militia clauses in Article I was
more extensive, as he thoroughly covered what had grown to be
an extensive body of case law, governing topics such as when
the militia could be called out and the parameters of federal
control over the militia.
440
The Milit ia, he said, consist s “of the
able-bodied male inhabitants of a prescribed age . . . the body of
arms-bearing citizens, as contradistiguinshed from the regular
army.”
441
4. J oel Bishop
Joel Prentiss Bishop authored important treatises on
criminal law, and in those treatises addressed criminal law-
related constitutional issues in passing. The 1865 third edition
of Commentaries on the Criminal Law and the 1873 first
edition of Com m entaries on th e law of S tatu tory Crim es
contained identical discussions of the Second Amendment:
This pr ovision is found among the amendments; and, though
most of the amendments are restrictions on the General
Government alone, not on the States, this one seems to be of a
nature to bind both the State and National legislatures; and
doubtless it does.”
442
Bishop obviously adhered to the Standard Model individual
rights view; he viewed the Second Am endm en t as a restriction
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1480 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
443. BISHOP, STATU TOR Y CRIMES, supra note 442, § 792, at 497; see also 1 BISHOP,
CRIM INAL LAW , supra note 442, § 124, at 73-74.
444. Here Bishop cited Nunn v. State, 1 Ga. 243 (1847) (discussing an individual
Second Amendment right to carry unconcealed guns for personal defense), and
Stockdale v. State, 32 Ga . 225 (18 61) (d ecis ion of Con feder at e sta te court ) (reasoning
that a person does not violate law against concealed carry if part of the gun is
visible).
445. BISHOP, STATUTORY C RIMES , supra note 442, § 792, at 497-98 (citing State
v. Jumel, 13 L a. Ann . 399 (1858), wh ich explained that the Second Amendment
guarantees an individual righ t to carr y for per sonal defense, but not to concealed
carry).
on state governments, not a protection of state governments
against the federal government. Bishop continued:
As to its interpretation, if we look to this question in th e light
of juridical reason, without the aid of specific a uthority, we
shall be led to the conclu sion, th at th e pr ovision protect s only
the right tokeep” sucharms” as are used for purposes of war,
in distin ction from those which are employed in quarrels,
brawls, and fights betw een m add en ed indiv idu als; since such,
only, are properly known by the name ofarm s; and such,
only, are ad ap ted to pr om ote “the secur ity of a free Stat e.”
443
Bishop thus followed the dominant line of state
constitutional case law, exclu ding cer tain weapon s fr om the
scope of the right. Next, Bishop articulated the nineteenth
centurys most restrictive reading of the Second Amendment
righ t to bear arms in a scholarly treatise, although Bishop
acknowledged that there was contrary case law:
In like manner , the r ight to “bear arms refers m erely to the
military way of using them, not to their use in bravado and
affray. Still, the Georgia tribunal seems to have held, that a
statute prohibiting th e open wear ing of arm s upon th e person
violates this provision of the Constitution, though a statu te
against wearing of the arms concealed does not.
444
And, in
accor d with th e latt er br an ch of t his G eorgia doctrin e, the
Louisiana court has laid it down, that the statute against
carrying concealed weapons does not infringe the
constitutional right of th e people to ke ep an d bear a rm s; for
this statut e is a measure of police, prohibiting only a
particular mode of bearing arms, found dangerous to the
community.
445
Bishop’s contrast between bearing arms in the military
way” versus using them for “bravado and affray” (such as
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1481
446. To pu t t he me re pos se ssion of guns for home defen se w ith in t he scope of
bravado and affray” would require a very elastic reading of Bishops words.
447. JOEL PRENTISS BISHOP, COMMENTARIES ON THE LAW OF STATU TOR Y CRIMES
§ 792 , at 5 36 (3 d ed. 1901 ).
shooting them off at New Years, or using them in duels), does
not explicitly state Bishop’s views on carryin g gu ns for personal
defense. But Bishop’s acknowledgment of Nunn v. State (a case
guaranteeing a right to carry unconcealed firea rms for person al
protection) as a case contrary to Bishop’s own position suggests
that Bishop opposed gun carrying for personal defense.
446
Read in the most restrictive light possible, Bishop’s treatise
suggests: (1) t he Secon d Am endment guarantees a right of
individuals to own guns; (2) the right’s sole purpose was
insurrection against tyranny; (3) the arms which could be kept
included only arms suita ble for warfare; and (4) the right to
bear” arms included only the right to carry arms in public
during militia activity.
There is no nineteenth century commentator who appears
more dubious about the Second Amendment than Bishop. All of
the restrictions articulated by Bishop were, at the least, well-
grounded in at least one branch of nineteenth century case law.
It is important to recognize that, as restrictive as Bishop’s
approach is, it is clearly an individual rights one, comfortably
within the Standard Model.
The 1901 ed ition of Statu tory Crim es condensed t he Second
Amendment discussion, emphasizing that the Second
Amendment isdeclaratory of personal rights but (like most of
the rest of the Bill of Rights) does not bind the states:
It is among th e older a men dm en ts, most of which ar e held t o
be restrict ions on th e n at ional pow er , and not to bind the
states. This one is declaratory of personal righ ts , so also a re
som e of the others which are adjudged not to extend to the
states; and, contrary perhaps to some former views, it is now
settled in authority that this provision has no relevancy to
stat e legislat ion.
447
5. J ohn Norton Pom eroy
New York University law professor John Norton Pomeroy
wasone of the ten top law teachers in nineteenth century
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1482 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
448. THO MAS GARD EN BARNES, HASTINGS COLLEGE OF LAW: THE FIRST CENTURY
89 (1978).
449. See Bar bar a Allen Babcock, Clara Shortridge Foltz:First Woman”, 28 VAL.
U. L. REV . 1231, 126 6 (1988).
450. See Siegel, supra note 379, at 1453 n.89.
451. See JOHN NORTON POMEROY, A TREATISE ON EQU ITY J URISPRUDEN CE (5th ed.
194 1); J OHN NORTON POMEROY, POMEROYS EQUITABLE REMEDIES (191 9); Robert G.
Bone, Mapping the Boundaries of a Dispute: Conceptions of Ideal Lawsuit S tructure
from th e Field Code t o th e Fed eral Rules, 89 COLUM. L. REV. 1, 27 n.63 (1989) (“Many
considered his tr eatis e on equ ity jur ispru den ce . . . t he lea din g wor k on the subject
during th e la te ni ne te en th an d ear ly t went iet h ce nt ur ies .”).
452. See JOHN NORTON POMEROY, AN INTRODUCTION TO MUNICIPAL LAW (2d ed.
188 6); J OHN NORTON POMEROY, A TREATISE ON THE LAW OF WATER RIGHTS (189 3);
JOHN NORTON POMEROY, A TREATISE ON THE SPECIFIC PERFORMANCE OF CONTRACTS
(2d ed. 1874); J OHN NORTON POMEROY, CODE REMEDIES (4th ed. 1904); JOHN NORTON
P OMEROY, LECTURES ON INTE RNAT IONAL LAW IN TIME OF PEACE (1886); JOHN NORTON
P OMEROY, REMEDIES AND REMEDIAL RIGHTS BY THE CIVIL ACTION ACCORDING TO THE
REFORMED AMERIC AN PROCEDURE (3d ed. 1894). The Cod e Rem edies book “was the
seminal lat e n ine te enth centu ry work on th at subject .” Bone, supra note 451, at 27
n.63.
453. JOHN POMEROY, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE CONSTITUTIONAL LAW OF THE
UNITED STATES (187 0).
454. See JOHN POMEROY, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE CONSTITUTIONAL LAW OF THE
UNITED STATES (8th ed. 1885); Bone, supra note 451, at 27 n.63 (year of Pomeroy’s
death).
455. See Siegal, supra note 379, at 1469 n.201.
456. See Aynes, supra note 416, at 90.
America.”
448
Pomeroy moved to California, where he led the
founding of the Hastings College of Law
449
(the first three-year
law school in the American West),
450
and served as the reporter
for the California Supreme Court. His treatise on equity
endured for decades as the leading authority on the subject,
451
and his treatises on municipa l law, contracts, water law, and
other subjects were also important, continuing for many
editions.
452
But of all Pomeroy’s books, the one that was apparently
most in demand was An Introduction to the Constitutional Law
of the United States.
453
First published in 1870, the book went
through eight editions until Pomeroy’s death in 1885,
454
plus a
posthumous edition in 1888.
455
Pomeroy’s constitutional treatise
was known nationally and used as a textbook at West Point and
other colleges.
456
Prefatory to his discu ssion of the cla uses of t he Bill of
Rights following the First Amendment, Pomeroy stated,
[W]hatever construction is given to these clauses, will also
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1483
457. P OMEROY, supra note 454, at 152.
458. Id. at 152-53.
459. Id. at 152.
460. Id.; cf. 3 STORY, supra note 106, at 746-47.
apply to the same or similar provisions in the state
constitutions.”
457
He wrote:
1. The righ t of t he p eople t o ke ep and bea r a rm s. The object of
this clause is to secure a well-regulated m ilitia. It has always
been the policy of free governm ents to dispense, as far as
possible, with standing armies, and to rely for their defence,
both against foreign inva sion an d domestic t urb ulen ce, upon
the militia. Regu lar ar mies h ave alwa ys be en associat ed w ith
despotism. But a militia would be useless unless citizens were
allowed to exercise themselves in the use of warlike weapons.
To preserve this privilege, and to secure to the people the
ability to op pos e t hem selves in military force against
usurpations of the government, as well as against enemies
from withou t, tha t governm en t is forbidden by any law or
proceeding to invade or destroy the right to keep and bear
arm s. Bu t a ll su ch pr ovisions, a ll su ch guarantees, must be
construed with reference to their intent and design. This
constitutional inh ibition is certa inly not violat ed by laws
forbiddin g per sons to carry dangerous or concealed weapons,
or laws forbidding the accumulation of quantities of arms with
the design to use them in a riotous or seditious mann er. The
clause is analogous to t he on e secu ring freedom of speech and
of the pr ess. F re edom, not license, is secu red; the fair u se, not
the libelous abuse, is protected.
458
Pomeroy’s analysis succinctly distills the nineteenth century
Standard Model. St anding armies were still considered
dangerous. The militia was to be secured by guaranteeing a
right of individual cit izens “to exercise them selves in the use of
warlike weapons.”
459
Lik e J oseph St ory, Pomeroy saw nothing
inconsistent with the role of the people’s militia in suppressing
domestic turbulence”and the Second Amendment’s purposeto
secure to the people the ability to oppose them selves in military
force against usurpations of the government .”
460
Repu blican
order could be disturbed by domestic riots or domestic tyrants;
the Second Am endm ent wa s t o ensu re t he defeat of both.
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1484 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
461. “Th e people themselves, the entire mass of persons who compose the
political society, are the true nation, the final, permanent depository of all power. The
organized govern me nt , wh at ever b e it s for m a nd cha ra cter, is but the creature and
servant of the political u nit . . . .” JOHN POMEROY, AN INTRODUCTION TO
CONS TITU TION AL LAW OF THE UNITED STATES 28 (9th ed. 1888).
462. Id. at 220.
463. Id. at 718.
To Pomeroy, the essence of th e nation was t he people of t he
United States, not the government they had erected.
461
Therefore, the people’s sovereignty “still potentially exist[s] in
the nation, ready to be called forth whenever the people shall
see fit . . . to put their inherent, paramount force in motion.
462
Consisten t with Cruikshank, Pomeroy saw the limitations
expressed in the Bill of Rights not as grants by the government
of certain rights to the people, but instead as safeguards
created by the people
to protect the private righ ts wh ich exist an terior to all
governments . . . these lim ita tion s, I sa y, are th e very por tion s
of th e con stitu tion wh ich, m ore than all other s, should r eceive
a broad, extensive, liberal inte rpr et ation in favor of th e citizen
against the government[]. All experience shows that these
fundamental righ ts ar e the most exposed t o injurious
legislation ; and it often needs the whole moral force of t he
judicia ry to shield th em from invasion .
463
Pomeroy, consistent with explicit state constitutional
provisions and state case law from the post-war years, thought
there were excep tions to the right to arms: carrying concealed
weapons and seditious accumulation of weapons. These
exceptions, which only make sen se as exceptions t o an
individual right, not to a state government right, are the
except ions which prove the rule: the Second Amen dment, like
the First Amendment, is an individual right, but abuse of the
right is not constitutionally protected.
6. Oliver Wendell Holm es, J r., an d J am es Kent
Oliver Wendell Holmes, J r., was a distinguished legal
scholar and professor of law a t Harvard. Servin g on the
Massachusetts Supreme J udicial Cou rt, he became one of the
most important judges of the nineteenth century. His three
decades of service on the United States Supreme Court have
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1485
464. J AMES KENT, COMMENTARIES ON AMERICAN LAW (O.W. Holmes, J r. ed.,
Boston, Lit tle, B rown 12t h e d. 1873 ).
465. See 1 id. at *262-67. All citations to Kent use the star pagination system,
which is k eyed to th e fir st edition .
466. 2 id. at *15.
467. Id. Lawrence Cress uses the fact that “James Kent does not mention the
right to bear arms among the individual rights guaranteed in English tradition and
Ame ri can law to bolster the argument that the Second Amendment protects the
authority of stat e govern men ts, n ot th e righ t of individua ls. Cress, supra note 2, at
42 n.48. Cr ess cites Ke nt s discu ssion of person al r ights in t he secon d volu me of th e
Com m ent ari es on pages 1-13. See id. But in fact, there are many individual
constitutional rights wh ich Kent did n ot mention in these pages, such as t he right
to as sem ble, th e r ight t o pet ition, a nd protection from unreasonable searches and
seizures. Cress’s citat ion to Kent term inates in the middle of Kent’s discus sion of
personal rights, rather than at the end of a section. Cress thereby avoids directing
the reader’s attention to the last full page of the section, in which Kent discussed and
praised the individual right to self-defense.
made him the m ost wid ely rem embered legal scholar from the
nineteenth century. But in 1873, Holmes was only at the
beginning of his legal career when his first book was published,
an annotated edition of Chancellor James Kent’s Com m entaries
on American Law.
464
Chancellor Kent’s multi-volume commentaries, first
published in 1826, had displaced Tucker’s American Blackstone
as the leading American law book. Kent’s Com m entaries had
systematically discussed the main body of the Const itution,
including the Congressional militia powers.
465
The
Com m entaries did not include a syst ematic analysis of
amendments to the Const itution, and Kent sa id nothing abou t
the Second Amendment, although he did extol self-defense as
one of th e absolute r igh ts of Am erican citizens. Americans have
the natural right of self-defence, in all those cases in which the
law is eit her too slow or too feeble t o st ay the h and of
violence.”
466
Kent explained that homicide in self-defense is
justifiable, not merely excusable, an d that the right to self-
defense “cann ot be superseded by the law of society.”
467
Holmes added his own annotations to Kent’s Com m entaries,
and Holmes did a ddress t he r igh t to arms. In a discu ss ion of
the police power, Holmes observed:
As the Constitution of the United States, and the constitutions
of sever al of th e sta te s, in term s m ore or less comprehen sive,
declar e the right of the people to keep and bear arms, it h as
been a su bject of grave discussion, in some of the sta te courts,
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1486 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
468. 2 KENT, supra note 464, at *340 n.2.
469. Id.
470. See POUND, supra note 380, a t 30 n .2.
471. See Pa ts one v. Pe nn sylva nia, 232 U.S. 1 38 (1914 ).
472. See id. at 143. Holmes cited s eve ra l cases affirm ing st at e a ut hor ity to control
the ta kin g of gam e: Lawton v. Steele, 152 U.S. 133 (1894) (holding that a ban on the
use of nets for fishing on rivers is within police power; the preservation of game is
a core compone nt of th e police power ); S ilz v. H esterber g, 211 U.S. 31 (19 08) (holding
that the fourteenth amendment was n ot violat ed by a s ta te law bann ing hu nt ing of
certa in birds dur ing cer ta in seas ons); Purit y Extract Co. v. Lyn ch, 226 U.S. 192 (1912)
(quoting Silz fav orably).
In treating Patsone as a pure hunting cas e, Holmes willfully ignored the facts.
Despite the legislative declaration, the Patsone statute had been passed ver y shortly
after a violent incident involving immigrant mine workers. S ee G. Edward White,
Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., in THE SUPREME COURT JUSTICES: A BIOGR APH ICAL
DICTIONARY 225, 228 (Melvin I. Urofsky ed., 1994). The stat ute was, like earlier
English stat utes, condemned by Blackstone, Tucker, and Rawle, ost en sibly for th e
prese rvat ion of game, but a ctually for the protection of the existing govern men t. See
supra notes 36-39, 61, 96, 120 and accompanying text.
473. Patsone, 232 U.S. at 143.
wheth er a statute prohibiting per sons, wh en n ot on a journey,
or as tr av ellers , from wearing or carrying concealed weapons,
be constitu tion al. Th ere h as bee n a great differ en ce of opin ion
on th e qu estion .
468
Holmes then noted the states and ca ses wher e such restrictions
had been found unconstitutional (Kentucky, Tennessee, and
Mississippi) and the states where such restrictions had been
upheld (Indiana, Alabama, and Arkansas). Holmes concluded
with his own opinion that “[a]s the practice of carrying
concealed weapons has been often so atrociously abused, it
would be very desirable, on principles of public policy, that the
respective legislatures should have the competent power to
secure the public peace, and guard against personal violence by
such a precautionary provision.”
469
Holmes, like James Kent, Thomas Cooley, and Joseph
Story, earned a place on Roscoe Pound’s list of the ten greatest
Am er ican judges.
470
As a jurist, Holmes made two more
contribu tions to self-defense jurisprudence. In Patsone v.
Pennsylvania, he upheld a state statute which barred aliens
from possessing rifles and shotguns.
471
Holmes observed that
the purpose of the statute was to preserve the game for
consumption by Americans.
472
And he explained that the
statutedoes not extend to weapons such as pistols that may be
supposed to be needed occasionally for self-defence.”
473
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1487
474. 256 U.S. 3 35 (1921 ).
475. Id. at 342.
476. Id. at 343. This echoes Holmes’ observation in his classic 1881 book, The
Com m on Law, that “[t]he life of the law has not been logic: it has been experien ce.”
O.W. HOLMES, JR., THE COMMON LAW (188 1).
477. Br own, 256 U.S. at 343; cf. O.W. Holmes, J r., George Otis S hatt uck , in THE
OCCAS ION AL SPEECHES OF JUSTICE OLIVER WENDELL HOLMES 92, 95 (Mark DeWolfe
Howe ed., 1962) (“I t is one thing to utter a happy phr ase from a protected cloister;
another to think under fire—to think for action upon which great interests depend .”).
478. See Car rington, supra note 381, at 516.
479. BLACKSTONE, supra note 403.
480. Herbert E. Broom au thored a number of tr eat ises. See, e.g., HERBERT
BROOM, COMMENTARIES ON THE COMMON LAW: DESIGNED AS INTRODUCTORY TO ITS
But Holmes’ most important work in a self-defense case was
the 1921 decision Brown v. United States.
474
The Brown case
began at a feder al naval ya rd in Texas. A man named Hermis
had twice assaulted Brown with a knife, and warned that the
next time, either Herm is or Brown “would go off in a bla ck
box.”
475
One day, Hermis again attacked Brown with a knife;
Brown ran to get his coat, which contained a pistol. Hermis
pursued, and Brown shot him four times, killing him. At trial,
the judge instructed the jury that Brown had a duty to retreat,
if he could do so safely.
Justice Holmes, a legal historian, traced the duty to retreat
rule to an earlier period in English history, when the law did
not even recognize a legal r ight of self-defense. “The law has
grown ,” Holmes wr ote, “in the direct ion of rules consistent with
human nature.”
476
Thus, declared Holmes, there is no legal duty
to retrea t before using dea dly force. Nor should a victim’s
response to a criminal attack be second-guessed at leisure by a
judge:Detached reflection cannot be demanded in the presence
of an uplifted knife.”
477
7. Editions of Bla ckst one
By the la te ninet eenth cen tury, Am er ican law had come a
long way from the days when Tucker’s American Blackstone
was the only law book available. But Blackstone was still the
first treatise read by most would-be lawyers, and the only law
book read by some.
478
Thomas Cooley’s edition of Blackstone,
479
while benefit ting from its authors great pr estige, wa s n ot the
only updated edition available. English law professor Herbert
Broom
480
and Edward A. Hadley had their own edition, pub
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1488 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
STUDY (reprint ed. 1997 ); HERBERT BROOM, LEGAL MAXIMS (W. J. Byrne ed., 9th ed.
192 4); HERBERT BROOM, SELECTION OF LEGAL MAXIMS CLASSIFIED AND ILLUSTRATED
(reprint ed. 1971); HERBERT BROOM, THE PHILOSOPHY OF LAW: BEING NOTES OF
LECTURES DELIVERED DURING TWENTY-THREE YEARS (1852 TO 1875 IN THE INNER
TEMPLE H ALL) ADAPTED FOR STUDENTS (reprint ed. 1980); E. HILTON JACKSON &
HERBERT BROOM, LATIN FOR LAWYERS (1992) (1915). Broom taught at the Inns of
Court, in London. The Maxim s was “enormously successful” and enjoyed ten editions,
from 1845 to 1939. S ee Simp son, supra note 96, at 647.
481. WILLI AM BLACKSTONE, COMMENTARIES ON THE LAWS OF ENGLAND (Herbert
Broom & E dwar d A. H ad ley eds., 1875).
482. 1 id. at 121 n.64.
483. See supra text accompanying note 152.
484. See supra text accompanying notes 246-54.
485. See supra notes 394-95 and accompa nying text.
486. See Stephen Bot ein, William Draper Lewis, in DICT. AM. BIO., supra note 90;
Korematsu v. United Sta tes, 323 U.S. 214 (1944 ); see also WILLIAM D. LEWIS & A. Q.
KEASBEY, MISCELLANEOUS WRITINGS OF THE LATE HON. JOSEPH P. BRADLEY AND A
REVIEW OF HIS J UDICIAL RECORD (188 6).
487.
A defe nce of the right to carry concealed deadly weapons—delivered,
however, in a dissenting opinion in Andrews v. State, 3 Heisk. (Tenn.) 199
lished in 1875.
481
The Broom and H adley a nnotation about
Blackstone’s description of the English right to arms quoted the
Second Amendment, and pointed out:The constitutions of
several of the states contain a simila r clause. Th e righ t of
carrying arms for self-protection was discussed in Bliss v.
Commonwealth, 2 Lit. 90; Nunn v. State, 1 Kelly, 243; and Ely
v. Thompson, 3 A.K. Marsh. 73.”
482
The citations suggest a
rather st rong prodefen se inclin ation on the part of Broom and
Hadley, since they are the three strongest cases from the
nineteenth century involving an individual right to arms. Bliss
declared a law against concealed carry unconstitutional;
483
Nunn declared a law against open carrying unconstitutional,
while extolling the right to arms;
484
and Ely held that free
people of color had a right to use force t o defend themselves
against criminal attacks by whites.
485
William Draper Lewis was a leading Progressive, the Dean
of the University of Pennsylva nia La w School, t he fir st Dir ect or
of the American Law Institute, and one of the attorneys who
wrote the American Civil Liberties Union’s amicus brief in the
Korematsu case.
486
Lewiss 1897 edition of Blackstone, like
Broom and Hadleys Blackstone, explicated an individual
Second Amendment right, but cited Andrews v. State to show
that concealed carry restrictions were lawful.
487
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1489
(187 1). That the right of carrying arms as secured by t he U.S . cons tit ut ion,
and gener ally by State constit utions, does n ot includ e the habitual carrying
of concealed deadly weapons by private individuals.
1 WILLI AM BLACKSTONE, COMMENTARIES ON THE LAWS OF ENGLAND 144 n.91 (William
Draper Lewis ed., 1897 ).
488. Paul Fin kelm an, Legal E th ics a nd Fu git ive S laves: The A nt hon y B ur ns Cas e,
Judge Loring, and Abolitionist Attorneys, 17 CARDO ZO L. REV. 179 3, 1836 (1996).
489. See Allen D. Boyer, Book Review, Logic an d E xperience: The Origin of
Modern Am erican L egal E du cati on, 80 CORNELL L. REV. 362 (1995).
490. See Robert W. Gordon , The Case For (and Against) Harvard, 93 MICH. L.
REV. 1231, 1233 (1995) (recounting how one student stopped taking notes in Parsons’
class in October , writing in h is notebook “at th is point Parsons became Pathetic!”).
491. See E. Allan Farnsworth, Contracts S cholarship in the Age of the Anth ology,
85 MICH. L. REV. 1406, 1 408-09 (1 987 ).
492. THEOPHILUS PARSONS , THE PERSONAL AND PROP ER TY RIGH TS O F A CITIZEN OF
THE UNITED STATES: HOW TO EXERCISE AND HOW TO PRESERVE THEM (Hartford, S.S.
Scran ton 187 6).
8. Theophilus Parsons
Theophilius Parsons was the son of the renowned
Theophilus Parsons, Chief Justice of the Massachusetts
Supreme Judicial Court from 1806 to 1813. The younger
Parsons was a successful insurance and admiralty lawyer”
488
who later taught contracts at Harvard Law School.
489
Although
Parsons was a poor lecturer,
490
he wrote several treatises,
491
including a very popular one on contract law, which Samuel
Williston later took over as r evisor and editor.
In 1876, Parsons wrote, for a nonlegal audience, The
Personal and Property Rights of a Citizen of the Un ited
States.
492
Parsons’ treatment of the Second Amendment came as
part of his three paragraph chapter “Military Rights and
Duties.” After describing federal militia powers, he wrote:
“Militia undoubtedly means the body of arms-bea rin g citizens,
as distinguished from the regu lar army. In 1863 Congress
passed an act declaring that all citizens of the United States,
&c., “are hereby declar ed t o const itu te the national forces, a nd
shall be liable to perform military duty in the service of the
United States, when called out by the President for that
purpose.” In New York it has been held that this act was
unconstitut ional, and in Pennsylvania that it was
constitutional; both the decisions being by single judges.
The second article of th e a men dm en ts to t he constitu tion
provides that a well-regulated militia being necessary to the
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1490 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
493. Id . at 189.
494. See H. VON HOLST, THE CONSTITUTIONAL LAW OF THE UNITED STATES OF
AMERICA (Alfred Bishop Mas on tr an s., Ch ica go, Calla ghan 188 7).
495. Id. at 230.
496. H. VON HOLST, THE CONSTITUTIONAL AND POLITICAL HISTORY OF THE UNITED
S TATES (John J . Lalor trans., Chicago, Callaghan 1885) (first published in 1873, as
Verfassung un d D em okr atie der Verein igt en S taaten).
497. 5 id. at 306-07. Cont ra ry to the tit le chosen by th e Amer ican p ublis her , the
book is rea lly a constitutional hist ory from 1750, with an eye on even ts lea ding to the
slavery crisis. See Hermann Edward von Holst, in DICT. AM. BIO., supra note 90.
Holst had lived in America for many years, after being exiled for writing a pamphlet
opposing Prussian dictatorship. His eight volume opus was published after he was
security of a free State, the right of the people to keep and
bear arms shall not be infringed.
493
Since Parson s h as n othing to sa y about the Second
Amendment, other than to quote it, it is difficult to discern his
views, if any, on the subject. Thus, he is the only nineteenth
century commentator whose statement about the Second
Amendment may be sa id not to take a St anda rd Model position.
9. A foreigner’s vantage: von Holst
In 1886, Dr. Hermann Eduard von Holst, a member of the
German Privy Council and professor at the University of
Freiburg, authored a treatise on American law for a European
audience.
494
After quoting the Second Amendment, he noted
that
It has th erefore been ar gued th at th e con stitu tion al provision
refers only to arms necessary or suitable for the equipment of
militia; although it must not be inferred from this that the
right is restricted to those citizens who belong to the m ilitia.
As to whether or not the bearing of other arm s can be
forbidden, judicial decisions are far apart. It is, however,
gen erally admitted that the secret ca rrying of arms can be
prohibited.
495
Holst also authored an eight-volume treatise entitled,
Constitutional and Political History of the United S tates.
496
He
devoted several chapters to the pre-Civil War troubles in
Kansas and noted, “The gover nor and t he federal dragoons
were very active in the discovery and con fiscation of ar ms,
although the possession of bearing of arms is a right of every
American, guaranteed by the constitution.”
497
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1491
allowed to return to Germany; the books’ moral fervor and devotion to freedom made
them highly readable, in spite of their length. Holst s r epu ta tion w as of su ch
magnitude that he was chosen to hea d th e History Department at the new University
of Chicago in 1892. See id.
498. See 1 J. I. CLARK HARE, AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONAL LAW (Boston, Little,
Brown 188 9); see also Fr ancis Sam uel P hilbr ick, John Innes Clark Hare, in Dict . AM .
BIO., supra note 90.
499. 1 HARE, supra note 498, at 521-22 (citations om itted).
500. See id.
10. John Hare
Thus far, none of the la te ninet eenth century commen tators
had dealt with Cruikshank and Presser in much detail. In
contrast, Pennsylvania state district judge John Hares treatise
American Constitutional Law addressed the Second
Amendment exclusively through the lens of two recent Supreme
Court cases.
498
Hare wrote:
[T]h e Second Amendm ent, which declares, “A well-regulated
militia being necessary to the security of a free State, the right
of the people to keep and bear arms shall not be infringed,”
neither confers the right so guar an teed n or la ys a ny restra int
on the States. They may make any regu lation wh ich does n ot
impa ir the prerogative of the Gen eral Governm ent to ca ll fort h
all citizens cap ab le of bear ing arm s for th e public defen ce, or
disa ble the people from performing their duty in response to
such a behest.
So the right volunta rily to as socia te as a m ilitar y com pa ny
or organ ization , or to drill and parade with arms, is not an
attribute of national citizenship, but m ay be re gu late d by ea ch
State and forbidden to any company or body of men who are
not duly organized for that end, according to her laws or those
passed by Congress under the power to provide for organizing,
arming, an d d isciplining the m ilitia. Su ch a conclu sion is the
more necessary beca use th e a uth ority of the General
Government in this behalf is so limited a s to be practically a
dead letter; a nd if it were held to be exclusive of the States, an
important arm of national defence an d for th e su pp re ssion of
riot and insurrection would be impotent.
499
The above quotation contains t wo pinpoint cites to Presser.
500
Hare’s next paragraph observed that, similarly, the right to
practice law in a state court was not an attribute of national
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1492 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
501. See id. at 522.
502. Id.
503. Scott v. Sa nfor d, 60 U.S. (19 H ow.) 39 (1856); see Car l Russell Fish, George
Ticknor Curtis, in DICT. A M. BIO., supra note 90.
504. His broth er Ben jam in C ur tis ser ved on t he U.S . Su pr eme Cou rt .
505. See GEORGE TICKNOR CURTIS, A TREATISE ON THE LAW OF COPYRIGHT (1847);
GEORGE TICKNOR CURTIS, A TREATISE ON THE LAW OF PATENTS (1849 ); GEORGE
TICKNOR CURTIS, COMMENTARIES ON THE JURISDICTION, PRAC TICE, AND PECU LIAR
citizenship, but depended exclusively on the la ws of th e
relevant state.
501
He continued:
The prohibitor y articles of th e Con stitu tion wer e crit ically
considered by Chief-Justice Waite in The United States v.
Cruikshank in an opinion which gives a clear and consistent
view of their operation on the United States, the States, and
the people, and defines th e limits within which they may be
enforced by Congress. The case arose out of an indictment
containing numerous counts, drawn under a statute which was
held to be invalid because the clauses relied on for it s supp ort
sim ply disa ble the States or the General Gover nmen t, w ith out
imposin g any duty or restraint on individu als, a nd
consequ en tly do n ot a fford a grou nd for penal legislation .
502
Hare’s exposit ion of Presser and Cruikshank was fully
consistent with the Standard Model. Presser removed the
Second Amendment as a barrier to state gun control, except to
the extent that a state law might interfere with federal militia
powers. Cru ikshank stood for the principle that the Fourteenth
Amendment does not grant Congress power to legislate against
nongovernmental conduct. The language in the first paragraph
that the Second Amendment does not “confer[] the right so
guaranteed tracked Cruikshank’s language that the Second
Amendment (like the First Amendment right of assembly)
guaranteed a pre-existing human right, rather than conferring
a new right.
11. George Ticknor Curtis
George Ticknor Curtis achieved national fame as the losing
lawyer in the Dred Scott case.
503
Ther eafter , he enjoyed a long
career as a Washington lawyer, and fr equently practiced before
the Supreme Court.
504
George Curtis was also a pr odigious
author of important treatises on jurisprudence, equity,
admiralty, and intellectual property.
505
His modern importance,
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1493
JURISPRUDEN CE OF THE COURTS OF THE UNITED STATES (2 vol s. 1 854 & 1858); GEORGE
TICKNOR CURTIS, DIGEST OF CASES ADJUDICATED IN THE COURTS OF ADMIRALTY OF THE
UNITED STATES, AND IN THE HIGH COURT OF ADMIRALTY IN ENGLAND (1839); GEORGE
TICKNOR CURTIS, EQU ITY PRECEDE NTS (1850 ); GEORGE TICKNOR CURTIS , TREATISE ON
THE RIGHTS AND DUTIES OF MERCHANT SEAMEN (184 1).
506. Fish, supra note 503, at ¶ 3.
507. Regarding the Tenth Amendment , Curtis ar gued tha t the reser vat ion of
powerto the states or to the people meant thepeople” as citizens of particular
states, “not the people of the United States, regarded as a mass.” 2 GEORGE TICKNOR
CURTIS, CONS TITU TION AL HISTORY OF THE UNITED STATES: FROM THEIR DECLARATION
OF INDEPE NDENCE TO THE CLOSE OF THEIR CIVIL WAR 160 n .1 (J oseph Culb erts on
Clayton ed., 1896). Espousing the th eory th at th e Con stitution was created by the
people through the st ates—and not by the people of the nation d irectly—Curtis wrote:
The people of th e Unit ed S ta te s,’ rega rded a s a na tion , ha ve n o powers of
government—they have the power to make a revolut ion.” Id.
508. Id. at 155.
509. See id. at 159.
510. See id. at 491.
however, is based mainly on his two volume Constitutional
History of the Un ited States: From th e Declaration of
Independence to the Close of Their Civil War. “This work is the
classic treatment of the Constitution from the Federalist,
Websterian point of view.”
506
The creation of the Constitution, and the causes and
aftermath of the Civil War were Cur tiss primary focus, and his
atten tion to the Bill of Rights was cu rsor y. In his chapt er on the
Bill of Rights, Curtis focused on the Ninth and Tenth
Amendments as limitations of federal power, and offered no
ela boration about any of the first eight amendments.
507
But
Curtis did plainly treat the Second Amendment as an
individual righ t—one of therights of persons”like the rest of
the first eight. Explaining the controversy that led to the
creation of the Bill of Rights, Curtis noted that the human
rights provisions in the text of the Constitution (such as the
prohibition on ex post facto laws) “did not secure the rights of
persons as they were provided for in eight of the amendments,
and, above all, they did not reach the very im por tant
declarations contained in the ninth and tenth.”
508
Curtis added
that amendments in the Bill of Rights wer e r estrictions on ly on
the federal government, not the states.
509
Volume II contained
an annotated appen dix, in wh ich Su pr em e Court case citations
were placed next to the provision to which they pertained. The
only citation that Curtis gave for the Second Amendment was
to Presser v. Illinois.
510
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1494 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
511. S ee, e.g., JOHN C. ORDRONA UX, COMMENTARIES ON THE LUN ACY LAW OF NEW
YORK AND ON THE JUDICIAL ASPECTS OF INSANITY AT COMMON LAW AN D IN EQUITY
(1878); J OHN C. ORDRONAUX, JUDICIAL PROBLEMS RELATING TO THE DISPOSAL OF
INSANE CRIMINALS (188 1); J OHN C. ORDRONAUX, THE PLEA OF INSANITY AS AN ANSWE R
TO INDICTMENT (1880); S ee also G. Alder Blumer, John Ordronaux, in DICT. AM. BIO.,
supra note 90.
512. JOHN ORDRONAUX, CONSTITUTIONAL LEGISLATION IN THE UNITED STA TES: ITS
ORIGIN, AND APPLICATION TO THE RELATIVE POWERS OF CONGRESS, AND OF STATE
LEGISLATURES (189 1).
513. Ordronaux was using a Spanish spelling; the English spelling is “bandoliers,”
meaning “A shoulder-belt for holding a mm unition, (Hist.) with s ma ll ca ses each
containing a cha rge for a musket , (now) with small loops or pockets for carr ying
cart ridges.” 1 THE NEW SHORTER OXFORD ENGLISH DICTIONARY 177 (199 3).
514. By the rude bridge that arched the flood,
Their flag to April’s breeze unfurled,
Here once the embattled farmers stood,
And fired the shot heard round the world.
Ralph Waldo Emerson, “Concord Hymn ” (recit ed a t t he comp let ion of t he Concord
Monument, J uly 4, 183 7).
12. John C. Ordronaux
The 1890s saw a significant accelerat ion in the publication
of legal treatises. Columbia law professor John Ordronaux, who
also held a medical degree, wr ote extensively on issu es of
criminal law and mental health.
511
He also wrote Constitutional
Legislation in the United States in 1891.
512
Ordronaux stated:
The right to bear arms ha s alwa ys been the distinctive
privilege of freemen. Aside from any necessity of self-
pr otection to the per son, it repr esent s among all nations power
coupled with the exercise of a certain jurisdiction. From tim e
immemorial th e sw ord ha s been th e scep tr e of military
sovereignty. From this arose the profession of arm s, as a
distinctive calling in every age. Exposed as our early colonists
were to the atta cks of sa va ges , th e possession of ar ms beca me
an indispensable adjunct to the agricultural implements
employed in th e cultivat ion of th e soil. Men went armed into
the fields, and went a rmed to church. There was a lways public
dan ger. Th is was recognized by t he la ws of th e P lym outh
Colony, which requ ired tha t “each person for himself have
piece, powder, and shot—viz., a sufficient musket or other
ser viceable piece for wa r, with bandeleroes,
513
swords, and
other appurtenances for himself, and each man-servant he
kept able to bear arms.” And another ordinance required that
men should go armed to church. Whence it followed that the
embattled farmers”
514
of the Revolution naturally enough
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1495
515. ORDRONAUX, supra note 512, at 241-42 (footnotes omitted). For the last
sentence, Ordonona ux cited a lett er by John Adam s. John Adam s, Letter to Abbé
Mably, in 5 WORKS OF JOHN ADAMS, SECOND PRESIDENT OF THE UNITED STATES: WITH
A LIFE OF THE AUTHOR 495 (Charles Francis Adams ed., 1850-56), also cited in
ORDRONAUX, supra note 512, at 242 n.2.
516. ORDRONAUX, sup ra note 512, at 242. Besides Cruikshank, Ordronaux cited
State v. Hewson [sicNewsom”], 27 N.C. 350, 5 Ired. 35 (1 844 ) (upholding a law
against possession of weapons by free people of color, since they are not parties to
the constitutional compact); and Fife v. State, 31 Ark. 455 (1876) for th e natural right
proposition. See id. at 242 n.3.
517. Id. at 242.
518. Id. at 242-43 (e mp ha sis in origin al ).
beca m e th e m inute men of Con cord an d Lexin gton, and the
founder s of our na tional system of militia.
515
Next, Ordronaux cited Cruikshank for the “arms as a
natural right” view:
Therefore, it was not n ecessary that the right to bear arms
should be granted in the Constitution, for it had always
existed. It is n ot in consequ en ce depen dent u pon th at
instrument, and is only mention ed th erein as a r estr iction
upon the power of the national government against any
attempt to infringe it. In other words, it is a right secured and
not created.
516
Wit hout citing Presser, Ordronaux stated that “this prohibition
is not upon the States, whose citizens are left free in respect to
the extent of their enjoyment or limitat ion of the right.”
517
Becausearms” were meant “in its milita ry sense alone,”
states could regulate the carrying of arms. “Thus, the carrying
of concealed weapon s m ay be absolutely pr ohibited wit hout the
infringement of any constitutional right, while a statute
forbidding the bearing of arms openly would be such an
infringement.”
518
Further , states could require permits for
armed assemblies in public, or for the carrying of concealed
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1496 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
519. See id. at 243 (citing Presser v. Illinois, 116 U.S. 252 (1886) (holding that
the Secon d Amen dmen t is not a limit on state governm ent); Nunn v. State, 1 Ga. 243
(1847) (holding that the Second Ame nd me nt gu ar an te es an individu al right t o car ry
arms for p er son al defens e, but not to ca rr y concealed ); St at e v. J um el, 13 La. Ann .
399 (1858) (same holding as Nunn); Stat e v. Smith, 11 La. Ann. 633, 66 Am. Dec. 208
(1856) (same holding as Nunn); State v. Chandler, 5 La. Ann. 489 (1850) (same
holding as Nunn); Andrews v. State, 50 Tenn. (3 Heisk.) 165 (1872) (esta blishing an
individual Secon d Amendm en t r ight t o carry unconcealed arms for personal defense;
the Ame nd me nt en compa sses al l arm s u sa ble in “civilized wa rfa re ”)).
520. See ORDRONAUX, supra note 512, at 243.
521. See JOHN R. GALVIN, THE MINUTE MEN: THE FIRST FIGHT: MYTHS AND
REALITIES OF THE AMERICAN REVOLUTION (1989) (publish ed in con junction with the
Institute of La nd Warfa re Associa tion of th e U .S. Arm y); ROBERT A. GROSS, THE
MINUTEM EN AND THEIR WORLD 59 (1 976 ).
522. See Ph ysi cian s in Pu blic Service to A m erica, POLIT ICAL STETHOSCOPE,
Summ er 1996 (visited Feb. 6, 1998) <http://www.ama-assn.org/ad-com/roots/
pol_edu/stetho.htm>.
weapons by even a single person .
519
Ordronaux concluded with
a paragraph summarizing state and federal militia powers.
520
Modern scholars might quibble with some of Ordronaux’s
historical details. We now know, for example, that the
Minutemen were not the same as the militia; the Minutemen
were a smaller group, who received extra training.
521
The issue
for this article, though, is not whether Ordronaux and his
fellow scholars were right in every detail, but what the legal
scholars thought about the Second Amendment. Ordronaux,
with a high degree of enthusiasm , join s t he u nanimous opinion
of other nineteenth century scholars in viewing the Second
Amendment as an individual righ t. Like t he Reconst ruction
Congresses, but unlik e Bishop, Or dr onaux exulted the Secon d
Amen dment not just for resistance to tyranny, but for self-
defense.
13. Sam uel Freeman Miller and J.C. Bancroft Davis
After practicing medicine in Kentucky for twelve years,
Samuel Freeman Miller became an attorney, moved to Iowa,
helped found the nascent Republican party in that state, and
became frien ds wit h another attorney interested in Repu blican
politics—Abraham Lincoln.
522
Appointed to the Supreme Court
by President Lincoln in 1862, Justice Miller served until his
death in 1890. Throughout his tenure, he was a strong
opponent of allowing use of the Fourteenth Amen dment to
protect human rights. He lectured on the Constitution at the
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1497
523. See SAMUEL FREEMAN MILLER, LECTURES ON THE CONSTITUTION OF THE
UNITED STATES, at v (Fre d B. Rot hm an & Co. 198 0) (18 93).
524. See id.
525. Id. at 521.
526. The editor, John Chandler Bancroft Davis, had served as U.S. Minister to
Germany from 1874-77, a s a ctin g Secreta ry of State in the Grant administration, as
a Judge on th e Cour t of Claim s, an d as the report er for t he U .S. Supre me Court. See
Claude Moore Fues s, John Chandler Bancroft Davis, in DICT. AM. BIO., supra note
90; The Political Graveyard (visited Feb. 6, 1998) <http://www.pot ifos.com /tpg/bio/
davis.ht ml>; see generally JOHN CHANDLER BANCROFT DAVIS , MR. FISH AND THE
ALABAMA CLAIMS (189 3).
527. MILLER, supra note 523, at 661-62.
528. Id. at 662.
University of Michigan Alumni Day, at a Philadelphia
celebr ation commemorating the Constitution, and ten times at
National University Law School in Washington, in the years
1887-1890.
523
After his death, the lectures were collected and
published as a book in 1893.
524
Regar ding Cruikshank, he cit ed the case for the proposition
that the Seventh Amendment is “a restriction upon the power
of Congress, but did n ot lim it the power of the State
governments in respect to their own citizens.”
525
He did not
mention Presser in his lectures.
Miller’s editor, J.C. Bancroft Davis, wrote an appendix to
Lectures on th e Constitution of the Un ited States, to discuss
constitutional provisions which had not been addressed in the
Miller lectures.
526
The editor cited Cruikshank for the
proposition that the Fourteenth Amendment
sim ply fur nishes an a dditional guaranty against any
encroachment by the States upon the fundamental rights
which belong to every citizen as a m ember of society. . . . The
only obligation resting upon the United States is to see that
the States do not deny the right. This the amendm ent
guarantees, but no more.
527
On the same page, he cited Presser for the statement that the
Fourteenth Amendment Privileges and Immunities Clause
“does not prevent a Stat e from passing such laws to regulate
the privileges a nd immunities of its own citizens a s do not
abridge their privileges and immunities as citizens of the
United Stat es.”
528
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1498 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
529. Id. at 625.
530. Id. at 645 (cit ing P re sser v. Illin ois, 116 U.S. 252 (188 6)).
531. See id. at 708 & n.1.
532. Presser v. Illin ois, 11 6 U.S. 252 (188 6).
533. 123 U.S. 1 31 (1887 ).
534. 134 U.S. 3 1 (1890).
535. See infra text accompanying note 587.
In a discu ssion of th e m ilit ia clauses in Art icle I of the
Const itution, the editor cited Presser for the premise that the
power retained by states over the militia
is so complete that a State may, unless restrained by its own
constit ution , enact laws to prevent any body of men whatever,
other than the regularly organized volunteer militia of the
State, and the troops of the United States, from associat ing
them selves together as a m ilitar y com pa ny or organ ization , or
to drill or parade with arms in any place within the State,
without the consent of the governor of the State.
529
The description of the first three amendments to the Bill of
Rights was terse, consisting of only a paragraph for each
amendment. The Second Amendment was explained:
This pr ovision is a limitation only on the power of Congress,
and not upon the power of the States; and, unless restrained
by their own constitutions, State legislatures may enact
statutes to control and regulate all organizations, drilling a nd
parading of military bodies and associations, except those
which are authorized by the militia laws of the United
States.
530
The book concluded with another appendix written by
Gher ardi Da vis, wh ich consist ed of the t ext of the Constitution,
with string citation footnotes provided for each constitutional
provision. For the Second Amendment,
531
the editor cited
Presser,
532
Spies v. Illinois,
5 33
and Eilenbecker v. Plym outh
County.
534
S pies was the prosecution growing out of the Haymarket
Riot , and is discussed below.
535
The on ly t hing the court said
about the Second Amendment was: “[t]hat the first ten Articles
of Amendment were not intended to limit the powers of the
state governments in respect to their own people, but to operate
on the National Government alone, was decided more than a
half century ago, and t hat decision has been steadily adhered to
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1499
536. S pies , 123 U.S. at 166.
537. See id.
538. Eilenbecker, 134 U.S. at 34.
539. For example, he took over Pomer oy’s wat er la w treat ise after Pomeroy’s
death. See J OHN N ORTON POMEROY, A TREATISE ON THE LAW OF WATER RIGHTS: BEING
A REVISED AND ENLARGED EDITI ON OF “P OMEROY ON RIPARIAN RIGHTS,” WITH SEVE RAL
ADDIT ION AL CHAPTERS BY HEN RY CAMPBELL BLACK (189 3); see also HENRY CAMPBELL
BLACK, A TREATISE ON THE LAW OF INCOME TAXATION UNDER FEDERAL AND STATE
LAWS (191 3); HEN RY CAMPBELL BLACK, A TREATISE ON THE LAW OF JUDGEME NTS (2d
ed. 190 2); HEN RY CAMPBELL BLACK, A TREATISE ON THE RESCISSION OF CONTRACTS AND
CANCELLATION OF WRITTEN INSTRUMENTS (2d ed. 1929); HEN RY CAMPBELL BLACK,
HANDBOOK ON THE LAW OF JUDICIAL P RECEDENTS OR THE SCIENCE OF CASE LAW (191 2);
HENRY CAMPBELL BLACK , THE RELATION OF THE EXECUTIVE POWER TO LEGISLATION
(1919). Starting in 1917, Campbell also edited The Cons tit ut ion al R eview , a law
review dealing with constitutional issues.
540. HENRY CAMPBELL BLACK, HANDBOOK OF AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONAL LAW
(1895). There was a second edition in 1897, and a third print ing in 1910.
541. William D. Bader, S om e Thou ghts on B lack stone, Preced ent, and
Originalism, 19 VT. L. REV. 5, 13 (1994).
since.”
536
The Court also cited Presser, Cruikshank, and other
cases for the proposition.
537
Similarly, Eilenbecker held that the
Fourteenth Amendment does not apply the Fifth, Sixth, and
Eighth Amendments against the states. The cases only
reference to the Second Amendment is the following statement:
the first eight articles of the amen dm en ts t o the Const itution
have reference to powers exercised by the government of the
United States and not to those of the States.”
538
Again, the
Court cited Cruikshank, Presser , and other cases.
14. Henry Campbell Black
Henry Cam pbell Black is known toda y by almost every
Amer ican law student and lawyer as the author of Black’s Law
Dictionary. However, he also authored treatises on a variet y of
other subjects,
539
including the Handbook of American
Constitutional Law.
540
In this “celebrated summ ar y of
constitutional law,
541
he wrote:
RIGHT TO BEAR ARMS
203. The secon d am endm ent to th e federal con stitu tion , as well
as the constitutions of many of the states, guaranty to the
people the right to bear arms.
This is a nat ura l righ t, not created or granted by the
constitutions. The second amendment means no more than
that it shall not be denied or in frin ged by con gress or th e other
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1500 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
542. BLACK , supra note 540, at 462-63.
543. See id. at 463 n.35.
544. Id. at 463.
545. See Com monw ea lth v . Mu rp hy, 44 N.E. 138 (Ma ss. 18 96).
546. BLACK, supra note 540, at 463.
547. See id. at 463 n.37 (citing English v. State, 35 Tex. 473 (1872); Fife v. State,
31 Ark . 45 5 (1876); S ta te v. Work ma n, 14 S .E. 9 (W. Va. 1891)).
548. See id. at 463 (cit ing H aile v. St at e, 3 8 Ar k. 564 (188 2) (u pholding a law
allowing th e ca rr yin g of weap ons in public only whe n ca rr ied ope nly in th e h an d);
State v. Wilforth, 74 Mo. 528 (1882) (holding that a concealed weapons law was not
unconstitutional because it still allowed open car rying for personal defense); Sta te v.
Speller, 86 N .C. 69 7 (1882) (up hold ing a con cealed wea pons law based on express
authority to restr ict concealed carry in st ate constit ution; noting that the law does
not prevent a person from carrying weapons openly for personal pr otection); Wrigh t
v. Commonwealth, 77 Pa. 470 (1875) (holding that the state constitutional right to
arms was not infringed by imposition of court costs on a defendan t who carried a
concealed weapon wit h m aliciou s in te nt )).
departments of the national government. The amendment is
no restriction upon the power of the several states.
542
As authority, Black cited Cruikshank.
543
He continued: “Hence,
unless restrained by their own constitutions, the state
legislatures may enact laws to control and regulate all military
organizations, and the drilling and parading of military bodies
and associations, except those which are authorized by the
militia laws or the laws of the United States.
544
Black cited
Presser and a Massachusetts case.
545
As to the type of arms protected, the arms
are those of a soldier. They do not include dirks, bowie knives,
and such other weapons as are used in brawls, fights, an d
riots. The citizen ha s at all times th e right to keep arm s of
modern warfare, if with out d anger to ot her s, . . . but n ot s uch
weapons as are only intended to be the instruments of private
feuds or vengeance.
546
He cited som e of the st anda rd state ca ses for this pr oposition.
547
Lastly, he asserted that pr ohibitions on carrying concealed
weapons are not unconstitutional.
548
Bla ck thus provides
another individual rights view, along with the standard
exceptions from the late nin eteenth centur y.
15. George S. Boutwell
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1501
549. James Ford Rhodes, Ulysses S. Gran t, E igh teen th Presid ent , 9 AMERICA 69,
75 (1868), in AMERICAN FREEDOM LIBRARY: TODAYS ISSUES, TRADITIONAL VALUES (CD
ROM ed. 1997).
550. John Harr ison, Reconstructing the Privileges or Imm unities Clause, 101 YALE
L.J. 1385, 1440 (199 2).
551. See THO MAS H. BROWN, GEORGE SEWALL BOUTWELL: HUMAN RIGHTS
ADVOCATE 66 (1989 ); Michael W. McConn ell, Institutions and Interpretation: A
Critique of City of Boerne v. Flores, 111 HARV. L. REV. 153 , 183 (19 97).
552. See Michael W. McConn ell, Originalism an d the Desegr egation Decisions, 81
VA. L. REV. 947, 1071-7 2 (19 95).
553. S ee, e.g., GEORGE S. BOUTWELL, THE WAR OF DESPOTISM IN THE PHILIPPINE
ISLANDS (189 9); Hen ry G. P ear son, George Sewall Boutwell, in DICT . AM. BIO., supra
note 90; George S. Bou twell, Imperialism and Anti-Imperialism, Address at Con fer en ce
of Anti-Im perialist s, Boston (May 16, 1899), available online <http://home.ican.net/
[A] sturdy Puritan and politician of sterling virtue,”
549
attorney George S. Bou twell was t he “arch-radical” of ra dical
Repu blicans du ring the Civil War and Reconst ruction.
550
He
was elected to the Massachusetts state legislature as a
Democrat, and then elected Governor of Massachusetts in 1851
by a coalit ion of Democrats and Free Soilers. But his vehement
opposition to slavery impelled him to becom e one of the
founders of the Massachusetts Republican party.
During the Civil War, Boutwell served as America’s first
Commissioner of Internal Revenue, and then in the United
States House of Representatives from 1863 to 1869. He was one
of the Radical Repu blican lea ders in the House, ser vin g on the
Joint Committee on Reconstruction, and playing a major role in
the shaping and passage of the Fourteenth and Fifteenth
Amendments. Boutwell was exceeded by no one in Congress in
his determination to use federal power t o end slavery and
promote civil rights for the freedmen.
551
He was far ahead of his
time, proposing an amendment to the Civil Rights Act of 1866
that would have required public schools to be integrated.
552
President Grant appointed Boutwell Secretary of the
Treasury, a post he left in 1873 wh en he was elect ed to the
Senate. He left the Senate in 1877 when President Hayes
appointed him to recodify the statutes of the United States. He
produced the Revised Statutes of the United States in 1878.
Thereafter, until h is death in 1905, he practiced inter national
law in Massachusetts. Boutwell remained active in public
affairs, closing his career as President of the Anti-Imperialist
League and playing a leading role in the fight against the new
American foreign policy created by President McKinley.
553
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1502 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
~fjzwick/ailtext s/gsbimper .htm l>.
554. GEORGE BOUTWELL, THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES AT THE END
OF THE FIRST CENTURY (1987) (18 95).
555. Id. at 358
556. Id. at 359.
557. See id. at 359-60.
558. See JAMES SCHOULER, A TREATISE ON DOMESTIC RELATIONS (187 0); JAMES
SCHOULER, A TREATISE ON THE LAW OF HUSBAND AND WIFE (188 2); J AMES SCHOULER,
A TREATISE ON THE LAW OF MARRIAGE, DIVORCE, SEPARATION AND DOMESTIC RELATIONS
(6th ed. 192 1); see also Michael Grossber g, Balancing Acts: Crisis, Change, and
Continuity in Am erican Family Law, 1890-1990, 28 IND. L. REV. 273, 275 (1995)
(noting that “family law ha d been scatter ed about the lega l landscape” until th e “first
major compilat ion” by Sch ouler ).
559. See JAMES SCHOULER, A TREATISE ON THE LAW OF BAILMENTS (3d e d. 1 897);
JAMES SCHOULER, A TREATISE ON THE LAW OF PERSONAL PROPERTY (2d. ed. 1887);
JAMES SCHOULER, LAW OF WILLS, EXECUTORS AND ADMINISTRATORS (6t h e d. 1 921).
George Boutwell’s The Constitution of the United States at
the End of the First Century appeared in 1895.
554
Boutwell’s
chapter onThe Right of the People to Keep and Bear Arms”
informed the reader that “the only case of impor tance” which
has arisen under the Second Amendment was Presser.
555
After
summarizing the case background and pointing out that the
Illinois militia statute enrolled able-bodied males between the
ages of eighteen and forty-five in the state militia, Boutwell
noted that the claim was made that the Illinois statute against
armed parades without a permit (exceptin g para des by th e
state militia) was challenged under the Second Amendment.
But the Supreme Court explainedthat the Second Amendment
was a guarantee that nothing should be done by the United
States in restraint of the right of the people to keep and bear
arms, but that the amendment could not be appea led to as
limiting the power of the Sta tes.”
556
Boutwell concluded with
Presser’s caveat that state gun controls could not disable
citizens from performing their federal militia duties.
557
16. J am es S chouler
Professor James Schouler essentially founded the legal
subject of domestic relations with his 1870 treatise on the topic,
a treat ise which went through six pr intings over the next half-
century.
558
He also wrote treatises on wills, bailm ents, and
property,
559
and authored a major history of the United
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1503
560. See JAMES SCHOULER, HISTORY OF PEOPLE OF THE UNITED STATES OF
AMERICA: UNDER THE CONSTITUTION (Dodd, Mead & Co. rev. ed. 1970) (1st pub. 1880-
1913, 7 vols.); John H . Lat an e, J am es S chou ler, in DICT. A M. BIO., supra note 90.
561. JAMES SCHOUL ER, CONSTITUTIONAL STUDIES: STATE AND FED ERAL (Da Capo
Press ed. 1971) (1 897 ).
562. Id. at 192.
563. See id. at 192-93.
564. Id. at 192-93, n.6.
565. The Virginia section of the treatise quoted the Virginia Declar ation: “A well-
regulated militia is the na tu ra l an d sa fe defence of a fr ee s ta te; standing armies in
time of peace are dangerous to liber ty; and in a ll cases the m ilitar y should be strictly
subordinate to th e civil power.” Id. at 33. Schouler’s footnote added: “See standin g
army grieva nces u nd er th e Kin g recited in t he Decla ra tion of Independence, also
English Bill of Rights (Righ ts 6 and 7). Depen den ce upon a militia is more str ongly
asserted th an hither to.” Id. at 33 n.5.
566. Id. at 145-46.
567. Id. at 146 n.1.
States—the first to cover the period between the Revolution
and the Civil War in a scholarly manner.
560
In 1897, Professor James Schouler’s series of lectures to
graduate students at J ohns Hopkins University was published
as Constitutional S tudies: State and Federal.
561
Describing the
first eight amendm ents of t he Bill of Rights, Schouler wrote
that they “touch the individual and civil rights” andapply
exclusively to Federal jurisdiction and pr ocedure.”
562
For the
Second Amendment and the Fourth Amendment, Schouler’s
text did nothing more than quote the amendment in full,
offering a sparse commentary in a footnote.
563
The Second Amendment footnote stated:In the English Bill
of Rights of 1688 was a similar provision as to Protestants,
whom the King had disbanded while trea ting Rom an Catholics
with favor.”
564
The footnote also referred the reader to “State
maxims corresponding, in an earlier part of the treatise,
dealing with the Virginia Declaration of Rights of 1776.
565
Explaining the Congressional militia powers, Sch ouler
wrote that St ates “feared that the Union would weaken ea ch
local militia for st rengthening the regular army; and hence the
reservation here asserted [Article I’s reservation of militia
training, and the appointment of militia officers to the states],
as well as the jealous amendments of 1789.”
566
The “jea lous
amendments” are cited in the footnotes as “Amendments II. and
III.”
567
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1504 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
568. A footnote here referred the reader to the Second Amendment discussion.
See id. at 226 n.3.
569. Id. at 226. His footnote cited the 1850 Ken tu cky Constitution. See id. at 226
n.4. That Constitution included a right to bear arms provision t ha t spe cifically
excepted concealed carr y. See supra note 190. This provision was a r esp onse to an
1821 Kentucky cour t decision holding a law against concealed car ry to be in violation
of the state constitutional right to keep and bear ar ms. See supra note 152 and
accompanying text.
570. See C HARLES E. CHAD MAN , CONSTITUTIONAL LAW, FEDERAL AND STATE: BEING
A CLEAR AND COMPLETE ANALYSIS OF THE CONSTITUTION, TOGE THER W ITH A SUMMARY
OF THE LEADING DECISIONS AND BASIC PRINCIPLES WHICH GO TO MAKE UP THE
FUN DAME NTAL LAW OF THE STATE AND NATION (1899).
571. Id. at 159.
Like many other late nineteenth century commentators,
Schouler took care to emphasize that laws restricting concealed
weapons could pass constitutional muster. Describing changes
in state constitu tions in the middle of the nineteenth centur y,
he wrote: “To the time-honored right of free people to bear
arms
568
was now annexed, . . . the qualification that carrying
concealed weapons was not to be included.”
569
State laws
restricting the carrying of concealed weapons apply, obviously,
only to individuals, and not to state governments or state
militias. If concealed weapons laws are an exception to the right
to keep and bear a rm s, then the right is necessarily an
individual right.
17. Home schooling
TheHome Law School Series” of books reminds us of an
era when graduation from a law school accredited by the
Amer ican Bar Association wa s n ot necessary for adm ission to
the bar. The Constitutional Law book in the series combined
the Second and Third Amendments into a single paragraph.
570
The pr ovisions of Articles 2 and 3 were intended to protect the
peop le from arbitrary action on the part of governm ent similar
to that of the E nglish government in the past. The right of the
peop le to bear arm s was a practical recognition of their right to
demand with force that the government as constituted obser ve
Constitutional restraints. The right is general, and extends to
all citizen s, wh ether enr olled in th e m ilitia or not. But it is
held that it does not authorize the carrying of weapons that
are concea led, a nd wh ich are chiefly usefu l in in dividua l
encounters.—Cooley, Principles, 3d ed., 299.
571
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1505
572. See CASPAR THOMAS HOPKINS, A MANUAL OF AMERICAN IDEAS (187 2),
available online <htt p://moa.um dl.u mich.e du/cgi-bin /moa /sgm l/moa -
idx?notisid=AEW4514>.
573. Id. at 49.
574. Id. at 177-78.
575. See id. at 178-79.
The paragraph is a rather concise su mmary of the view of
the ninet eenth cen tury commentators: t he righ t belongs to all
Americans, not just militia members. The purpose of the right
is to resist unconstitutional government. The right to bear arms
does not extend to the concealed carrying of guns, or to weapon s
unsuitable for resistin g tyranny.
18. Civics manuals for youth
While legal text s fr om the nineteenth century are found in
most academic law libraries, books which discuss legal matters
for a popular audience are often not. Nor are such books often
listed in legal in dexes . Th us, the four popular books discussed
in this section are likely not the only books from the nineteenth
century wh ich were written by a nd for non-lawyers about legal
aspects of Amer ican government, in cluding the Second
Amendment. But the books do offer at lea st som e insight of how
materials for seconda ry schools and colleges treated the Secon d
Amendment.
Caspar Thomas Hopkins’ 1872 book A Manual of American
Ideas wa s written to inst ruct youth in pr inciples of American
government.
572
Hopkins listed “The right to keep and bear
arms as among “the rights which are secured to every
individual by th e Con stitutions and laws of th e Un ited
States.”
573
In a chapter devoted to a denunciation of standing
armies, Hopkins explained that one method by which standing
armies are kept in check is that[e]very individual throughout
the nation has the Constitutional right to keep and bear arms.
This accustoms t he people t o their use. (Th is righ t is not
allowed by governments that are afraid of the people.)”
574
The
state-based militia system was described separately, as a
distinct check on standing armies.
575
The Reverend Joseph Alden’s Alden’s Citizen’s Manual: A
Text-Book on Govern m ent for Com mon Schools was simpler
than the Hopkins book in its approach to many issues. Alden
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1506 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
576. JOSEPH ALDEN, ALDENS CITIZENS MANUAL: A TEXT-BOOK ON GOVERNMENT,
FOR COMMON SCHOOLS (New York, Sheldon & Co. 1869), available online
<http://moa.umdl.
um ich.edu/cgi-bin /moa /sgm l/moa-idx?n otisid=AHM4111>. Alden was a professional
educator, and the author of over seventy books, most of them didactic and intended
for Sun day school or classroom use . See Ha rris Elwood Sta rr , Joseph Alden, in DICT.
AM. BIO., supra note 90.
577. ISRAEL WARD ANDREWS, MANUAL OF THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED
STATES (Homer Mor ris r evised ed., N.Y., Am er ica n B ook 1 900 ) (188 7).
578. See Arth ur Gra ndville Beach , Israel Ward Andrews, in DICT. AM. BIO., supra
note 90.
579. ANDREWS, supra note 577, at 267.
580. See supra notes 3-4 and accompanying text.
quoted the full text of the Second Amendment in answer to the
question “Can the government disa rm the people?”
576
Israel Ward Andrews’ 1874 textbook Manual of the
Constitution of the United States had the same title as Timothy
Farrar’s 1867 legal treatise, although it is impossible to know if
Andrews knew of the Farrar book.
577
Andrews was a highly-
regarded professor at Mar ietta College in Ohio, and his Manual
was used for many years as a college t ext book.
578
Andrews gave
a milit ia-based exposit ion of th e Second Am endm ent: “The
militia are the citizen soldiery of the country, as distinguished
fr om the standing, or regular, army. The militia system has
been allowed to fall into partial decay, showing that the people
have little fear of need t o defen d t hemselves by force of ar ms
against their government.”
579
Andrews’ Manual is not
inconsistent with Henigan’s theory,
580
since Andrews does not
specify who the m ilitia are, or how t hey a re armed. Nor are
Andrews’ two sentences inconsistent wit h the mainstream of
nineteenth century thought.
Calvin Townsend’s 1868 Analysis of Civil Governm ent
(written as a textbook usable for prima ry, secondary, and
higher education) also offered a militia-cen tric explanation of
the Second Amendment:
The righ t of t he people t o ke ep and bea r a rm s, with wh ich
the General Government is herein prohibited from interfering,
refers to an organization of the militia of the States. There
have been fear s exp ressed, tha t t he liberty t he people might be
destroyed by the perverted power of a form ida ble sta nd ing
army. But here is the check t o an y su ch d an ger . The m ilitia,
that might be called out anytime on a month’s notice, would
outn umber , tw en ty to on e, any stan din g arm y in tim e of peace
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1507
581. CALVIN TOWNSEND, ANALYSIS OF CIVIL GOVERNMEN T 224 (1868).
582. Id. at 91.
583. See 1 JOHN RANDOLPH TUCKER, THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES,
at v (Fred B. Rothm an & Co. 1981) (1899). For a discussion of Hen ry St. George
Tucker, see supra notes 136-49 an d accompanying text.
584. See Ha lbrook, supra note 19, at 33.
585. “It is unfashionable, I know to stickle for the Constitution,” he once said.
49 CONG. REC., 1st Ses s., a pp. at 59 (18 86); see William G. Bean, John Randolph
Tucker, in DICT. AM. BIO., supra note 90.
586. See Car rington, supra note 19, at 333.
that will ever be tolerated in Un ited States. La rge stan din g
arm ies might in deed be da ngerous in a repu blican
government, but for a much stronger force distributed
throughout the ranks of the people.
581
But while H enigan sees the lauding of the militia as
inconsistent with an individual right, the nineteenth century
did not. Townsends book included detailed outlines showing
the order in which individual topics should be presented. Under
the general hea ding of “Freedomwas the subheading “Civil.”
The individual topics listed under civil freedom were fr eedom of
speech, freedom of the press, “[t]he right of the people
peaceably to assem ble and pet ition the government for redress
of grievances” and “[t]he right of the people to keep and bear
arms.”
582
Townsend listed the right to arms as among the rights
of an individual to civil freedom , rather than among the powers
of state governments.
19. John Randolph Tucker
The story of nineteenth century legal treatises and the
Second Amendment ends where it began, with the Tucker
family. John Randolph Tucker was the son of the Henry St.
George Tucker (the treatise writer and Vir ginia judge).
583
John
Randolph Tucker served as Attorney General of Virginia,
United St ates Repr esen tative, and P resident of the Amer ican
Bar Association.
584
He was a Democratic leader in Congress and
an ardent defender of the Constitution and its limits on central
power.
585
He also taught law at Washington & Lee, bearing as
pr ofound an influence on the growth and success of that school
as Thomas Cooley did at the University of Michigan.
586
As a private attorney, his most famous trial was the
Haymarket case, wh ich grew out of an 1886 confrontation
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1508 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
587. See Spies v. Illinois, 123 U.S. 131 (1887 ). At a meeting called to protest the
killing of striker s by police, someone th rew a bomb into a group of policemen.
588. See O’Neil v. Vermont, 144 U.S. 323, 361 (1892) (Field, J., dissenting, joined
by Harlan, J ., and Bradley, J.) (“[A]fter m uch r eflection I think th e definit ion given
at one tim e before th is cou rt by a distin guish ed a dvocate—Mr. John Randolph Tucker,
of Virgini a—is corr ect.”); see also Twining v. New Jersey, 211 U.S. 78, 114-27 (1908)
(Harlan, J., dissenting); Maxwell v. Dow, 176 U .S. 581, 605-17 (1900) (Harla n, J .,
dis sent in g).
589. See 1 JOHN RANDOLPH TUCKER, supra note 583, at vi.
590. The Tuckers’ footnote cited Federalist Nos. 28 and 46. In Federalist 46,
between strikers and a violent police force.
587
Tucker argued to
the Supreme Court that the Privileges and Immunities Clause
of the Fourteenth Amendment made all of the Bill of Rights
(including, of course, the Second Amendment ) enforceable
against the states, and therefore, the Haymarket defendants
were entitled to a reversa l of their convict ions, based on the
violation of the rights against self-incrimination and on their
right to an impartial jury. Tucker pointed to Congressional
debates on the Fourteenth Amendment, argued that
Cruikshank supported his position, and suggested that Presser
merely stood for the proposition that armed parades could be
prohibited. The Supreme Court, however, managed to sidestep
the wh ole issue, by pointing out that the object ions r aised by
Tucker in the Supreme Court had not been raised by th e
Haymarket defendants’ attorney at trial. Tuckers arguments
concerning the Fourteenth Amendment were adopted in 1892
by Justices Field, Harla n, and Bra dley.
588
John Randolph Tucker continued tea ching at Wash ington &
Lee throughout his 1876-88 ten ure in Congress. Up on
retirement from Congress h e resumed full-time law teaching
and began writing a treatise on constitutional law. Elected
President of the American Bar Association in 1892, Tucker was
not able to see h is treatise through to pu blication before his
death in 1897. His son , Henry St. George Tucker II (also a law
professor at Washington & Lee, and a future Congressman)
brought the manuscript to completion, without making editorial
changes, in 1899.
589
John Randolph Tucker explained the
Second Amendment:
This prohibition indicates that th e security of liberty
against the tyrannical tendency of government is only to be
foun d in the right of the people to keep and bear arms in
resisting the wrongs of government.
590
The case of Presser v.
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1509
Madison rejoiced in “the advantage of being armed, which the Americans possess over
the people of almost every other nation.” A national st anding army could not, as a
practical matter, amount to more t han 30,000 men, Ma dison said. “To these would
be oppos ed a militia a mou nt ing to near half a million of citizens with arms in t heir
hands . . . . It may well be doubted whether a militia thus circumscribed could ever
be conquered by s uch a prop ort ion of regular troops.” He predicted that the European
governments, who wereafraid to trust the people with arms,” would be “speedily
overturned if ever opposed by a popular m ilitia directed by locally-controlled
governments and officers.
In Federalist No. 28, Hamilton outlined one scenario of resistance to
[t]he enterpr ises of ambitious rulers in the national councils. If the
federal army should be able to quell t he r esist an ce of one Sta te, t he
distant States would have it in their power to make head with fresh
forces. The a dvan tages obtained in one place must be abandoned to
subdue the opposit ion in oth er s; a nd th e m ome nt th e pa rt wh ich ha d
been reduced to submission was left to itself, its efforts would be
renewed, and its r esistance revive.
591. 2 JOHN RANDOLPH TUCKER, THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES 671-
72, (Henr y St . Geor ge Tuck er ed., 1899); see also id. at 853 (citing Pres ser for the
proposition th at un der sect ion 5 of th e Fourteenth Amendment, Congresscan take
no action . . . to protect a citizen in his rights as a citizen of a State”; citing
Cruikshank for the proposit ion that federa l constitutional righ ts belon g to a per son
in his capacity as a citizen of the United St ates, and that section 5 of the Fourteenth
Amendment “does n ot limit t he police powers of th e St at es, nor affect the State
organism or it s fu nct ion s”).
592. See William M. Ivins, The S tatus of the Militia in Tim e of Riot—Part I, 18
ALB. L.J . 85 (1878); William M. Ivins, Note, Th e S tat us of th e Militia in T im e of
Illinois arose out of an act p assed by th e S ta te of Illinois
prohibiting all bodies of men other th an th e regu lar ly
organized volunt eer militia of the state from associating an d
drilling as such. The Suprem e Court held th at it d id n ot
conflict with this amendment, beca use the am en dm en t is only
a limitation of power on Congress, not on the States.
591
Thus, Tucker followed standard nineteenth century thought in
seeing the Second Amendment as designed to facilitate popular
resistance to tyranny. He likewise followed the standard post-
Presser view t hat the Secon d Am endm ent wa s n ot directly
applicable to the states.
C. Law Review Articles
So far as the indexes reveal, few nineteenth century law
reviews discussed the Second Amendment. For example, the
Albany Law Journal carried a two-part article about the New
York militia law, which did not mention the Second
Amendment.
592
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1510 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
Riot—Part II, 18 ALB. L.J . 107 (187 8).
593. See G.C. Clem ens, The Militia Law, 1 KAN. L.J. 261 (1885).
594. Id.
595. See id. at 261-62.
596. See id. at 263.
597. See id.
598. See id. at 264.
599. See id. at 265.
600. See id. at 262.
One notable exception, however, appeared in the Kansas
Law Journal. Published in 1885, this article remains to this
day one of the most incendiary discussions of militias ever to
appear in a law journal.
593
The article opened with sentiments
that are commonpla ce in the militia movement of the 1990s,
but rarely seen in law jou rnals. “Devoted to the constitution,”
began th e epigraph quoting Wisconsin Supreme Court Chief
Justice Ryan, “we invoke the vengeance of God upon all who
raise their sacrilegious hands against it.” The author continued
by quoting Tocqueville’s statement that unless democra cy is
guarded, “it merges into despotism.”
594
The author maintained
that Kansas was in fact drifting into despotism, as
demonstrated by the new state militia law.
595
This new Kansas militia law gave local officials the
authority to call out the militia, and the author feared that the
law would be invoked to suppress peaceful assemblies of
political dissidents.
596
Even worse, militia commanders
themselves were given unilateral authority to take action.
597
The author theor ized t hat this wa s particularly danger ous
because railroad companies could make their employees militia
captains, and then have the militia available as a private
army.
598
This new law was said to violate the Kansas
Const itution, which gave on ly t he Gover nor the authority to call
out the militia in circumstances far more limited than the
militia law authorized.
599
A strike in the town of Atchison illust rated the danger of
the new state militia law. Although the strike ended peacefully,
it was learned that both the Mayor and Sheriff of Atchison
wrote to the Kansa s Gover nor du ring the conflict, falsely
claiming that the town was in the possession of a violent mob.
In their letters, they a sk ed that the Gover nor call out the
militia to break the strike and suppress the mob.
600
If the
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1511
601. Id.
602. Id.
603. Id. at 265-66.
604. Id. at 266.
605. See Note, Constitutional Law— Militia—Right to Bear Arms, 22 CENT. L.J .
411 (1886).
Mayor or Sheriff had possessed unilateral authority to call out
the militia, they “would h ave cr imson ed the streets of Atchison
with the blood of curious men, women and children, and
provoked an insurrection th at would have made that city a
bloody field of battle.”
601
Moreover, continued the article, the militia created by the
new law was a select militia in wh ich only a sm all class of
citizens enlisted; in other words, “a milita ry class to terrorize
the community.”
602
In contrast:
The const itu tion al m ilitia is a thing into which a m an grows by
reaching his majority—he does not become a m ember by
voluntary enlistment. The intention was that every able-
bodied citizen should have a gun in his hands and know how to
use it; th en non e n eed fear his neighbor nor a despot; wh ile
this law puts arms into the ha nds of a class, and leaves the
average citizen at th eir mercy. This law creates a stan din g
army in violat ion of the Bill of Righ ts. What elem en t does it
lack? And while “th e people have the right t o bea r a rm s for
their defense and security,”standing arm ies, in time of peace,
ar e dan ger ous to libert y, and shall not be tolerated.” ([Kansas]
Bill of Righ ts, sec. 4.)
603
The article concluded by urgin g “some courageou s county
attorney towrap the stars and stripes about his hand and get
hold of this reptile before it hurts somebody.”
604
Although the
subject of the a rticle was t he Kansa s State Const itution, not
the Second Amendment, the article’s sen timents are notable
because it is one of only three nineteenth century American law
review articles that addressed the militia.
The only nineteenth century law journal article to address
the Second Amendment directly is a casenote on Presser, in the
Central Law Journal.
605
The note is a straightforward summary
of Presser, treating the case as affirming state authority over
conduct within its boundaries. The author concluded that “[i]t
will no doubt be n ews t o most people, not members of the legal
profession, and to many who are,” that the Second Amendment
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1512 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
606. Id. at 412-13.
607. Presser v. Illin ois, 11 6 U.S. 252 (188 6).
608. United St at es v. Cru iksh an k, 92 U .S. 542 (1876).
609. Pres ser, 116 U.S. 252.
610. 165 U.S. 275 (1897). For a discussion of the case, see infra text
accompanying notes 623-25.
611. The discussion of th e facts about Miller is based on the on-going research
of Stephen Halbrook, including the m aterial in STEPHEN P. HALBROOK , FREEDMEN,
THE FOURTEENTH AMENDMENT, AND THE RIGHT TO BEAR ARMS, 1866-1876, 184-85
(1998).
limits only Congress, and provides no protection against state
gun laws.
606
D. Summary of the Late Nineteenth Century Commentators
Some important lessons may be gleaned from the post-Civil
War treatises, commentaries, and law r eview articles. All of
them treat the Second Amendment as an individual right.
Except for Cooley, none are mentioned anywhere in the anti-
individual literature. Some of them limit the individual right to
the possession of guns for resisting tyranny, while others
explicitly affirm an individual right to own and carry guns for
personal protection.
The treatises also list various exceptions to the right to
arms, which were also expressed in Supreme Court cases: the
right limits only the federal government, not the states
(Presser
607
and perhaps Cruikshank
608
); the r igh t is not
infringed by a ban on armed parades on public property
(Presser);
609
and the right is not infringed by a pr ohibition on
carrying concealed weapon s (Robertson v. Baldwin).
610
VII. FIN- DE-S IÈCLE AND BEYOND
A. The Supreme Court
The Supreme Court decided t wo cases involving the Second
Amendment in the 1890s.
1. Miller v. Texas
Franklin P. Miller was the white owner of a small store in
Dallas wh o fell in love wit h a bla ck woman.
611
Because the
period just before and after the turn of the century was the
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1513
612. “J im Crow” was the name of a plan tation song; the ter m wa s applied to the
Southern system of le gally-man dated r acia l segregation .
613. The moder n t erm for th is is “dyna mic entr y.”
614. See Miller v. Texa s, 153 U .S. 535 (189 4).
apex of the horrible Jim Crow era,
612
a white man associating
with a black wom an often sparked violence in the South. The
city police in Da llas hea rd that Miller was carrying a handgun
without a license. The law of the time did not require that a
warrant be obt ained in order to arrest a person for unlicensed
gun carryin g. A gr oup of police officer s a ssembled in a local
tavern, enjoyed a good session of whiskey drinking, headed over
to Millers store, snuck in a side alley, and then burst into
Miller’s store with guns drawn.
613
The evidence is conflicting as to whether Miller thought
that the men breaking in with drawn revolvers were criminals
or government officia ls. Th e evidence is also conflict ing abou t
who fired first. In any case, Mr. Miller got off the first good
shot, killing one of the intruders. But Miller was outnumbered
and captured.
The episode infuriated the people of Dallas. Newspapers
raged that a man who loved agrea sy negress” had shot a police
officer. A lynch mob attempted to extricate Mr. Miller from jail
and hang him on the spot, but they did not succeed. Mr. Miller
was able to get a trial before being hanged. At the trial, where
defendant Miller was charged with murder, the prosecutor told
the jury that Miller had been illegally carrying a gun. Miller
was convicted of murdering a police officer. Seeking to stave off
execution, Miller filed various appeals (all of which were
rejected), finally appealing to the United States Supreme Court.
Miller’s appeal to the Supreme Court claimed that his Second,
Fourth, Fifth, and Fourteenth Amendment rights had been
violated.
614
In particular, Miller argued that (1) the Texas
statute against concealed carry was invalid; (2) the statute
allowing arrest with out a wa rrant was also invalid; and (3) his
alleged violation of the carry law should not have been used as
an argument by the prosecutor.
The Court disa greed a nd wrote that “the law of the State
[which forbade the carrying of dangerous weapons on the
person did not] abridge the privileges or immunities of citizens
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1514 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
615. Id. at 539.
616. Id. at 538.
617. Id.
618. See Chicago, Burlingt on & Quincy R.R. Co. v. Ch icago, 166 U.S. 226 (1 897 ).
619. See Halbrook, Personal Security, supra note 1, at 343-44.
620. See supra notes 498-510, 522-48, 583-91 an d accompa nying text.
of the United States.”
615
Further,the restrictions of these
amendments [Second and Fourth] operate only upon the
Federal power.”
616
At first glance, Miller would seem to reiterate what was
well established by Cruikshank and Presser. However, the
Court muddied the waters by stating that[i]f the Fourteenth
Amendment limited the power of the States as to such rights,
as pertaining to the citizens of the United States, we think it
was fatal to this claim that it was not set up in the trial
court.
617
The neglect to raise the Fourteenth Amendment at
trial was also fatal to Miller, and he was executed by the State
of Texas.
If the problem with Mr. Miller’s Fourteenth Amendment
argument was that the argument was not raised at the trial
court, then the Fourteenth Amendment issue must logically be
one which has not been finally settled. The Miller court had
said that the Second, Fourth, and Fifth Amendments had no
place in state courts, but this language could be read as stating
only that the Amendments are not directly applica ble to the
states.
And, in fact, the Court was preparing to move a wa y from
earlier holdings that the Fourteenth Amendment did not apply
the Bill of Rights to the states. Three years after Miller, the
Court held the Fifth Amendment (one of the amendments at
issue in Miller) enforceable against the states.
618
Was Miller
one of the first hints that the Court was going to start taking
the Fourteenth Amendment more seriously after decades of
malign neglect?
Halbrook, almost alone among twentieth century
commentators, character izes t he n onincorporation language of
Cruikshank and Presser as dicta.
619
Yet the nineteenth century
commentators who mentioned Presser and Cruikshank, as well
as the Court in several cases, habit ually cited those cases for
non-incorporation.
620
On the other hand, not only did Miller
leave the door open a crack, but the 1891 West Virginia
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1515
621. See supra notes 277-80 an d accompa nying text.
622. See supra notes 587-88 an d accompa nying text.
623. Robert son v. Baldwin, 165 U .S. 275 (1897).
Supreme Court case Workman applied the Second Amendment
directly against the state.
621
John Randolph Tucker, a very
highly rega rded lawyer, apparently felt that Preseser and
Cruikshank left enough room for him to argue to the Supreme
Court—the year after Presser was decided—that the whole Bill
of Rights was enforceable against the states.
622
Further, in the
years between Cruikshank and Presser, a number of
commentators, including Th omas Cooley, viewed the Second
Amendment as enforceable against the states.
If Miller leaves us unclear about the Fourteenth
Amendment, its Second Amendment implications are
straightforward. Mr. Miller was a private store owner and
never claimed to be part of the Texas militia. Unlike the
defendant in Presser, Miller was not even acting as part of an
unofficial private militia. Un der the anti-individualist theor y of
the Second Amendment, it should have been easy for the Court
to deny his Second Amendment claim on the grounds that, as a
private citizen, he had nothing to do with the Second
Amendment. But instead, the Court simply said that Miller had
raised the claim against the wrong government by invoking the
Second Amendment directly against a state and at the wrong
time (attem pting post-trial to use the Second Amendment as
applied t hrough the Fourteenth).
Miller’s practical result, allowing the execu tion of a m an
who defended himself against racist thugs, is hardly a shining
example in civil liberty. But the case, like the preceding
Supreme Court cases involving the right to arms, does treat the
Second Amendment as a right of individuals.
2. Robertson v. Baldwin
Three years after Miller v. Texas, the Court heard R oberts on
v. Baldwin, a case involving merchant seamen who, after
jumping ship, were captured and impressed back into maritime
service without due process. The seamen argued that the terms
of their service contract amounted to “involuntary servitude” in
violation of the Thirteenth Amendment.
623
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1516 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
624. Id. at 281. The Robertson Court’s theory that the American Bill of Rights
includes all th e limits from Br itish common la w was plainly wrong. “[T]o assume t hat
English common law in this field became ours is to deny the generally accepted
historical belief thatone of the objects of the Revolution was to get rid of the English
comm on law on liberty of speech and of the press.’ A Book Named “John Cleland’s
Memoirs of a Woman of Pleasure” v. Attorney General of Mass., 383 U.S. 413, 429
(1966) (Douglas, J., concurring) (quotin g Schofield, Freedom of the Press in the United
S ta tes, 9 PUBLICATIONS OF THE AMERICAN SOCIAL SOCIETY 67, 76). Indeed, St. George
Tucker’s exposit ion of t he new American Const itu tion ha d sh own in great det ail how
Ame ri can rights were broader than their British counterparts. See BLACKSTONE, supra
note 14.
625. See Roberts on, 165 U.S. at 282.
The Court disagreed, exp laining that all Const itutional
rights (including the right to be free from involuntary
servitude) include certain except ions. These exceptions did not
need to be specifically noted in the Constitution, since they
were obvious and traditiona l:
The law is p erfectly well settled that the first ten amendments
to the Con stitu tion , comm only kn own as th e Bill of Rights,
were not intended t o lay down an y n ovel p rin ciples of
government, but simply to embody certain gua ranties and
immunities which we had inherited from our English
ancestors, an d which ha d from tim e im mem oria l been subject
to certa in well-recogn ized except ions arising from th e
necessities of the case.
624
The Court went on to add that these exceptions constituted
such things as legislation prohibiting libel, which does n ot
abridge the First Amendment freedom of speech, and the
prohibition of carrying concealed weapon s, wh ich does n ot
infringe the right to keep and bear arms.
625
The Court’s statement about the Second Amendment
indicates that the Court believed the Second Amendment
protects an individual right. After all, there were no statutes
prohibiting state militias or the National Gu ard fr om carrying
concealed weapons. Concealed carry proscriptions are aimed
only at private citizens, not at state militias.
Standard Model authors cite Robertson and Miller
frequently. Anti-individualists tend to emphasize the holding in
Miller, while ignoring the implications of the point abou t a
procedural default. Robertson is rarely cited, since it is fatal to
the theory that the Second Amendment does not protect the
right of individuals to carry guns.
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1517
626. See Sa lin a v . Blak sle y, 83 P . 619 (Ka n. 1905).
627. See J un ction Cit y v. M evis, 6 01 P .2d 114 5 (Ka n. 197 9).
628. The nin et een th centu ry un der stan din g of a “collect ive r igh t” read the Secon d
Amendment as guaranteeing a personal right to keep arms, so that th e people as a
group could r esist tyra nn y. Bu t a s u sed by th e Ka ns as cour t, “collective right” meant
an affirma tion of government power, in derogation to any right of a citizen.
629. The “collective right” (meanin g no right at all), next appeared in a judicial
opin ion in United States v. Adams, 11 F. Supp. 216 (S.D. Fla. 1935) (reasoning t hat
the Secon d Amen dmen t “refer s to th e milit ia, a prot ective for ce of government; to the
collective body a nd not ind ivid ua l righ ts ”). Since Adam s, the collective right has
appeared frequently in dicta in lower federal cour ts, bu t has n ot ma de headwa y in
the Sup rem e Cour t. S ee Denn ing, Simple Cite, supra note 1 (discussing lower cour t
cas es); Kopel & Little, supra note 1, at 525-41 (discussing Supreme Court case
hist ory).
630. 12 Ky. (2 Litt .) 90 (1822).
631. See Salina, 83 P. at 620-21.
632. Id. at 621 (quoting BISHOP, STATU TOR Y CRIMES, supra note 442, § 793, at
B. The Collective Right Establish es a Footing: Salina v.
Blaksley
After its creation by a concurring judge on the Arkansas
Supreme Court in 1842, the anti-individual theory of the
Second Amendment disa pp ea red from cases a nd t rea tises for
the rest of the nineteenth century. Beginning in 1905, the anti-
individual theory gained a more secure footing in the Kansas
Supreme Court decision Salina v. Blaksley. The S alina court
ruled that “right to arms” mea nt only that the state militia, in
its official capacity, and while in actual service, could not be
disarmed.
626
Although the Kansas Supreme Court later moved
away from Salina by declaring a local gun control ordinance
unconstitutional,
627
by then, Salinas “collective righ t” theory
(meaning, in this cont ext , no right at all),
628
had spread far
beyond the Kansas state line.
629
The significance of Salina for this article is that the Salina
court was forced to reject or misdescribe every nineteenth
century source of authority which it used. (No eighteenth
century or prior sources were cited.) The Kansas court rejected
Bliss v. Commonwealth
630
and the long line of cases holding
that in order to secure a well-regulated militia, individual
citizens needed to be able to own and practice with guns.
631
The
court quoted a sentence from Bishops Statu tory Crim es that
the keeping and bea ring of arms has reference only to war, and
possibly also to insurrections.”
632
The quote was accurate, but
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1518 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
536 ).
633. See supra notes at 442-47 an d accompanying text.
634. See Com monw ea lth v . Mu rp hy, 44 N.E. 138 (Ma ss. 1896).
635. Id., quoted in S alina, 83 P. at 621.
636. The Salina court was clearly on a mission. Neither party had urged an anti-
individual int er pretat ion in t he briefs; t he government attorney had sim ply argued
that the local law was a reas onable gun cont rol. See Brief for Appellee, Salina v.
Blaksley, discussed in Dowlut, Guarantees to Arms, supra note 1, at 77.
Unsur prisin gly, the Salina court also ignored th e pre-Civil War h ist ory of Kansas, in
which the proslavery government’s disarmament of individual citizens was denounced
nationally as a violation of the Second Amendment . See supra notes 310-16 and
accompanying text.
the Ka nsa s cou rt neglect ed the la nguage surrounding the quote
and other wr itings by Bishop, which made it clea r that Bishop
thought the right to arms belonged to individuals, not the
state.
633
Lastly, the court quoted Commonwealth v. Murphy, an
1896 decision which had upheld, against a state constitutional
claim, a Massachusetts law (similar to the Illinois law upheld
by the U.S. Supreme Court in Presser) which banned mass
parades with weapons.
634
The Massachusetts court had written:
The right to keep and bear arms for the common defense does
not include the right to associate together as a military
organiza tion, or to drill and parade wit h arms in cities or
towns, unless authorized so to do by law.”
635
But of course, the
Massachusetts holding that the right to arms does not
authorize individuals to behave in a certain manner is not the
same as the Kansas holding that there is no individual right at
all.
Ultimately, the Salina holding stands on the Kansas court’s
textual analysis of the implicat ions of th e Kansas arms right
provision and of t he Second Am endm ent. Th e Second
Amendment was not at issue in the case, and was simply
analyzed as a guide to textual analysis of the Kansas provision.
No amount of textual analysis, however, can explain why the
framers of the Kansas Constitution, in the middle of an Art icle
titledBill of Rights,” suddenly inserted a pr ovision that had
nothing to do with rights, but which instead tautologically
affirmed a power of the state government: in essence, the
m ilitia is under the com plete power of th e state governm ent.
636
Salina’s pa ragraph of dicta abou t the m ea ning of the Second
Amendment laid the foundation for a late twentieth century
anti-individual theory of the Second Amendment, a theory
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1519
637. See William s, Militia Movement, supra note 8. But cf. SIR EDWARD COKE, 2
THE FIRST PART OF THE INSTITUTES OF THE LAWS OF ENGLAND § 279b (Garland Publ.
1979) (162 8) (“ A right cannot d ie.’ Dorm it a liqu ando jus, moritur nunquam. For of
such an high estim ation is righ t in the eye of the law, as th e law prese rveth it from
death an d destr uct ion: tr odden downe it ma y be e, but ne ver tr odd en out.”).
638. See Powe, supra not e 1, a t 1379-8 1; Volokh , Th e Am azi ng Vanishing S econd
Amendment, supra note 1.
whose proponents often insist is the only possible
interpretation. The record of the nineteenth century
demonstrates just the opposite.
C. Late Twentieth Century Comm entators
1. Some thoughts about David Williams
David Williams is the twentiet h century expon ent of the
most sophisticated version of the collective rights theory of the
Second Amen dm en t. According to Willia ms, the Second
Amendment was, as the nineteenth century cases and
commentators agreed, intended to ensure thatthe people” of
the United States would be able to overthrow federal tyranny.
According to Willia ms, the sole purpose of the Second
Amendment was a well-regulated militia; self-defense had
nothing to do with it. The right to arms continues to exist,
wrote Willia ms, only a s long as do the con ditions on which the
Second Amendment’s republican theory is premised: only as
long as the people are universally trained to virtue through
state militia service; and only as long as the people are unified,
homogenous, and share a common vision of the good, so that
they could rise as a single body to overthrow a tyrant. Since the
diverse Americans of the late twentieth century do not fit the
criteria of the republicanpeople,” there is currently no Second
Amendment right to arms, although the right could reappear if
the people changed so t hat they on ce again fit the r epublican
model.
637
Williams’ theory has been criticized on three major grounds.
First, his theory allows a constitutional right to vanish as a
result of governmen t inaction (failure to conduct militia
training).
638
Second, his theor y is ahistorical. The F ramer s of
the Second Amendment were well awa re that “th e people” of
the early American Republic were never as unified as in the
republican ideal that Williams posits. If the Framers and the
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1520 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
639. See Kopel & Lit tle, supra note 1, at 483-84; see also GORDON WOOD, THE
CREATION OF THE AMERICAN REPUBLIC, 1776-1787, at 60-63, 218-222, 491, 579, 607
(1969) (stating that, in contrast to the British Whigs of the seventeenth century, the
Founders were well awa re of divisions a mong t he people, particula rly class conflict s).
As Chancellor Kent explained, the thirteen colonies were
jealous of each other’s prosper ity, an d divided by policy, institutions,
prejudice, and ma nn ers. So strong was th e force of these cons ider ations, and
so exasperated were th e pe ople of th e colon ies in th eir dis pute s with ea ch
other concern ing bound ar ies and chart er claims, that Doctor Franklin (who
was one of the commissioners to the congress th at form ed t he pla n of u nion
in 1754) observed , in th e year 1760, th at a union of the colonies against the
mother country was absolutely impossible, or at least without being forced
by th e most grievou s tyran ny an d oppre ssion.
1 KENT, supra note 464, at *205. In oth er words, William s ha s things exa ctly
backwards: nationa l unity is the result of resistance to tyranny, not an ess ential
condition precedent . The absence of national unity in a n ontyrannical per iod (such as
the late twen tiet h cent ury) does not pr eclude the em ergen ce of unity in a time of
emer gency.
640. See Lun d, Past and Fu ture, supra note 1, at 59 n.138.
641. See Kopel & Lit tle, supra note 1, at 483-84 n.237.
642. It is n ot enou gh to con fine th e mea sure of hu ma n r ights to t he virtu ous :
We should endeavour to mete out the blessing to ages of depravity (and
these will sooner or later take place) as a restorative to virtue. . . . The
surest way to avoid the evil [of enslavem ent by government], an d preserve
the dign ity an d hap pin ess of ma n, is to begin right—by clearly defining the
powers intended to be delegated by the people to their rulers for the sake
of protection—and expressly enumerating the rights to be reserved. Here
would appear the quid pro quo–and by appearing, these r ights would be
universa lly understood and rem em bered . Th e tra nsition fr om fr eedom t o
slavery would be less ea sy–for the rights of the people bein g constantly
impressed upon the min d, and th e prin ciples of government fully
understood–nothing would be left to th e sp ort of imp lication , or t he
constr uct ion of arbitrary controul.
Amer ican people would crea te a Second Am en dm en t wit hout
need for a utopia n t ype of “people,” why should we now impose
utopian conditions precedent on the Second Amendment?
639
Indeed, Williams admits that the virtuous people of his theor y
never existed, but incongruously asserts that the Second
Amendment cannot be given force unless his Platonic ideal
becomes incarnate.
640
Third, any change for the worse in the
character of any actor named in the Constitution (e.g., “the
people,” or “the House of Representatives”) is not a valid reason
for nega ting a por tion of the Const itution.
641
The Bill of Rights
was written not only for an age of virtue, but for potential
future ages of depravity, wh en controls on governmen t—and
reminders of virtuous ideals—wou ld be all t he more
necessary.
642
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1521
. . . [Quoting Jefferson:] “Our rulers will become corrupt , our people
careless. . . . It can never be too often repea ted , THAT THE TIME FOR
FIXING EVERY ESSENTIAL RIGHT ON A LEGAL BASIS, IS WHILE
OUR RULE RS ARE H ONE ST, AND OURSE LVES U NITED.”
Tullius (Philadelphia ), FREE MAN S J., Mar . 26, 1788, in ORIGIN, supra note 37, at 309-
10 (quot ing Jeffer son from Notes on the S tate of Virginia).
At the Virginia ratifying convention, Patrick Henry warned that the federal
government might neglect the militia, and the people would be disa rmed. Expecting
that virtue alone would guarantee the continuation of the militia was foolish, Henry
predicted:In this great, this essential part of the Con st it ut ion [feder al power s of t he
militia], if you are safe, it is not from the Constitution, but from the virtues of men
in gover nm ent. I f gen tle men a re willing to t rust them selves and posterity to so
slender and improbable a chance, they have greater strength of ner ves tha n I h ave.”
Richard Henr y Lee, Va. Convention Debates, June 14, 1788, in ORIGIN, supra note
37, at 407.
In what age is it more important to enforce strictly all constitutional rules
designed to protect the people from less than virtuous rulers: The Age of Thoma s
Jeffer son, or The Age of William Jeffer son Clin ton ?
643. S ee, e.g., ARTHUR M. SCHLESINGER, JR., THE DISUNITING OF AMERICA (1997).
But it is nineteenth century legal history that provides the
most powerful critique of Williams’ theory. Du ring that centur y,
according to Williams, the Second Amendment right to arms
should have vanished. Instead, the Amendment grew stronger
than ever. Williams points t o the va rious for ms of Amer ican
disunity toda y—such as divisions r ega rding race, r eligion ,
ethnicity, and sexu al orien tation—as proof that Americans of
the late twentieth century are no longer the homogenous and
unified Americans of the late eighteenth century. While we
should not underestimate the centrifugal pu ll of multi-
culturalism, and its harmful effect on American national
unity,
643
American disunity today is trivial compared to the
disunity associated with the Civil War. A civil war is, after all,
about the most profound sign of disunity possible.
Even after the North defeated the South, the country
experienced great difficulty restoring its u nity. Th e end of the
Civil War was t he beginning of a lower-grade, often violent
struggle between white supremacists and freedmen in the
South. And not long after the struggle ended, with the triumph
of white supr em acy, America found itself in the m idst of
another violent struggle—this one taking place all over the
nation—as workers literally fought for their rights and capital
holders suppressed the workers violently. America in the last
half of the nineteenth century was divided on sectional, racial,
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1522 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
644. See supra notes 333-58 and accompanying text.
645. See supra notes 348-54 and accompanying text.
646. See supra notes 360-487, 494-591, 611-25 and accompanying text
647. Bogus, Hidden History, supra note 2.
648. See generally id.
649. See id. at 333-35.
650. See Cottrol & Diamond, supra note 1.
and class lines to a much more profound degree than America is
divided today.
And what happened to the Second Amendmen t during this
period of very unrepublican disunity? Th e elect ed
representatives ofthe people” made the Second Amendment
stronger than ever.
644
For over a decade, Congress worked
energetically to protect the Second Amendment from private
and state government interference. Further, the state
legislatures ratified a Fourteenth Amendment intended to
guarantee a right to own weapons for personal defense.
645
Commentator after commentator and court after court affirmed
that the Second Amendment was a current, enforceable
guarantee of the righ t of every American citizen to own
weapons.
646
Almost all of these cases and commentaries were
contemporaneous with the turm oil associated with the Civil
War, the Reconstruction, or the labor wars. If the Second
Amendment survived and thrived through all the disunity of
the second half of the nin eteenth century, and also survived the
abandonment of the pretense of regular militia training by most
states after the Civil War, then it is hard to believe that the
Second Amendment is such a feeble creature that it can be
felled by the relatively minor modern disunities of the 1990s.
2. Some thoughts about Carl Bogus
In his 1998 article, The Hidden History of the S econd
Amendment, Carl Bogus follows in the path of David
Williams
647
and attempts to seriously engage original sources.
648
Alth ough Bogus writes in opposition to the Standard Model, his
article makes an important contribution by highlighting the
importance of the militia in the South in crushing and deterring
slave insurrections.
649
With the exception of Robert Cottrol and
Ray Diamond,
650
Standard Model authors have neglected this
unattractive aspect of the militia.
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1523
651. See Bogus, Hidden History, supra note 2, at 333-37.
652. See id. at 322-37.
653. See id. at 359-74.
654. “Have we means of resisting disciplined armies, when our only defence, the
militia, is put into the h ands of Congress?” Patr ick Hen ry, Virginia Ratifying
Convention, Jun e 5, 1788, in ORIGIN, supra note 37, at 370.
655. See Bogus, Hidden History, supra note 2, at 331 n.102, 349, 374 n.313.
656.
Forty year s ago, when the r esolution of enslaving America was formed in
Great Britain, the British P arliament was advised by an artful man [Sir
William Keith ], who was gover nor of Pen nsylvania, to disarm t he people;
that it was the best and most effectual way to enslave them; but that they
should not do it openly, but weaken them , and let them sink gradually, by
tota lly disusing and neglecting the militia.
Unfortunately, Bogus attem pt s t o turn a useful contribu tion
to scholarship about the militia into a tool that single-handedly
overturns the individual rights Standard Model. Bogus’ history
is plainly defective in its reading (and invention) of th e
eighteenth century record, and the defects become all the
clearer in light of the nineteenth centur y. Because Bogus’
article addresses eigh teenth century sources not previously
discussed in this article, it is now necessary to examine these
sources.
Bogus makes the following argument: (1) the militia in the
South was frequently used to suppr ess slave insurrections, and
for slave p atrolling to deter insu rrect ion or flight;
651
and (2) at
the Virgin ia ratifying conven tion, oppon ents of t he proposed
Const itution, such as Patrick Henry, worried that the federal
powers over the militia would prevent the states from calling
out their militias to suppress slave insurrections.
652
From these
uncontested facts, Bogus then makes a leap of reasoning to
conclude that Madison wrote the Second Amendment solely to
affirm the power of states to use their milit ias to crush slave
revolts.
653
One problem with Bogus’ thesis is that it ignores the
evidence that even the hard-cor e Vir gin ia slave owners, su ch as
Patrick Henry, who wanted a strong militia to protect them
from the slaves, also wanted a st rong militia for protection from
the federal government.
654
Bogus tells the reader three times
that George Mason had three hundred slaves;
655
but Bogus
never tells the reader that Mason wanted an armed white
populace not just to control slaves, bu t because wit hout arms,
the white population could more easily be enslaved.
656
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1524 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
George Mason, Virgin a Ratifying Conven tion, June 14, 1788, in ORIGIN, supra note
37, at 401.
657. The Address and Reasons of Dissent of the Min ority of the Convention of the
State of Pen nsylv an ia t o th eir Cons tit uen ts, PEN NSL YVANIA PAC KET, Dec. 18, 1797, in
ORIGIN, supra note 37, at 160.
658. Massachusetts Conven tion Debates, Feb. 6, 1788, in ORIGIN, supra note 37,
at 260. See als o id. at 263 n.4, for the political machinations surrounding the Adams
amendment.
Further, Bogus underplays the demand for an arm s right
that came from the Northern states, where protection of slavery
was not an important issue. Half a year before the Virginia
conven tion had m et, the m inority of the Pennsylvania ratifying
convention had demanded a Bill of Rights, includin g:
7. That the people have a right to bear arms for the
defense of them selves and their own state, or the United
States, or for t he pu rp ose of killin g game; an d n o law shall be
passed for disarming th e people or an y of th em , unless for
crimes com m itte d, or real danger of pu blic injury from
individuals; an d a s st an din g arm ies in the time of peace are
dangerous to liberty, they ought not to be kept up; and that
the militar y sh all be kept under str ict subordin at ion to and be
governed by the civil power.
8. The inhabitants of the several states shall have liberty
to fowl and hunt in seasonable times, on the lands they hold,
and on all other lands in the United States not enclosed, and
in like man ner to fish in all navigable wa te rs , an d ot hers n ot
private property, without being restrained therein by any laws
to be passed by the legislature of the United States.
657
Four months before Virginia met, Massachusetts ratified
the Const itution, after hard-line federalists turned back an
amendment authored by Samuel Adams,
that the said Constitution be never construed to authorize
Congress to infringe the just liberty of the press, or the rights
of conscien ce; or t o prevent the people of the United States,
wh o ar e pe aceable citizens, from keepin g their own arms; or to
raise standin g arm ies, unless when necessary for t he defence
of th e U nited Sta tes . . . .
658
Likewise, while Virgin ia wa s still debating the Constitution,
New Hampshire ratified t he document and recommended
amendments, including thatCongress shall never disarm any
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1525
659. N.H. Rat ifying Convent ion, J une 21, 1788, in ORIGIN, supra note 37, at 446.
660. N.Y. Ratifying Convention, J uly 26, 1788, in ORIGIN, supra note 37, at 481.
661. See R.I. Ratifying Convention, May 29, 1790, in ORIGIN, supra note 37, at
735.
662.
That the people have a right to bear arm s for the defence of themselves and
the state; and as stan ding armies in the time of peace are dangerous to
liberty, they ought not to be kept up; and th at the military should be kept
under strict subordina tion to, and governed by, the civil power.
PENN. CONST., DECLARATION OF RIGHTS ar t. XIII (1776), excerpted in ORIGIN, supra
note 37, at 754.
663. See VT. CONST. ch. 1, art . XV (1777), excerpted in ORIGIN, supra note 37, 767
(same la ngua ge a s P en ns ylva nia).
664.
The people have a right to keep and to bear arm s for the common defence.
And as , in th e t ime of peace, armies are dan gerous to liberty, th ey ought
not to be maintained without the consent of the legislature; and the military
power sha ll alwa ys be in an exact subordinat ion to the civil au thority, and
be governed by it.
MASS. CONST., PART THE FIRST art. XVII (1780), excerp ted in ORIGIN, supra note 37,
at 773.
665. See Bogus, Hidden History, supra note 2, at 364-65.
citizen, unless such as are or have been in actual rebellion.”
659
New Yorks convention concluded about a month after
Virginia’s, and New York ratified while requesting
amendments, inter alia, “[t]hat the people have a right to keep
and bear arms; that a well-regulated militia, including the body
of the people capable of bearing arms, is the proper, natural,
and safe defen ce of a free stat e.”
660
Rhode Island, which refused
to ratify until 1790, copied New York’s right to arms demand.
661
Long before the United States Constitution had even been
proposed, a right to arms had alrea dy been constitutionally
recognized—n orth of the Mason-Dixon line—in the
Pennsylvania Const itution,
662
the Vermont Constitution,
663
and
(more restrictively) in the Massachusetts Const itution.
664
Bogus
entirely neglects t o mention the Pennsylvania dissent and the
Samuel Ada ms proposal in Massachusetts. He provides no
explanation for why the right to arms amendment , supposedly
motivated only by Southern slave concerns, was demanded by
three Northern state conventions where slavery was
insignifica nt.
665
Thus, Bogus errs by giving the entire credit for the Secon d
Amendment to Virginia a nd the rest of the South, even though
demands for a right to bear arms came first from the North,
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1526 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
666. Bogu s briefly acknowledges the North ern views, but argues that they were
insignificant, compared to th e importance of Virginia. See id.
667. See William s, Civic Republicanism, supra note 8.
668. See Ha rdy, Second Amendment, supra not e 1. J effer son s m odel constit ut ion
for Virginia declared, “No freeman shall be debarred the use of arms within his own
lands or tenemen ts.” Thomas Jefferson , The Virginia Constitu tion, Third Draft, in 1
THE PAPERS OF THOMAS JEFFE RSON, 1760-1776, at 363 (195 0).
669. See sources cited supra note 1.
670. Bogus, Hidden History, supra note 2, at 344.
671. See id. at 390-407.
672. See id. at 393-95. Throughout the article, Bogus offers a one-sided catalogue
of militia failures, never a cknowledging a ny m ilitia success after 1775. See id. at 337-
44. For example, Bogus twice reminds the rea der th at the Virginia militia disgraced
itself by fleeing a t the Ba ttle of Camden, Sout h Ca rolina in 1780. See id. at 341, 345.
But Bogu s ign ore s the militia’s excellen t perform an ce a few m ont hs later in South
Carolina, at the Bat tle of Cowpens—the tur ning point of the wa r in t he South —wh ich
and such a right wa s alrea dy constitutionally established in
three northern states.
666
Bogus further errs by emphasizing
only one important Souther n inter est in the militia
(suppression of servile insurrection), while underestimating
other important Southern and Northern interests in the m ilitia
(such as deterring centralized tyranny enforced by a standing
army, or promoting civic virtue).
667
Moreover, Bogus ignores the
human rights tradition—of which Madison s closest political
ally and life-long friend Thomas Jefferson was an important
part—which promoted the right to arms for reasons totally
unconnected to the militia.
668
The Standard Model scholarship has provided abundant
eighteenth century historical evidence that one pu rpose of the
state militias was to resist federal t yranny, should the other
checks and balances in the gover nment fail. Another purpose
was to ensure that the people would be armed so that the
militia might be effective.
669
But Bogu s a voids discuss ing or
quoting any of these many statements by dismissing them as
soapbox rhetoric.”
670
He makes the astonishing claim that,
despite having recently fought a revolution to overthrow a
tyrannical government, the Framers of the Constitution did not
believe in the legit imacy of armed r esistance to a tyrannical
government (and hence, the Second Amendment could not
protect the arming of the populace as a last-resort check on
despotism).
671
Bogus supports this claim by stringing together a
litany of quotes showing that the Framers (Jefferson excepted)
were horrified by Shays Rebellion.
672
Bogus asserts that
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1527
set th e stage for York town. See LAWRENCE E. BABITS, A DEVIL OF A WHIPPING: THE
B ATTLE OF COWPENS (1998). Ther e, t he militia was suppor ted by the Continental
Army, an d su perbly led by Br igadier Gener al Da niel Morgan. See id.
Nor does Bogus mention the militia’s success again st General Burgoyne’s 1777
Sar atoga campaign, or that in 1778-79, the Kentucky m ilitia, led by George Rogers
Clark, captured key British posts on the Wabash River in the future states of Indiana
and Illinois. The victories helped legitimize the United States’ claim to all British
territory east of the Mississippi, wh ich Britain later recognized in t he 1783 peace
treaty. See ROBERT W. COAK LE Y & STETSON CONN, THE WAR OF THE AMERICAN
REVOLUTION 60-62 (19 75); EDWARD COUN TRYMAN , A PEOPLE IN REVOLUTION: THE
AME RICAN REVOLUTION AND POLITICAL SOCIETY IN NEW YORK, 1760-1790, at 76 (1 989 );
WALTER LAFEBER, THE AMERICAN AGE: UNITED STATES FOREIGN POLIC Y AT HOME AND
ABROAD SINCE 1750, at 20 (198 9).
A recent study of George Washington’s use of the militia in Connecticut, New
York, and New Jersey explains that, while the militia could not, by itself, defeat the
Redcoats in a pitched battle, the militia was essential to American success:
Washington learned to recognize both the st rengths and t he weaknesses
of the militia. As regular soldiers, militiamen were deficient . . . . He
therefore incr easin gly detach ed Cont ine nt als to sup port them when
operating against the British army . . . . Militiamen wer e available
everywhere and could respond to sudden attacks and invasions often faster
than the army could. Wa shington t her efore used th e militia units in the
states to provide local defense, to suppress Loyalist s, a nd to r all y to t he
army in cas e of an in vasion . . . .
Washington ma de ful l use of th e par tisa n q ua lit ies of the militia forces
around him. He used them in sma ll parties t o har ass and raid th e army,
and to gua rd all the places he could not send Continentals . . . . Rather
than try to turn the militia into a regular fighting force, he used and
exploited its irregular qualities in a partisan war against the British and
Tories.
. . . His view of militiam en a tt ach ed t o th e a rm y did not cha nge from
the view presented early in the war: “all the General Officers agree that no
Dep enden ce can be put on th e militia for a Continuance in Camp, or
Regularity or Discipline dur ing the short time they may stay.” This was
Washington’s major complaint about the militiamen. He did not quest ion
their bravery, loyalty, or willin gness to fight wh en n ecessary, but he could
never accept their h abit of comin g and going wh en t hey pleased. . . .
On the other h and, militiamen had m uch t o offer, especially when
fighting on their own and as partisans, and Washington tried to take
advantage of th eir availability eve rywher e. As th e wa r ca me to an end,
Washington expressed this attitude clearly: “The Milit ia of t his Count ry
must be considered as th e Pa lladiu m of our secur ity, and the first effect ua l
resort in cas e of hostility . . . .”
MARK W. KWASNY, WASHINGTONS PARTISAN WAR: 1775-1783, at 337-38 (1996)
(alt er at ion in original for Washington quote) (citing Letter fr om George Wa sh ington
to John Hancock (J uly 10, 1775); George Wash ington, Circular to the States (June 8,
178 3)).
673. See Bogus, Hidden History, supra note 2, at 390-96.
because the Fr am ers wer e against Daniel Shays, they must
have been against the gener al principle of revolution against
tyranny.
673
To the contrary, Shays Rebellion lacked t wo of the
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1528 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
674. THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE para . 2 (U.S. 1776). Some of the mor e
fervid Shaysites did claim th at the Massachusetts government wan ted t o take all
their land an d enslave them, see DAVID P. SZATMA RY, SHAYS REBELLION: THE MAKING
OF AN AGRARIAN INSURRECTION 96-97 (1980), but the claim obviously had no credibility
among the Fr am ers of the Const itution.
675. THE DECLARATION OF INDEPE NDENCE pa ra . 19 (U.S. 1 776).
676. Id. at pa ra. 20.
essential elements which, according to the Decla ration of
Independence, were necessary justifications for a legitimate
revolution. First, the policies of the Massachusetts government,
which so aggrieved Shays and his fellow farmers in the western
part of the state, may have been mistaken and burdensome, but
they were not an attempt to enslave t he people of
Massachusetts. In contrast to the policies of King George III,
nobody could seriously describe the polices of th e
Massachusetts government as “a ll having in direct object the
establishment of an absolute Tyranny.”
674
Second, the Massachusetts government, in contrast to King
George’s government, wa s a republican one in wh ich Shays and
his fellows were represented. When the American colonists had
Petitioned for Redress in the most humble terms . . . [and]
been answer ed by repea ted injury,”
675
the colonists’ peaceful
remedies were at an end; they had no representation in
Parliament. To accept Bogu s’ theory that the Founders were no
longerinsurrectionists” (Bogus’ term for just ifia ble revolution
against tyranny), Bogus requires us to believe that the
condemnation of Shays’ Rebellion proves that the Founders had
turned against the very political theory to which they had
pledged their “Lives,” theirFortunes,” and their “sacred
Honor.”
676
An explanation which does not require the reader to
believe that the Founders were so ideologically inconsistent is
simply that the Framers thought revolution justified in 1776
against King George, but not in 1787 against Massachusetts.
After all, if a speaker condemns an unjustified use of force in
purported self-defense, the condemnation does not necessarily
mean that the speaker is opposed to forceful self-defense in all
circumstances.
The theory that t he Framers disapproved of revolt against
tyranny is particular ly erroneous in the case of James Ma dison ,
because in Fed eralist No. 46 Madison sketched out a scenario in
which the necessarily small federal standing army would be
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1529
677. THE FEDERALIST NO. 46 (J am es Ma dis on).
678. Id. As the rest of the essay makes clear, Madison saw the likely success of
a militia revolt a gainst tyranny as depending on t he existence of strong state
governments to lead th e milit ias. See id.
679. See Bogus, Hidden History, supra note 2, at 400-04.
680. See id. at 401.
681. Id. at 404.
682. See ORIGIN, supra note 37, at 234, 647.
opposed bya militia amounting to near half a million of
citizens with arms in their hands” which would be able to
defeat a tyrannical standing army.
677
How could tyranny
over comethe advantage of being armed, which the Americans
possess over the people of a lmost every other nation”?
678
Bogus
labor s mightily to undo t he obviou s implications of these words,
and in the process offers some useful insights. For example,
Bogus observes that Madison was writing arguendo, since
Madison had made it clear that he expected that the federal
government would never attempt to rule tyrannically by
military force.
679
But neither this point , nor Bogus’ other points
(such as the fact that the Federalist essays were written in a
hurry),
680
undermine th e basic fact that Madison obviously
thought armed militia resistance to American federal tyranny
to be legitimate–even though Madison never expected the dire
event to take place.
That Madison apparently saw the militia as potentially
useful in resisting tyran ny cann ot be squared wit h Bogus’
assertion that the Second Amendment was only about
protecting the militia for slave patr olling and slave controlling;
nor can Madison’s words be squared with Bogus’s assertion that
except for Jeffer son none of the Framers were
insurrectionists.” Bogu s erroneou sly states that “one cannot
read The Federalist Num ber 46 as an explanation of the Second
Amendment because, of course, it would be several more years
before Madison would write that provision.”
681
Actually, the
interval from the publication of Federalist No. 46 (January 29,
1788) to Madison’s introduction of the Bill of Rights in Congress
(June 8, 1789) was less than a yea r and a half.
682
What evidence
is ther e in this interval that Ma dison abandoned his last
insurrectionist” thoughts? In support of his statement that the
Federalist No. 46 is not an explanation of the Second
Amendment, Bogus argues that Madison’ssupport for a strong
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1530 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
683. Bogus, Hidden History, supra note 2, at 404.
684. See id.
685. Id.
686. See ROBERT A. RUTLAND, JAMES MADISON: THE FOUNDING FATHER 5 (1987).
687. Letter from J am es Ma dison to George Mater (Ja n. 7, 1787), in 9 THE
PAPERS OF JAMES MADISON 230, 231 (Ro bert Rutland ed., 1975); see also RUTLAND,
supra note 686, a t 14. T he su ppre ss ion of an y futu re Shays -like ins ur rection was of
great impor ta nce to t he Ph ila delph ia Conve nt ion, an d wa s one of the reasons that the
new Constitution gave th e nationa l governm ent power over the militia, to rescue the
militia from t he n eglect of th e stat es. See SZATMARY, supra note 674, at 129 (citing
Madison’s Notes of the Debates in the Federal Convention of 1787). The Framers’
interest in u sin g th e milit ia t o suppr ess ins ur rection s by Nor thern white farm ers of
course cont ra dict s Bogu s’s pictur e of the militia a s ir releva nt excep t for th e purposes
of crushin g Sout her n sla ve revolts.
federal government and his fear of anarchy probably both
increased.”
683
Bogus further notes that one of Madison’s
biographers concluded that Madison liked the Constitution
even better after he had finished writing the Federalist.
684
True
enough, but liking the Const itution even more does not mean
that Madison loved civil liberty any less.
In addition, writes Bogus, “The full impact of Shays’
Rebellion and lesser insu rrect ions h ad proba bly not been fully
absorbed.”
685
Bogus provides no support for this claim, and it is
preposterous. As Robert Rutland, one of Madison’s biographers
on whom Bogus does not rely, notes, Shays’ Rebellion was
precisely the event that Madison used to convince George
Washington to attend the Phila delphia Conven tion that
Madison was trying to organize.
686
Rutland also observes that
the Philadelphia Convention opened in an atmosphere of panic
engendered by Shays Rebellion, and Madison himself found the
Rebellion distressing beyond measure to the zealous friends of
the Revolution.”
687
But if we are to believe Bogus, the very
Founder who organized this convention which was so stricken
by panic over Shays that it crea ted an entirely new form of
government, wa s h imself not feelin g “th e full impa ct” of the
Rebellion. Madison was a pparently a rather odd person : he
used Sh ays Rebellion to convin ce Am er icas elite that a new
government was desperately needed, and led a campaign that
spanned the continent in order to get the new government
approved; but perhaps suffering from some form of psychic
numbing, Madison never felt the full impa ct of Sh ays Rebellion
until the next year.
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1531
688. Bogus, Hidden History, supra note 2, at 404.
689. RUTLAND, supra not e 686, a t 168 (cit ing Let ter fr om J am es M adison to
Thomas Jeffers on (Fe b. 28, 1801 )).
690. James Madison, First Inaugural Address, March 4, 1809.
Finally, writes Bogus, Madisons insurrectionary
inclin ations from Federalist No. 46 cannot be carried forward
seventeen months into the Second Am en dm ent because, in the
interval, the “rhetoric that had been so useful in stimulating
revolution, such as romanticizing the militia and railing against
the evils of a standing army, must have begun to have a
different effect on Madison as it became th e tool of anti-
Federalist opposition.”
688
Again, there is no evidence for Bogus’
attempted mind reading.
The historical record makes it abundantly clear that to
James Madison, “the rhetoric” about the virtues of militias and
the terrors of standing armies was not a mere talking point
that he abandoned once his cherished Const itution became
operative. In 1801, the political party created by J efferson and
Madison took power after winning the election of 1800—despite
the problems caused by the elect ion being thrown into the
House of Repr esen tatives by Vice-Presiden t Aaron Burr’s
chicanery.What had saved America from the spectacle of
bloodsh ed?” ask s Robert Rutland, the compiler of the Madison
Papers.
In Ma dison s m in d t he a nswer wa s cr ysta l-clea r: th e la ck of a
standing arm y. He never expected the anti-Jefferson forces to
win, he con fess ed to the n ewly elected p re siden t, for it would
have been im possible to oppose the people’s will “without any
military force to a bet usu rp at ion.” Ever t he optim ist , Ma dis on
said the wh ole exp erien ce had been beneficial. “And what a
lesson to Am er ica & t he w orld, is g iven by th e efficacy of t he
pu bl ic w ill w h en ther e i s n o a rm y t o b e t urn ed ags t. it !”
689
In his First Inaugural Address, in March 1809, President
Madison urged Americans during a period leading up to war
with Great Britain, “to keep within the requisite limits a
standing military force, always remembering that an armed
and trained militia is the fir mest bu lwark of republics—t hat
without standing armies their liberty can never be in danger,
nor with large ones safe.”
690
Not only did Madison still prefer
militias to standing armies, he obviously saw the militia as
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1532 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
691. 1 W. & M., Sess. 2, ch. 2 (1689).
692. Bogus, Hidden History, supra note 2, at 384. Bogus is corr ect in saying that
the British provision gave Par liament wide latitude in controlling who could own
what types of gun s, bu t wron g to con clud e tha t t he pr ovision’s pla in lan guage did not
recognize a right of Englishmen . Bogus rea sons that since the “as allowed by law”
clause recognized Parliamentary authority to limit arms ownership, the entire clause
is mer ely an assert ion of Parliament ar y supr ema cy against t he Kin g with regard to
arms contr ol. Id. at 383-85. The assertion that a subordinate clause overwhelms and
obliterates the plain mea ning of the main clause is an interpr etive m ode which Bogus
applies to both th e E nglish Decla ra tion of Righ ts an d the American Secon d
Amendment.
Bogus leads h imself int o error by r ea soning th at sin ce t he Conven tion Parliament
(which gave the crown to William and Mary, after the Glorious Revolut ion) was a ngry
that the previous King, Jam es I I, h ad at te mpte d t o disar m m ost of th e popula tion ,
Parliament was merely asserting its own supremacy regarding arms control. But
everything that James II did to take arms away from English subjects was pursuant
to duly-elected Parliamentar y statutes, including the Game Act of 1671. James II had
never asserted that he, rather than Parliament, could make the gun laws; he had
simply rigorous ly en force d the gun s laws ma de by the Re stor at ion Parliam ent s. See
MALCOM, supra note 1, at 94-112. Bogus does not provide one example of any seizu re
of private arms by King James II that went beyond the bounds of what Parliament’s
laws authorized.
Of cours e, t he me re re cogn it ion of an individual right by Parliament did not do
much to protect the right, beyond making a moral statement. In a system of
Parliamentary supremacy an d with out m eaningful judicial review, future Parliaments
could easily undo what the 1689 Parliament ha d done. And gi ven th e br ea dt h of th e
“suitable to t he ir conditions, an d a s allowed by law” lan guage, one could argue that,
even today, Parliam ent has not infringed the right, since modern English subjects are
allowed to have manua l action rifles and shotguns, after passin g th rou gh a r igor ous
licensing process .
693. Bogus, Hidden History, supra note 2, at 386.
694. Id. at 366.
useful for somet hing other than catching slaves—namely
pr otection against foreign invasion.
The English Declaration of Rights of 1689 proclaimed
[t]hat the su bjects which are Protestants m ay have a rms for
their defence suitable to their conditions and as allowed by
law.”
691
Bogus argues that this provisiondid not give
Protestants an individual righ t to have a rms; it decreed that
Parliament, and not the Crown, would determine the right of
Protestants to have arms.”
692
Madison, Bogus informs us,was
almost certainly influenced by the right to arms provision of the
Declar at ion,” and “Madison followed Parliaments solution” by
not inserting an individual right into the Second Amendment.
693
“We do not know why Ma dison chose to dr aft his pr ovisions
precisely this way. He did not explain his thinking in any
speech or letter that has come to light,” writes Bogus.
694
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1533
695. James Madison, N otes for S peech in Congress Supporting Amendments, June
8, 1789, in ORIGIN, supra note 37, at 645.
696. Id.
697. FEDERAL G AZETTE (Phila delph ia), J une 18, 1789, at 2, in ORIGIN, supra note
37, at 671.
Actually, Madison did explain his drafting choices, and that
explanation makes it clear that Madison (unlike Bogus) viewed
the English Declaration as protecting an individual right, and
that Madison wanted the American arms right to be broader
and more protective of individual rights than was the English
ver sion.
Madison’s notes for his speech in Congress introducing the
Bill of Rights explained that the proposals were to deal with the
omission of guards in favr. of rights & libertys.”
695
His
amendmentsrelate 1st. to private rights.” A Bill of Rights was
useful—not essential.” There was a “fallacy on both
sides—especy as to English Decln. of Rts.” First, the
Declaration was a “mere act of parlt.” Second, the English
Declaration was too narrow; it omitted certain rights and
protected others too narrowly. In particular, there was no
freedom of pr ess—Conscience.” Th ere was n o pr ohibition on
Gl. Warrants” and no protection for “Habs. corpus. Nor was
there a guarantee of “jury in Civil Causes” or a ban oncriml.
attainders.” Lastly, the Declaration protected only “arms to
Protestts.”—appa rently t oo narrow a slice of popu lation.
696
And there is more evidence, apparently hidden from Bogus,
about what Madison’s Bill of Rights meant. A few days after
Madison introduced the Bill of Rights, Madisons political ally
Tench Coxe (who would serve President Madison’s
administration as the Purveyor of Public Su pplies, in charge of
procuring arms for the militia) wrote the most comprehensive
section-by-section exposit ion on t he Bill of Rights to be
published du ring it s r atifica tion period. Regarding the Second
Amendment, Coxe explained:
As civil ru lers, not having th eir du ty to t he people, duly before
them, may attempt to tyrannize, and as th e military forces
which shall be occasionally raised to defend our country, might
pervert th eir pow er to t he in jury of th eir fellow-citize ns, the
people ar e confirmed by th e next ar ticle in their right to keep
and bear their private arms.
697
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1534 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
698. See Coxe to Ma dison, Jun e 18, 1789, in ORIGIN, supra note 37, at 672.
699. Madison to Coxe, J une 24, 1789, in ORIGIN, supra note 37, at 673.
700. Id. at 674.
701. See JACOB E. COOKE, TENCH COXE AND THE EARLY REPUBLIC 113 (1978).
702. Bog us, Hidden History, supra note 2, at 369.
703. See id. at 408.
Coxe sent a copy of his essay to Madison, along with a letter
of the same date.
698
Madison wrote back acknowledging “your
favor of the 18th. instant. The printed rema rks inclosed in it
are already I find in the Gazettes her e [New York].”
699
Madison
approvingly added that ratification of the amendmentswill
however be greatly favored by explanatory strictures of a
healing tendency, and is t herefor e a lready indebt ed to the co-
operation of your pen.”
700
Madison respected Coxe’s ceaseless
work on behalf of the proposed Constitution in 1787-88, and
liked some of Coxe’s feder alist essays so much that Madison
successfully urged Virginia newspapers to reprint them.
701
Of
course, Madison’s apprecia tive endor sement of Coxes essay on
the Bill of Rights did not specifically say “I endorse every single
statement made in your essa y.” On the other hand, if Ma dison
disagreed with the prolific author’s analysis, Madison might
have been expected to correct him, so as to prevent the
propagation of further errors. Historians may debate how much
weight to give Coxes explica tion (wh ich was u ncontradicted
during the ratifying period) and Madison’s approving letter to
Coxe. But it is astounding that Bogus, in a hundred-page article
filled wit h specu lation about Madison’s supposed hidden
thoughts, fails even to mention some rather notable written
evidence about what Madison and his contemporaries rea lly
thought.
Bogus’ theory is also self-contradictory. He asserts that
Madison wrote the Second Amendment the way he did because,
“Specifically, Madison sought to assure that Congresss power
to arm the militia would not be used to disarm the militia.”
702
But then Bogus informs us that Congress can, using its power
toorganize” the militia, declare that the militia consists only of
a small group (such as the modern National Guard) and disarm
everyone else.
703
Bogus thus joins Garry Wills in the assertion
that the Second Amendment effectively means nothing at all.
But while Wills considers Madison a devious trickster —with a
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1535
704. See Wills, supra note 5.
705. House of Representatives, Ju ly 28, 1789, in ORIGIN, supra note 37, at 680.
706. See Bogus, Hidden History, supra note 2, at 370.
707. House of Represent at ives, Aug. 17, 1789, in ORIGIN, supra note 37, at 695.
708. Bogus, Hidden History, supra note 2, at 371.
709. See id.
clever ploy of draftsmanship that meant nothing and fooled the
entire nation
704
—the implication drawn from the Bogus article
is that Madison wa s a fool; Ma dison supposedly drafted an
amendment that was intended t o pr event Congress fr om
disarming the state militias; but despite Madison’s amendment,
Congress can do exactly what the amendment was designed to
prevent.
Here, Bogus is directly contradicted by t he h istorical record.
Madison’s original Secon d Am endm en t concluded with the
provisionbut no person religiously scrupulous shall be
compelled to bear arm s.”
705
Although Bogus notes that
Massachusetts Congressm an Elbr idge Ger ry wa nted Ma dison s
clause narrowed,
706
Bogus does not inform the reader of Gerry’s
specific objection: “Now, I am apprehensive, sir, that this clause
would give an opportunity to the people in power to destroy the
constitution itself. They can declare who are those religiously
scrupulous, and prevent them from bearing arms.
707
In other
words, Representative Gerry was afraid that Congress could
use the religious exemption as a pretext to exclude large
numbers of people from the militia. Representative Gerry was
attempting to ensure that Congress would not have the power
to do what Bogus asserts Congress can do: to replace the
universal militia with a select militia, and to disarm everyone
not in the select militia.
Bogus’ unsupported claim s to know what Madison t hought
are buttressed by claims to know what everyone else thought.
We are informed by Bogus thatMadison’s colleagues in the
House and Senate almost certainly considered the Second
Amendment to be part of the slavery compromise.”
708
But Bogus
provides no evidence, other than to list the slavery compromises
that were in cluded in the or iginal Con st itution.
709
Putting aside evidence from the Founding Era, a powerful
refutation of Bogus’ thesis can be found in the Appendix to
George Ticknor Curtis’ Constitutional History of the United
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1536 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
710. See discussion of Curtis supra notes 503-10 an d accompanying text.
711. See 2 CURTIS, supra note 507, at 580.
712. Id.
713. See id. at 580-88.
714. See id. at 584-85.
715. See id. at 580-88.
716. See supra notes 288-309 an d accompanying text.
States.
710
Among Curtis’ appendices is the full text of Anti-
Slavery Tracts published around 1833.
711
The tract is an
abolitionist argument that the United States Constitution “is a
pro-slavery instr ument.”
712
The tract analyzes in detail the text
of the Constitution, the intent of the Framers, the
implem entation of the Const itution by Congress, and the
constitutional law decisions of t he Supr em e Court, all of which
support slaver y, a ccording to the t ract.
713
In each of the four
parts of analysis, the tract points t o Article I, s ect ion 8, which
gives Congress t he authority to call forth the m ilitia to suppress
insurrection. The tract even quotes from the Virginia ratifying
convention, in which George Nicholas a nd J ames Madison both
argued that Article I, section 8 does not diminish a state’s
authority to use its own militia to crush an insurrection; rather,
the clause allows Congress to call forth the militias from other
st ates, in order to assist the suppression of the in su rrection.
714
Yet while Article I, Sect ion 8 is, quite plausibly, shown to be
a proslavery part of the Constitution, the Second Amendmen t is
never mentioned in that tract.
715
If, as Bogus argues, the only
important reason for the Amendment was to suppress slave
revolts, it is rather strange that the antislavery,
anticonstitution tract never mentioned the Second Amendment.
That one purpose of the militia was to suppress “servile
insurrection,” and that the Richmond Convention debates
discussed this militia purpose, was not “hidden,” but was
perfectly obvious t o antebellum America. Bu t as for the Secon d
Amendment, it was, so far as the known record indicates, never
used to bolster the argument (from either the abolitionist or the
slave-owning side) that the Const itution was m eant to pr otect
slavery. To the contrary, the Second Amendment appeared in
the antebellum writings of Lysander Spooner and J oel Tiffany
for just the opposite proposition: that the Second Amendment
was incompatible with slavery.
716
If the Second Amendment
were a slaver y-protecting device, then the Reconstruction
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1537
717. See supra notes 333-58 an d accompanying text.
718. See Wills, supra note 5.
Congresses would likely have treated it with the disdain
reserved for other const itutional theories—lik e t he doctrine of
nullification and interposition—that had been invoked to shield
slavery from federal interference. Congress, of cour se, did just
the opposite; Congress venerated the Second Amendment as a
right of individual freedmen to protect themselves against the
Ku Klux Klan and other descendants of the slave patrols.
717
Like Garry Wills’ theory that the Second Amendment was a
fraud known only to James Madison,
718
Carl Bogus’ Hidden
History is contrary to the writings of the Founders and to the
interpretive record of the century following the creation of the
Secon d Amendment. One testament to the overwhelming
evidence for the individual rights Standard Model is that
opponents of the model must rely on theories which claim to
read the secret thoughts of James Madison; secret thoughts
which are claimed to be more important than what James
Madison and his allies actually said and wrote.
D. Firearms Policy for the Twenty-first Century
Following a period of scholarly neglect in mid-century, the
Second Amendment is currently enjoying a renaissance of
scholarly interest as the twentieth centur y concludes. As
scholars attempt to provide constitutional guidance for the
twenty-first century, it is worth rem em bering the in tellect ual
heritage of the nineteenth century discussed in this article.
1. Who is protected by the Second Amendment?
This is the easiest question; the answer is “the people of t he
United States.” The right belongs t o all people, n ot ju st to
militia members or to state governments. According to
Robertson, there are im plicit except ions, su ch as prisoners.
Women were not subject to militia duty in the nineteenth
century, but no one appears to have argued that women could
legally be barr ed from owning and carrying guns.
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1538 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
2. Does the Second Am endm ent limit the states?
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1539
719. 307 U.S. 174 (1939).
720. See id. at 178.
This is the hardest question. Presser and the dicta in
Cruikshank su ggest not, bu t these two cases are part of a
period of constricted Fourteenth Amendment interpretation
which the Supreme Court rejected in the twentieth century.
The new research, conducted by scholars such as Richard Aynes
and Stephen H albrook, into the Congressional creat ion of the
Fourteenth Amendment provide additional justification for the
rejection of the Slaughter-House/Cruikshank/Presser lin e of
cases as inconsist ent wit h the or iginal inten t of the Fourteenth
Amendment—or at least the original intent of the Radical
Repu blicans who created and promoted the Amendment.
Perhaps the twenty-first century will put an end to over 125
years of result-oriented Fourteenth Amendment jurisprudence
and simply make the whole Bill of Rights enforceable against
the states through the Privileges and Immunities Clause. Such
a result would be more logically defensible than the current
practice, under which incorporated “due process” includes
everything in the fir st nine a rticles of the Bill of Rights except
the Second and Third Amendments and the right to grand jury
indictment.
3. What kind of “arms”?
The dominant line of nineteenth century inter pretation
protected ownership only of weapons suitable for “civilized
warfare.” This standard was adopted by the U.S. Supreme
Court in the 1939 United States v. Miller case.
719
There, the
Court allowed defendants who never claimed to be part of any
militia (they were bootleggers) t o raise a Second Am en dm en t
claim. But the Supr em e Court rejected the federal district
court’s determinat ion that a federal law requiring the
registration and taxation of sawed-off shotguns was facially
invalid as a violation of the Second Amendment. Rather, said
the Miller Court, a weapon is only covered by t he Second
Amendment if it might contribute to the efficiency of a well-
regulated militia. And the Court would not take ju dicial notice
of militia uses for sawed-off shotguns.
720
The case was
remanded for trial (at which the defendants could have offered
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1540 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
721. See Stat e v. Delgado, 692 P.2d 610 (Or. 1984) (switchblades); Stat e v.
Blocker, 630 P. 2d 824 (Or . 1981) (b illy clubs).
722. S ee, e.g., Cent er t o Prevent H andgun Violence, Center Files Suits Against
Assault Weapon Maker For Victims of California Shooting, LEG AL ACTION RPTR. (Sept.
1994) (quoting from the litigation arm of Handgu n Cont rol: “In filing these lawsuits,
the Cen te r h ope s fin ally t o mak e t he ma nu fact ur er s of these weapons of war and
their accessories pay for at least some of the cost th eir pr odu cts impose on the
victims of gun viole nce ”).
723. See David T. Ha rdy, The Firearms Owners’ Protection Act: A Historical and
Legal Perspective, 17 CUMB. L. REV . 585, 674 (1987) (citing statement by Director of
the Bureau of Alcohol, Tobacco and Firearms that “[r]egistered machine gu ns which
are involved in crimes ar e so minimal so as not to be considered a law enforcement
evidence that sawed-off shotguns have utility in a militia
cont ext ). However, the trial was never held because the
defendants disappeared while the governments appeal of the
indictment dismissal was pending.
A minority line of nineteenth century arms rights
analysis—adopted in this century, for exam ple, by the Oregon
Supreme Court—goes further. This analysis protects not just
militia-type weapons, but also weapons which are useful for
personal defense, even if not useful in a military context. Thus,
the Oregon state constitution’s right to arms was held to
protect the possession of billy clubs and switchbla des—weapon s
which were pointedly excluded from protection by the civilized
warfare cases.
721
With the civilized warfare test as the constitutional
minimum, efforts to ban machine guns or ordinary guns that
look like machine guns (so-calledassault weapons”) appear
constitutionally du biou s. Th ese r ifles a re selected for
prohibition because gun control lobbies claim that the rifles are
weapons of war.
722
This claim, if t rue, a mounts t o an
admission that the r ifles lie a t the core of the Second
Amendment.
In the 1990s, once people understand thatassault
weapons” are firearms that are cosmetically threatening, but
functionally indistinguishable from other long guns, they may
be more willing to accord t hese arms a place within the right to
keep and bear arm s. Machine gun s, in contr ast, really are
functionally different. Machine guns are rarely used in crime;
and lawfully possessed machine guns, which must be registered
with the federal government, are essentially absent from the
world of gun crime.
723
Nevertheless, even many people who
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1541
pr oble m”).
724. See Kat es, The Second Amendment: A Dialogue, supra note 1, at 146-48;
Kates, Hand gun Prohibit ion , supra note 1, at 261-64. The case which supplies Kates’
rule, Sir J ohn Knights Case, 87 En g. Rep. 75, 90 En g. Rep. 330 (King ’s Ben ch 1 687 ),
created the ru le in the cont ext of carr ying unconcealed arms in public. A r ul e
designed to protect people’s sensibilities in pu blic spaces shou ld n ot be applied to t he
mere possess ion of a wea pon on p rivat e pr oper ty. In a privat e sp ace, no on e from “the
public” is at risk of being terrified. Cer tain members of the public may be personally
offended by the knowle dge th at som eon e else ma y be in pr iva te pos session of a
machine gun, just as other members of the public may be offended that someone may
be engaged in a par ticular type of sex act. The legitim ate legal objective of protecting
public areas from undu e disturbance is ent irely distinct from t he illegitimate (but all
too common) objective of satisfying the desire of certain people to eradicate the
unseen private behavior of other adults. By exten ding Sir J ohn Knights Case from
public spaces into private homes, Kates wrongly conflates two distinct legal
interests—an interest in pu blic tranqu ility (an interest which deserves respect) and
an intere st in pr iva te re pr ession (an inte rest wh ich a tolerant society may give no
legal force).
725. Stephen Halbrook, What the Framers Intended: A Linguistic Analysis of the
Second Amendm ent Right to “Bear Arms”, 49 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 151 (1986).
726. Id. at 160.
consider themselves strong Second Amendment supporters
cannot bear the thought of a constitutional right to own
machine guns.
The civilized warfare test, however , offer s n o way out of this
problem. Accordingly, some of the twentieth century Standard
Modelers propose alternat ive tests. For example, Don Kates,
relying on commentary stemming from a 1687 English case
which allowed the carrying of arms in pu blic places for
protection so long as the circumstances of the carrying were not
apt to terrify the populace, proposes a test with a prong that
excludes wea pon s which “terrify” the public.
724
Stephen Halbrook suggests that artillery pieces, tanks,
nuclear devices and other heavy ordinances are not
constitutionally protected” arms, nor are “grenades, bombs,
bazookas and other devices . . . which have never been
commonly possessed for self-defense.”
725
But the Halbrook test
sidesteps the fact that militia uses, not just personal defense
uses, are part of the core of the Second Amendment. Moreover,
the Halbrook test could allow governments to ban new types of
guns or weapons, since those weapons, being new, “have never
been commonly possessed for self-defense.”
726
Further, the test
could allow Second Amendment technology to be frozen. Such a
ban would be like the government claiming that new
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1542 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
727. See Cha rles W. Pate, Researching th e Martial .2 5 Colt Pistol, MAN AT ARMS,
Jan.-Feb. 1995, at 20-29.
728. See T. Markus Funk, Note, The Melting Point Case-in-Point, 85 J. CRIM. L.
& CRIMINOLOGY 764 (199 5).
communications devices were unprotected by the First
Amen dment simply because they have never before been
commonly used for speech.
Just as the civilized warfare test protects firearms that
many person s want excluded fr om the Second Amendment, the
test excludes firearms that many persons want to be included.
The civilized warfare cases protected large handguns, but in
some applications excluded small, highly concealable ha ndguns.
This would suggest that modern ban s on small, inexpensive
handguns might not violate the Second Amendment. On the
other hand, small handguns, such as the Colt .25 pistol, were
used by the United States military during the Second World
War.
727
Of course, anyone using this test to make such an
argument must also accept the flip side of the civilized warfare
coin:assault weapon” prohibition is plainly unconstitutional.
The nineteenth century minority theory, however, would
recognize small, relatively inexpensive handguns as highly
suitable for personal defense and accord them Second
Amendment protection regardless of their militia utility.
Twentieth century constitutional law reflects a special concern
for problems of minorities and the poor that was not present in
nineteenth century law. Since a small handgun may be the only
effective means of protection wh ich is afforda ble to a poor
person, and since the poor and minorities tend to receive
infer ior police protect ion, modern Equal Protection analysis
might find some problems with banning inexpensive guns, even
if one sets aside the Second Amendment.
728
But under the main
nineteenth century line of cases, opponents of banning small
handguns must overcome the presumption in those cases that
small handguns are not suitable militia weapons; perhaps the
frequent and successful use of small handguns in twentieth
century partisan warfare against the Nazis and other
oppressive regimes offers one potential line of argument.
Twenty-first century jurisprudence might update the
civilized warfare test by changing the focus from the military to
the police. The modern American police, especially at the
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1543
729. See DAVID B. KOPEL & PAUL H. BLACKM AN, NO MORE WACOS: WHATS WRONG
WITH FEDERAL LAW ENFORCEME NT AND HOW TO FIX IT (199 7).
730. See supra note 186 and accompanying text.
731. The states are: Alabama, Alaska, Arizona, Arkansas, Connecticut, Florida,
Georgia, Idaho, Indiana, Kentucky, Louisiana, Maine, Mississippi, Montana, Nevada,
New Hampshire, Nort h Ca rolina, Nort h Dakota, Oklah oma, Or egon, Pennsylvan ia,
South Carolina , South Dakota, Tennessee, Texas, Uta h, Verm ont, Virgin ia,
Washington, West Virginia and Wyomin g. S ee John R. Lott , Jr., Gu ns & V iolen ce:
Does Allowing Law-abiding Citizens to Carry Concealed Handguns S ave Lives?, 31
VAL. U. L. REV. 355, 357 n.9 (1997).
federal level, resemble in many regards the standing army
which so concerned the founders. While the American army is
geared towards overseas warfar e, the police are oriented
towards the type of internal order functions (e.g., su pp ression of
riots) which were among traditional militia duties. Accordingly,
the twenty-first century questionwhat are suitable militia-
type arms? might be answered,arms that are typical of, or
suitable for, police duty.”
By the modernized test, high-quality handguns (both
revolvers and semiautomatics) would lie at the core. Smaller,
less expensive handguns (frequently carried by police officers as
back-up weapons, often in ankle holsters) would also pass the
test easily. Ordinary shotguns and rifles (often carried in patrol
cars) wou ld also be pr otected. Ma chine gu ns a nd ot her weapon s
of war are not curren tly ordinary police equipment, although
they are becoming common in special attack units.
729
Fin ally, Noah Webster’s dictionary reminds us that “arms”
are not just weapon s. “Arm s” also includes defensive a rmor.
730
This suggests very serious constitutional problems with
proposals to outlaw possession of bullet-resistant body arm or by
persons outside the government.
4. Can th e carrying of w eapons be controlled?
Thirty-one states now have laws allowing ordinary citizens
to carry fir ea rms for pr otect ion.
731
Thirty of those states require
a licensing process, and some of them require training.
Vermont allows concealed carry without a license. While the
concealed carry licensing laws are supported by the National
Rifle Association (NRA), other gun rights groups, such as Gun
Owners of America (GOA), argue that requiring a license for
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1544 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
732. See Gun Owners of America, Why Adopt a Vermont-style CCW Law? (Apr.
199 7), availabl e online <htt p://cgibin1.erols.com/crfields/vtcarry.htm>.
733. 12 Ky. (2 Litt .) 90 (1822).
concealed carry is no more legitimate than requiring a license
to go to church or to buy a book.
732
The GOA position is consistent with the first gun rights
case decided in the United St ates, Bliss v. Commonwealth.
733
But the jurisprudence of the nineteenth century from then
onward is on the other side. The weight of nineteenth century
precedent would allow sever e restrictions or perhaps even a
complete prohibition on concealed carry. Consequently, a fairly
administered licensing system would pose no constitutional
problem under the main line of nineteenth century cases.
But that same line of precedent also affirms the right to
open carry, and some of that precedent suggests that even a
licensing procedure for open carry would be unconstitutional. In
the 1990s, this has u nacceptable policy implications for som e
people; the thought of seeing a person on the street (other than
a policeman) wearing a handgun in a holster m ay be dist urbing.
Thus, concealed carry laws (like la ws allowing the sale of adult
magazines and videos in adults-only stores, but bar ring the
depiction of adu lt content in storefronts or other public venues)
reflect 1990s sensibilities. As a legacy of nineteenth century
constitutional interpretation, many states, especially in the
West, have no prohibition on open carry, even though the right
to open carry is rarely exercised in urba n areas. Arizon a,
however, not only has no law against open carry, but also
allows people to exercise that right. If one looks carefully, one
can find or dinary people walking down the streets of P hoenix or
Tucson with unconcealed guns in belt holsters.
Although the issues of the legitim acy of licensing and of
concealed vs. open carry will continue to be debated, the
nineteenth century jurisprudence reminds us that the right to
carry in some form is guaranteed by the right to keep and bear
arms.
5. Repealing or ignoring the Second Am endm ent
In the twentieth century, some courts have followed the lead
of Buzzard and Salina in rein terpr et ing the Secon d
Amendment or a state analogue as guaranteeing no right at
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1545
734. S ee, e.g., United States v. Wa rin, 530 F. 2d 103 (6t h C ir. 1976);
Commonwealth v. Davis, 343 N.E.2d 847 (Ma ss. 1976).
735. See David B. Kopel et al., A T ale of T hree Cities: The R igh t to Bear Arms
in State Courts, 68 TEMPLE L. REV. 1177 (1995) (discu ssing cases in Colora do and
Oh io).
736. United St at es v. Cru iksh an k, 92 U .S. 542 , 551 (1875).
all.
734
Other courts have gone almost as far, recognizing an
individual right to ar ms, but upholding any gun law short of a
total prohibition on all guns—so long as the law passes the
rational basis test, leniently applied.
735
Brooklyn Congressman
Major Owens has introduced legislation to repeal the Second
Amendment. The nineteenth century helps us remember why
so many otherwise law-abiding gun owners will not obey the
prohibitory or near-prohibitory laws made possible by the
repeal or judicial nullification of the right to keep and bear
arms.
Cruikshank teaches us that the right to bear arms, while
guaranteed by the Constitut ion, was not created by the
Const itution. Rather, it is found wher ever civilization
exists.”
736
Thus, rega rdless of what becomes of the Second
Amendment, the right to arms will not be negated. In a 1993
article in The Public Interest, attorney Jeffrey Snyder wrote:
Those wh o call for the repeal of the Second Amendmen t so
that we ca n r eally begin controlling firearm s betray a serious
misunderstanding of the Bill of Rights. The Bill of Rights does
not gran t r igh ts to t he people, such that its repe al w ould
legitimat ely confer upon government the powers otherwise
proscribed. . . .
. . . The repeal of the Second Amendment would no more
render the outlawing of firearms legitimate than the r epea l of
the due process clause of the Fifth Amen dment would
authorize th e gover nmen t t o impr ison an d kill people at will. A
government that abrogates any of the Bill of Righ ts, wit h or
without ma joritarian approval, forever acts illegitimately,
becomes tyrannical, and loses the moral right to govern.
This is th e uncom promising understan din g reflected in t he
warning th at America’s gun owners will not go gent ly into that
good, ut opian n ight: “You can ha ve m y gu n w hen you pry it
from my cold, dead hands.” While liberals take this statement
as evid en ce of th e retrogra de, violen t n at ure of gun own er s, we
gun owners hope that liberals hold equally strong sentiments
about their print ing presses, word processors, and television
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1546 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
737. J effr ey Snyd er, A Nation of Cowards, PUB. INTEREST, Fall 1993, at 40, 54-55
(1993); cf. Nicholas J . Johnson, Beyond the S econd Am endm ent: An In divid ual R ight
to Arm s Viewed T hroug h t he N inth Am end m ent , 24 RUTGERS L.J. 1 (1992) (asserting
that traditional sou rces of Nint h Am en dmen t la w—in clud ing Anglo-Amer ican his tor y
and natural rights theory—suggest that the r ight to own a han dgun sh ould be
considered an un en um er at ed const itut ion al ri ght if th e right is not located elsewhere
in th e Cons titu tion).
738. For example, Ju dge Lacy, the only nineteenth century judge who ever had
to argue for an individual rights view from a dissenting opinion, wrote:
Can it be doubted, that if the Legislature, in moments of high political
excitement or of revolution, were to pass an act disarming the whole
popu lat ion of the State, that such an act would be ut ter ly void, not only
because it violated the spirit and ten or the Constitution, bu t because it
invaded the original rights of natura l justice?
. . . .
. . . [S]uppose th e Legislature pass an act, that a man should not keep
private arms in his own house secretly, or about his person conce aled,
although they should be in every way n ecessary, in defence of his life,
liberty, or property. Can it be doubt ed th at such an act would be a palpa ble
infr act ion of the Constitution, a s well as an invasion of the natural right s
of society?
State v. Buzza rd , 4 Ar k. 18, 36-3 8 (18 42) (L acy, J ., diss en ting ).
739. The greatest excep tion s were th e Alien & Sedition Acts (which expired
during the J efferson administr ation), the ante-bellum suppression of abolitionism in
the South (one of the abuses that eventually prompted t he Fou rt eent h Am en dm en t),
and th e Com st ock Act (allow ing crim ina l pr osecu tion for sending sexually-oriented
material through the mail).
740. See David M. Rabban, The Free Speech League, the ACLU, and Changing
Conceptions of Free Speech in Am erican History, 47 STAN . L. REV. 47, 53 (1 992 ); see
also DAVID M. RABBAN , FREE SPEECH IN ITS FORGOTTEN YEARS (199 7).
cameras. Th e republic depen ds upon ferven t d evot ion to a ll our
fundamental rights.
737
This was a radical and provocative statement in 1993, but
conven tional wisdom to virtually every nineteenth century legal
commentator and judge who wrote about the right to arms.
738
Persons who loathe the idea of firearms possession by anyone
except government employees must understand the depth and
intensity of the moral position they are setting out to destroy.
6. The First Am endm ent
During the nineteenth century, speech in America was
generally free.
739
But the assassination of President McKinley
in 1901 sparked increasingly sever e controls on core polit ical
speech—especially speech by socialists and anarchists
criticizing the government.
740
Repression grew even more severe
as a result of World War I, with almost any critic of the war at
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1547
741. See Rabban , supra note 740, at 53.
742. See Br an denb ur g v. O hio, 39 5 U.S. 444 (196 9).
743. Rabban, supra note 740, at 77.
risk for federal prosecution.
741
Not until many decades later , in
Brandenburg v. Ohio, did the Supreme Court fully defend the
core of the First Amendment, allowing speakers to denounce
the legitimacy of the central government, even to suggest that
it should be overthrown, so long as the speech did not incite
violence.
742
Perhaps one reason that it took so long for the Court and
the Amer ican pu blic to come t o this view of the First
Amendment was that the First Amendment was examined in
isolation. Had the First Amendment examination looked next
door —at the Second Amendment and its nineteenth century
interpretive tradition—the examination would almost
immediately have d iscover ed that the core of the Second
Amendment was r et aining the ability of the American people to
overthrow a tyrannical central government. If the Framers
could recognize that democratic elections, checks and balances,
and the rest of the Constitutions safeguards might one day fail,
if the Framers could contemplate the risk that the federal
government might one day break the bounds of the Const itution
and become a tyranny, and if the Framers could guarantee the
right to resist tyranny by guaranteeing the possession of ar ms
through the Second Amendment, then a fortiori, speech wh ich
merely questioned the legitimacy of the government would not
be criminal.
The leading free speech advocates of the early twentieth
century understood this point. Before there was an American
Civil Liberties Union, there was a Free Speech League, led by
Theodore Schroeder. Schroeders group was the first in
Amer ican history to defend the rights of all speakers on all
subjects, based on the principles of th e First Amendment.
Journalist H.L. Mencken wrote that Schroeder haddone more
for free expression in America than any other.”
743
Schroeder’s 1916 book Free Speech for Radicals used the
Second Amendment to bolster his argument for a strong First
Amendment:
[U]nabridged free speech means the right to advocat e treason
(or lesser crimes) so long as no overt crimina l act is induced as
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1548 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
a direct consequ en ce of it s a dvocacy. We m ust in qu ire h ow far
this conclusion is confirmed by t he con stitu tion al guarantee to
carry arms.
Aga in the obvious import is to promote a state of
preparedness for self-defense even against th e in vasion s of
government, because only governm ents have ever disarm ed
any considera ble class of people a s a means toward their
enslavement. It remains to ask h ow this view is supported by
th e h istoric con flicts pr eced ing our Amer ican Revolu tion .
Our re volu tion only extended the prin ciples of freedom of
the English revolution of 1688. At th at tim e, to p reclude the
government from going into rebellion against the people and to
ch eck its power, th e revolu tion ists pla nt ed t hemselves firm ly
upon th ese pr oposit ions: (1) The illegality of raising money for
the use of the Crown without grant of Parliament; (2) The
illega lity of the power claimed by the king to suspend laws or
the execu tion of laws ; (3) Th e illegality of a st anding army
without consent of Parliament.
Here, as in the case of Magna Charta or our American
revolutions, parchment liberties are not long respected unless
backed up by an ad equ at e public opinion and physical force. So
these restrictions like the others wer e ignored when in the
cont est for power this seemed desirable. Let us not forget that
it has always been merely a cont est for pow er ra th er th an for
principles, though the latter sometimes furn ished the pretext
behind which the lust for power was bulwark ed. Thu s it
happened that often the precedents and principles of liberty
were promoted even by tories.
In the E nglish Bill of Rights dated Feb. 13, 1688, among
the grievances char ged an d to be elim ina ted was the “keeping
a standing a rm y with in th e kingdom in tim e of pe ace wit hout
consent of parliament, which supposedly represents the
people. Another complaint wa s that of “cau sin g sever al good
subjects, being protestants, to be disarm ed and employed
contrary to law.” If we a re to er ect t his complaint against
disarming part of the people into a general principle, it must
be that in order to maintain freedom we must keep alive both
the spirit and the means of resistance to government
whenever “govern ment is in rebellion ag ainst th e people,” that
bein g a phrase of the time. This of course included the right to
advocate the timeliness and right of resistance.
The reform ers of that period were more or less consciou sly
aiming toward the destruction of government from over the
people in favor of govern men t fr om out of the people, or as
Lincoln put it, “government of, for and by the people. Those
who saw th is clearest were working towards the
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1549
744. THEODORE SCHROEDER, FREE SPEECH FOR RADICALS 103-06 (1916). British
aristocrat Joh n Cartwright was an ear ly supp orter of the Amer ican Revolution, and
an advocate of radical reform in Great Britain, including a P arliament elected by
universal suffrage. He also s er ved for seven te en yea rs as a M ajor of th e
Nottinghamshire Militia. See John Cartwright, in ENCYCLOPEDIA BRITT ANIC A (CD- ROM
ed. 1997). Thomas Jeffer son wrote to Car tw right t o prais e “your valua ble volum e on
the English Constit ution” which “deduced the Constit ut ion of th e English na tion from
its righ tful r oot, th e Anglo Saxon.” Thomas J efferson, Letter to Major John
Cartwright (Ju ne 5, 1824), available online
<htt p://www.founding.com/library/cl01/cl014/cl0144/jeff1824.htm>.
The Swiss Jean Louis de Lolme, while living in England, authored The
Constitu tion of England in 1775. Disraeli later described de Lolme as “England’s
Montesqu ieu.” MALCOLM, supra note 1, at 166. De Lolm e pr ais ed t he right of
Englishmen to be “provided with arms for their own defence.” J. L. DE LOLME, THE
CONSTITUTION OF ENGLAND 307 (London 1821) (1775). He noted that violent resis ta nce
to tyran ny “gave birth t o the Great Charter,” and placed the current English dynasty
on the t hrone. Id. at 308 . Wh ile “resis ta nce is . . . t he ultima te an d la wfu l resource
against the violences of power,” id. at 306, an armed citizenry would rarely need to
resist, according to DeLolme, for “[t]he power of the people is not when they str ike,
but when t hey keep in awe: it is when they can overthr ow every t hing, that they
never need to move.” Id. at 314. De Lolme is cited in , inter alia, Near v. M innesota,
283 U.S. 697, 713 n.4 (1931) and 2 STORY, supra note 106, § 547 n.1.
745. See SCHROEDER, supra note 744, at 105.
746. Id.
de m ocra tizat ion of the army by abolishing standing arm ies
and repla cing them by a n arm ed pop ulace defending
them selves, not being defended and repressed by th ose in
whose name th e defence is made.
Upon these precedents, others like them, and upon general
principles reformers like DeLolme and J ohn Cartwright made
it plain that the right to resist government was one protected
by t he E nglish Con st itu tion .
744
Thus, Schroeder explicated that the Second Amendment
right to arms and t he First Amendm en t freedom of speech are
firmly rooted in the history of America and England. The
governments which now rule in America and England were put
in place by people who advocated, and then carried out, the
overthrow of a tyrannical government. In order to provide long-
term security against the recurrence of tyranny, the British and
Amer ican Bills of Rights both pr ovide for the fr eedom of speech
to call for the removal of a tyranny, and the right to arms to
carry out that removal.
745
Removing tyranny is not, observed
Schroeder, any kind of illegitimate rebellion. Ra ther , tyrannical
government is in rebellion against the people.
746
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1550 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
747. See Rabban, supra note 740, at 54.
748. S ee, e.g., THE FEDERALIST NO. 45 (J am es M adison ); THE FEDERALIST N O. 85
(Alexander Hamilton). As Alexander White wrote in reply to the widely-circulated
demand for a Bill or Righ ts, as proposed by th e min ority from the Pen nsylva nia
ratifying convent ion:
There are other t hings so clearly out of the power of Congress, that the
bare recital of them is sufficient, I mean th e “right s of conscience, or
religious liber ty —th e r igh ts of bearing arms for defence, or for killing
game—the liberty of fowling, hu nting and fishing—the righ t of altering the
laws of des cen ts an d dist ribu tion of t he effect s of de ceased persons and
titles of lands and goods, and the regulation of contracts in th e individual
Sta tes.” These things seems to ha ve been inserted among their [the dissent
at the Pen nsylvania ratifying conven tion] objections, merely to induce the
ignorant to believe that Congress would have a power over such objects and
to infer from th eir being re fus ed a p lace in th e Cons titu tion, the ir [th e
federalists’] intention to exercise that power to the oppression of the people.
By the 1930s, wh en the m ajority of the Supreme Court was
ready to begin defending the First Amendment, Schroeder had
retired from the fray, and the Free Speech League had been
eclipsed by the more cautious American Civil Liberties
Union.
747
Would some of the Courts worst pro-repression
decisions perhaps have been decided differently, or on narrower
grounds, if the Court had con sidered the lessons that the
Second Amendment teaches about the First Amendment? At
the least, some scholars and some portions of the general public
might have better and more quickly understood the broad
protection that the First Amendment offers to subversive
speech—if free speech advocates had con tinued Th eodore
Schroeder’s use of the Second Am en dm ent to tea ch abou t the
First.
7. The illegality of most federal gun laws
The Bill of Rights, including the Second Amendment, was
never intended by its Framers to be the primary safeguard of
liberty. In the view of the Framer s, the m ain pr otection of
liberty was the structure of the Const itution itself. The
separation of powers would prevent the rule by fiat which
burdened most of Europe. And the legislative branch was
granted only the power to legislate on specific, enumerated
subjects (e.g., pa ten ts, bankr upt cies, interst ate commer ce).
Thus, Congress would have n o power to censor speech, to
suppress assemblies, to outlaw guns, or otherwise in fringe
rights.
748
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1551
But if th ey h ad been a dm itt ed a s rese rvat ions out of the powers granted to
Congress, it would have opened a lar ge field indeed for legal const ruction:
I know not an object of legislation which by a pa rity of reason, might not
be fairly determined within the jurisdiction of Congress.
Alexander Whit e, To the Citizens of Virginia, VA. GAZETTE, Feb. 22, 1788, repr in ted
in ORIGIN, supra note 37, at 281. As a member of the Virginia legislat ure, White
“usually voted with Madison and was on e of his ablest lieut ena nts,” taking a
particular interest in issu es of religious liber ty. F reeman H . Hart, Alexander White,
in DICT. AM. BIO., supra note 90. As Virginia prepared to debate t he proposed
Constitution, White became th e “dominan t leader” of federalists in Northwestern
Virginia, and was elected as a delegate t o the state conven tion. Id. Afterwar ds, he
was elected to th e United States House of Representatives as a member of the first
two Congresses. “He wa s regarded by his contem poraries a s th e outstandin g leader
of we st er n Vi rgi n ia a nd o n e o f t h e a bl es t la wy er s in th e U nit ed Sta t es .” Id.
749. See supra text accompanying notes 62-63, 96, 426-28.
750. See generally David B. Kopel & Glenn H. Reynolds, Taking Federalism
Seriously: Lopez and t he Part ial-Birth Abor tion Ban, 30 CONN. L. REV. 59 (1997). Of
course, many of the federal laws m ight properly be enacted as a mat ter of stat e law,
and most are.
Libera ls and conservatives in Washington who insist on using the interstate
comm er ce power t o enact legis lat ion a bout loca l mat ters (e.g., gun possess ion, use of
controversial medicines) should realize what a dangerous game they are playing. The
thirteen colonies consent ed to the power of Parliament to regulate external commer ce,
but went to war against Parliament’s attempt to control intern al comm erce. See
KENT, supra note 464 , at *2 08 n .(a ).
751. See Posting of Signs and Wr itten Notification t o Pur chasers of Handguns,
62 Fed. Reg. 45364-65 (proposed 1997) (to be codified at 27 C.F.R. pt. 178) (requiring
gun stores to post a sign, or give customers a brochure statin g, inter alia, that
Handguns are a leading contributor to juvenile violence and fatalities” and that
“Safely stori ng an d lock ing han dgu ns away from childr en can he lp ensu re comp lia nce
with Federal law”—even th ough ther e is no feder al law requ iring gun owners to lock
In the nineteenth century, St. George Tucker, William
Rawle, and Timothy Farrar made precisely this poin t: the
Second Amendment (like the First Amendment ) was in a sense
superfluous, because Congress had no power t o ban guns in the
first place.
749
But in the late twentieth century, the structural
safeguards of the body of the Constitution have been eliminated
by judicial acquies cen ce t o legislative and execu tive abu se of
power. The federal power to regulate interstate commerce
(buying and selling things across state lines) and the power to
tax have been twisted into a general police power to legislate on
almost any subject—including the power to ban the simple
possession of firea rms by va rious classes of person s.
750
Thus, the exercise of power which can be found nowhere in
the text of the Constitution has become commonplace: the
President announces that gun store owners must post or
distribute antigun statements in their stores.
751
Executive
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1552 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
handguns, or to take affirmative steps to prevent children from obtaining handguns).
752. S ee, e.g., Robert W. Ha usm an , BATF Says Wallet Holster Sale Alone May
be an NFA Violation, GUN WEEK, Mar. 1, 1998, at 3; Letter from Edward M. Owen,
Jr., Chief, Firearms Technology Branch, BA TF, to Bob Gortz, Bob Gort z Gu n S ales
(Sept. 30, 1996) (on file with a uthor) (following BATF’s determ ination th at wallet
holsters are covered by the “any other weapon” language of the NFA, BATF decided
that wallet s design ed t o car ry a con cea led ha nd gun a re now strictly controlled by the
National Firearms Act); see also Letters to the E ditor, MACHINE GUN NEWS, Ju ly 1996,
at 60 (stating that a licensed firearms dealer reported that BATF confiscated a
handgun conta in ed in a w allet holst er ).
753. See Center to Prevent Hangun Violence et al., Petition to the Federal Trade
Commission (Feb. 14, 1996) (visited Mar. 16, 1998) <ht tp://www.handgun control.org/
c-main.htm> (arguing that advertising that promotes a gun’s utility for home defense
is in he re nt ly “de ceptive”).
754. S ee, e.g., Pr int z v. U nit ed Sta tes, 52 1 U.S. 98 (1997); Un ite d St at es v. Lopez,
514 U.S. 549 (1 995 ).
branch officials in the Burea u of Alcohol, Toba cco and Firearms
(BATF ) from time to time announce that an additional type of
weapon has been subjected to near-prohibitory federal controls,
thanks to BATFs reinterpret ation of a statute or regulation.
752
The Federal Trade Commission, meanwhile, is seriously
contemplating a request that it issue an order prohibiting gun
manufacturers from mentioning self-defense in their
advertising.
753
All this is normal constitutional law in the late twentieth
century, but the nineteenth century commentators bring us
back to first principles and remind us that all this federal “law-
making about guns is not really law-making at all. It may have
the appearance of law (written down in statute books or other
official records), and t her e m ay be the for ce of compu lsion
behind the “laws,” but the Framers and the nineteenth century
had a word for the exercise of power which was never granted.
That word was not “law.” The word was “usurpation.”
Toward the end of the twentieth century, the Supreme
Court has begun to take some tentative steps towards restoring
the structural safeguards of th e main body of the
Constitution.
754
The steps are hesitant, and there is great fear
of upsetting precedent. But precedent which authorizes the
violation of the text of the Constitution deserves no respect.
Beginning in the 1930s, and with increasing confidence in
subsequent decades, the Supreme Court began to abandon
precedent from the 1900s, 1910s, and 1920s which had
constricted the First Amendment. The Court moved forward by
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1359] SECOND AMENDMENT IN THE 19TH CENTURY1553
returning to the original First Amendment analysis, a s
articulated by, among others, St. George Tucker. Perhaps in the
twenty-first century, the Court will continue to restore the
structure of the Constitution, so that the invocation of the First,
Second, or other Amendments will become less necessary, as
the federal sph er e of a ction shrinks to constitutional
boundaries.
VIII. CONCLUSION
The historical record shows that, while the boundaries of
the Second Amendment were the subject of vigorous discussion
during the nineteenth century, the core mea ning of the
Amendment was well-settled: the Standard Model of the late
twentieth century sch olars was t he Standa rd Model of the
nineteenth century. For all practical purposes, it was the only
model. Every known scholarly commentator who said anything
about the Second Amendment, all six Supreme Court cases, and
every judge except for one in Arkansas treated the Second
Amendment as an individual right. These Standard Model
sources—like their twentiet h cen tury successors—disagreed
about important features of the Second Amendment, including
its application to the states and the types of arms whose
possession is protected. Some analysts treated the Amendment
in desultory fashion, while others celebrated it. Some cases and
commentators saw the right as intended solely to allow
resistance to oppressive government, while others saw the right
as also encompassing defense against individual criminals, and
not just criminal governments. But ther e is agreement on one
fundament al: the Secon d Am endm en t recogn izes a righ t of
individual Americans to own guns and edged weapons suitable
for resisting tyra nny, and protects that right from infringement
by the federal governmen t. However confusing the Second
Amendment may have become to Americans in the twentieth
century, the core of the Amendments meaning was readily
apparent in the nineteenth centur y.
In the late twentieth century, scholars are perfectly free to
argue against the Standard Model of the Second Amendment on
the basis of changed circumstances. For example, Donald
Beschle reasons that the Second Amendment should be
reconstrued into a right of personal security, and that right can
D:\ 1998-4\ FINAL\KOP-FIN.WPD Jan. 8, 2001
1554 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [1998
755. See Donald Besch le, Recons iderin g th e S econd Amendment Constitutional
Protection for a Right of Security, 9 HAMLINE L. REV . 69 (1986 ).
756. Madison, J effers on, Ada ms, and ma ny oth er Founders would appear to have
been complicit in t he fra ud, sin ce they were alive and active in public affairs when
Tucker and Rawle publish ed th eir well-kn own books. Th is frau d th eory is no less
preposterous than Garry Wills’ the ory th at th e Se cond Amendme nt is a hoa x
perpetrated by J ames Ma dison. See generally Wills, supra note 5.
be protected by banning all guns.
755
Several schools of
constitutional interpretation suggest that the established
interpretive history of constitutional provisions may be ignored
if the history impedes the achievement of desirable
governmental policies. Perhaps one could argue that the
nineteenth century wa s t he victim of a massive fraud
(apparently perpetrated by St. George Tucker and William
Rawle) wh ich fooled everyone fr om Justice Story onward about
the meaning of the Second Amendment.
756
Even within the
limits of a nineteenth century interpretive paradigm, there is
much useful precedent for advocates of restrictions on various
types of concealable wea pon s, and for pr ohibitions on the
carrying of concealed weapon s.
But it can no longer be argued—at lea st not by a nyone
constrained by respect for the truth—that the Second
Amendment has never been considered an individual right. The
anti-individual view of the Second Amendment was, at most, a
very lonely voice against an overwhelming nineteenth century
individual rights consensus. In light of the nineteenth century
record, no twentieth or twenty-first century scholars should
claim that the St anda rd Model individual rights view is a fraud
or a myth.